An Overview of the Use of Argumentation Schemes in Case Modeling ICAIL 2009 June 8. Douglas Walton (CRRAR) University of Windsor.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Visualization Tools, Argumentation Schemes and Expert Opinion Evidence in Law Douglas Walton University of Winnipeg, Canada Thomas F. Gordon Fraunhofer.
Advertisements

On the structure of arguments, and what it means for dialogue Henry Prakken COMMA-08 Toulouse,
The Liar and Dialetheism The Liar, the Strengthened Liar Dialetheism: Motivations and Problems Keith Allen Office Hour: Weds (D/140)
By Vikash kumar, Yashvardhan Singh & group 1 ST YEAR (B.B.A LLb.)
Legal Argumentation 2 Henry Prakken March 28, 2013.
Teaching American History: Moot Courts and Constitutional Concepts.
Explanations and Arguments Based on Practical Reasoning ExaCt 2009 July 12 Pasadena Douglas Walton (CRRAR) University of Windsor.
HUME ON THE ARGUMENT FROM DESIGN (Part 2 of 2) Text source: Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion, parts 2-8.
Identifying and Analyzing Arguments in a Text Argumentation in (Con)Text Symposium, Jan. 4, 2007, Bergen.
BIRDS FLY. is a bird Birds fly Tweety is a bird Tweety flies DEFEASIBLE NON-MONOTONIC PRESUMPTIVE?
Theory and Practice in AI and Law: A Response to Branting Katie Atkinson and Trevor Bench-Capon Department of Computer Science The University of Liverpool.
Elements and Methods of Argumentation Theory University of Padua Lecture Padua, Italy, Dec.1, Douglas Walton Assumption University Chair in Argumentation.
Conductive Arguments in Ethical Deliberation Douglas Walton: University of Windsor Assumption Chair in Argumentation Studies Distinguished Research Fellow.
Critical Thinking Rubrics David Hunter, Ph.D. Associate Professor, Chair Philosophy and Humanities Buffalo State College, SUNY November 4, 2005.
Argumentation in Artificial Intelligence Henry Prakken Lissabon, Portugal December 11, 2009.
Establishing Foreign Law Source: Gerhard Dannemann: Establishing Foreign Law in a German Court, German Law Archive,
FINDING THE LOGIC OF ARGUMENTATION Douglas Walton CRRAR Coimbra, March 24, 2011.
Leadership Institute Branch Legal Training Section Search & Seizure Plain View Roll Call Training
Lincoln-Douglas Debate An Examination of Values. OBJECTIVES: The student will 1. Demonstrate understanding of the concepts that underlie Lincoln-Douglas.
1 Law is a system of known rules applied by a judge is a pretence long under attack. In an important sense legal rules are never clear, if it had to be.
4.5 THE EFFECT OF STATUTORY INTERPRETATION KEY CONCEPT Judges will often be required to interpret a statute in the process of arriving at a decision in.
The Supreme Court at Work
Logic and Legal Reasoning iew/article/view/117 (Click on “Full Text PDF”)
+ Protecting Individual Liberties Section 1 Chapter 14.
THE ROLE OF THE FEDERAL COURTS Introduction to the Judicial Branch of the United States Government.
