Electoral agency in the lab Leif Helland & Lars Monkerud NSM BI.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
An Introduction to Game Theory Part V: Extensive Games with Perfect Information Bernhard Nebel.
Advertisements

The Basics of Game Theory
Introduction to Game Theory
Oligopoly.
Nash’s Theorem Theorem (Nash, 1951): Every finite game (finite number of players, finite number of pure strategies) has at least one mixed-strategy Nash.
ECON 100 Tutorial: Week 9 office: LUMS C85.
Non myopic strategy Truth or Lie?. Scoring Rules One important feature of market scoring rules is that they are myopic strategy proof. That means that.
Lecture #11: Introduction to the New Empirical Industrial Organization (NEIO) - What is the old empirical IO? The old empirical IO refers to studies that.
3. Basic Topics in Game Theory. Strategic Behavior in Business and Econ Outline 3.1 What is a Game ? The elements of a Game The Rules of the.
Copyright©2004 South-Western 16 Oligopoly. Copyright © 2004 South-Western BETWEEN MONOPOLY AND PERFECT COMPETITION Imperfect competition refers to those.
1 Public choice Alexander W. Cappelen Econ
Evolution and Repeated Games D. Fudenberg (Harvard) E. Maskin (IAS, Princeton)
© 2015 McGraw-Hill Education. All rights reserved. Chapter 15 Game Theory.
Game Theory Eduardo Costa. Contents What is game theory? Representation of games Types of games Applications of game theory Interesting Examples.
Regression Extensions W&W Chapter 14. Introduction So far we have assumed that our independent variables are measured intervally. Today we will discuss.
This paper reports an experimental study based on the popular Chinos game, in which three players, arranged in sequence, have to guess the total number.
Rational Expectations and the Aggregation of Diverse Information in Laboratory Security Markets Charles R. Plott, Shyam Sunder.
Fundamentals of Political Science Dr. Sujian Guo Professor of Political Science San Francisco State Unversity
Adverse Selection Asymmetric information is feature of many markets
EC102: Class 9 Christina Ammon.
A camper awakens to the growl of a hungry bear and sees his friend putting on a pair of running shoes, “You can’t outrun a bear,” scoffs the camper. His.
Oligopoly The challenge of analyzing interdependent strategic decisions.
Objectives © Pearson Education, 2005 Oligopoly LUBS1940: Topic 7.
1 Teck H. Ho April 8, 2004 Outline  In-Class Experiment and Motivation  Adaptive Experience-Weighted Attraction (EWA) Learning in Games: Camerer and.
Monopolistic Competition
Aging and the Welfare State: A Political Economy Model Assaf Razin, Efraim Sadka and Edith Sand October 2005.
Cal State Northridge  320 Ainsworth Sampling Distributions and Hypothesis Testing.
Job Market Signaling (Spence model)
C h a p t e r o n e Economics: Foundations and Models.
1 Democracy and Data Dissemination: The Effect of Political Regime on Transparency B. Peter Rosendorff, NYU James R. Vreeland, Yale IPES, Princeton, November.
Chapter Fourteen Strategy. © 2007 Pearson Addison-Wesley. All rights reserved.14–2 Strategic Behavior A set of actions a firm takes to increase its profit,
Games in the normal form- An application: “An Economic Theory of Democracy” Carl Henrik Knutsen 5/
Two-Stage Games APEC 8205: Applied Game Theory Fall 2007.
A Dynamic Level-k Model in Games Teck Ho and Xuanming Su UC Berkeley April 2011 Teck Hua Ho 1.
Electoral agency in the lab: preliminary findings Leif Helland Lars Monkerud Rune Sørensen.
Games of Incomplete Information. These games drop the assumption that players know each other’s preferences. Complete info: players know each other’s preferences.
Investor Contagion: A Network Model for Asset Markets James Luo ELE 381 Mini-project Presentation.
Introduction to Game Theory and Strategic Interactions.
Efficient Capital Markets Objectives: What is meant by the concept that capital markets are efficient? Why should capital markets be efficient? What are.
Brian Duddy.  Two players, X and Y, are playing a card game- goal is to find optimal strategy for X  X has red ace (A), black ace (A), and red two (2)
Chapter 9 Games with Imperfect Information Bayesian Games.
The paired sample experiment The paired t test. Frequently one is interested in comparing the effects of two treatments (drugs, etc…) on a response variable.
Monopoly with Incomplete Information Eric Maskin and John Riley The RAND Journal of Economics, Vol. 15, No. 2 (Summer, 1984), pp Presented by:
Auction Seminar Optimal Mechanism Presentation by: Alon Resler Supervised by: Amos Fiat.
ECO290E: Game Theory Lecture 12 Static Games of Incomplete Information.
Economics: Principles and Applications, 2e by Robert E. Hall & Marc Lieberman.
1 Chapter 11 Oligopoly. 2 Define market structures Number of sellers Product differentiation Barrier to entry.
Inferential Statistics 2 Maarten Buis January 11, 2006.
Nash equilibrium Nash equilibrium is defined in terms of strategies, not payoffs Every player is best responding simultaneously (everyone optimizes) This.
Lecture 2 Economic Actors and Organizations: Motivation and Behavior.
Dynamic Games & The Extensive Form
10.1 DAY 2: Confidence Intervals – The Basics. How Confidence Intervals Behave We select the confidence interval, and the margin of error follows… We.
Perfect competition, with an infinite number of firms, and monopoly, with a single firm, are polar opposites. Monopolistic competition and oligopoly.
Parallel Trade and the Pricing of Pharmaceutical Products Frank Müller-Langer Conference on „Health Economics and the Pharmaceutical Industry“
Diversification of Parameter Uncertainty Eric R. Ulm Georgia State University.
CHAPTER 15: Tests of Significance The Basics ESSENTIAL STATISTICS Second Edition David S. Moore, William I. Notz, and Michael A. Fligner Lecture Presentation.
 The point estimators of population parameters ( and in our case) are random variables and they follow a normal distribution. Their expected values are.
Auctions serve the dual purpose of eliciting preferences and allocating resources between competing uses. A less fundamental but more practical reason.
Testing theories of fairness— Intentions matter Armin Falk, Ernst Fehr, Urs Fischbacher February 26, 2015.
Auctions serve the dual purpose of eliciting preferences and allocating resources between competing uses. A less fundamental but more practical reason.
1 Optimizing Decisions over the Long-term in the Presence of Uncertain Response Edward Kambour.
EC941 - Game Theory Prof. Francesco Squintani Lecture 6 1.
Pricing of Competing Products BI Solutions December
Econ 805 Advanced Micro Theory 1 Dan Quint Fall 2009 Lecture 1 A Quick Review of Game Theory and, in particular, Bayesian Games.
Principles of Management
Monopolistic Competition & Oligopoly. Unit Objectives Describe the characteristics of monopolistic competition and oligopoly Discover how monopolistic.
Monopolistic Competition & Oligopoly
Monopolistic Competition And Oligopoly
Market Failure: Oligopolies
Presentation transcript:

Electoral agency in the lab Leif Helland & Lars Monkerud NSM BI

Motivation Liberal concept of democracy Roots in liberal political philosophy (Mill, Locke) Democracy negatively defined: citizens should be free from restraint and exploitation by state power: a) constitutional constraints, b) accountable leadership Accountability: achieved by retrospective voting for competing alternatives (Schumpeter 1942; Popper 1982, Riker 1984). A contemporary economists formulation (Myerson 1999): “When elected leaders use political power for their own profit, we call it corruption or abuse of power, or in its most extreme form, tyranny. One of the basic motivations of democracy is the hope that electoral competition should reduce such political abuse of power, below what would occur under an authoritarian system, just as market competition reduces oligopolistic profits below monopoly levels” What we want is: 1.An explicit model of electoral agency: a) based on parsimonious motivational assumptions, b) allowing for moral hazard on behalf of elected representatives, and c) allowing voters to select representatives through elections (Austen-Smith & Banks 1989, Banks & Sundaram 1993, Besley 2006) 2.Data on how real voters behave in situations resembling such a model.

Model (1) Two stages t=(1,2) with an election in between. Incumbents are of two possible types i  {g,b}. Let  {s,1} signify a productivity parameter with 0<s<  <1, where  is a discount factor. At the beginning of t=1 random draws determine the type of the first stage incumbent and the nature of the productivity shock for both stages, with commonly known probabilities Pr(i=g)=  and Pr(  =s)=q. Type and productivity is private information to the incumbent. Let q > ½ by assumption. The t=1 incumbent selects public production for t=1, and production is publicly announced. There is an election at the end of t=1. If the challenger wins, challenger type is randomly determined at the beginning of t=2, with commonly known probability Pr(i=g)= . If the challenger looses, the t=1 incumbent continues as incumbent in t=2. The t=2 incumbent selects public production for t=2. Production is publicly announced, payoffs are distributed and the game ends.

Model (2) Let payoff to an incumbent of type b be V b =r 1 +  r 2, where r t is rents (diversion of public funds for private ends) in stage t Let the type g incumbent set r t =0 for t=(1,2) Let voter payoff be U t =(1-  )y+  x t, where  is the tax rate, y is income before tax, x t is public production in stage t, and  >1 Let the budget restriction of the incumbent be  (  y-r t )=x t. Finally, let maximal rents equal r t =  y. It follows readily that a b-type incumbent always extracts maximal rents in t=2. Note also that r 1 =  y dominates r 1 =0 for a b-type incumbent Rent taking in t=1ReelectedNot reelected r 1 =0  y 0 r 1 =  y (1+  )  y yy

Model (3) It may still be in the interest of a b-type incumbent to mimic a g-type incumbent (by setting 0<r 1 <  y) in order to be reelected (and take r 2 =  y) The central question becomes: what is the rationally updated voter belief after observing production x 1 =s  y? Let 0< <1 be the probability that a b-type incumbent facing  =1 mimics a g-type incumbent facing  =s Bayes rule now provides an answer : Now, assuming voters use pure cutoff strategies; in which they reelect only if  > , we appreciate that as long as q > ½ all incumbents that produces either x 1 =s  y or x 1 =  y will be reelected unanimously while no incumbent that produces x 1 =0 will get any votes. As long as  >s mimicking is profitable for a b-type incumbent.

Design (1) q=.55 or q=.85,  =.20  =.23 (Marginal update) or  =.59 (Substantial update) Endowment per stage 100;  =1.1;  =0.5, s=0.5 Does update have an effect on behavior? Does group learning have an effect on behavior? Do subjects learn over time? How?

Design (2) To root out social distributive preferences and intentions –Electorates matched in absolute stranger protocol –Politician programmed as an automaton

Non-parametric tests (1) Games 1-7 (2 tailed MW-tests) Update effect (at P=25) Decisive voters 0.17 (p=0.09) Voters in electorates 0.14 (p=0.24 ) Group effect (at P=25) Marginal update 0.12 (p=0.26) Substantial update 0.15 (p=0.17)

Non parametric tests (2) Games 1-5 & (2 tailed MW tests) Update effect 5 first games 0.24 (p=0.06) 5 last games 0.26 (p=0.01) Learning effect Marginal update 0.08 (p=0.46 ) Substantial update 0.14 (p=0.23)

Non-parametric tests (3) Average mistakes (decisions): Absolute deviations of registered beliefs from equilibrium beliefs

Non-rational learning rules We look at two variants; fictitious play and payoff reinforcement learning Fictitious play variable: Dummy that takes value 1 if fictitious beliefs favor equilibrium behavior and zero otherwise. Uses all games; also test games Payoff reinforcement: Continuous variable between zero and one that captures reinforcement (of previous payoff experiences) towards equilibrium behavior (Roth & Erev 1995). Estimated from the first two games with earnings What is reinforced is actions given states Strength of attractions is set at 55 (the order of maximal payoffs)

Regression results Update has a significantly positive effect on probability of being in equilibrium (at P1=25) with no control for non-rational learning Controlling for non- rational learning, this effect is halved; and becomes far from significant Reinforcement has a strong, positive and highly significant effect Fictitious play does not have significant effects

Simulations (1) Substantial update A player facing a sequence of independent games Results are averaged over sequences Parameters; initial attractions; and strength of attractions as in experiment

Simulations (2) Marginal update A player facing a sequence of independent games Results are averaged over sequences Parameters; initial attractions; and strength of attractions as in experiment

Conclusions "...the typical citizen drops down to a lower level of mental performance as soon as he enters the political field. He argues and analyzes in a way which he would readily recognize as infantile within the sphere of his real interests. He becomes primitive again. His thinking is associative and affective... [This] may prove fatal to the nation.“ (Schumpeter 1942:262) Design: Control for “affective thinking” (distributive social preferences and intentions) Results: Thinking is “associative”, almost Pavlovian Under favorable conditions, this does not matter for “the fate of the Nation” (payoff reinforcement looks as if players were playing an equilibrium) Under less favorable conditions, it matters for “the fate of the Nation” (payoff reinforcement does is not conducive to optimal discipline and selection) Creates a challenge for field data studies that find a pattern consistent with equilibrium: It need not imply that data were generated by a bayesian perfect equilibrium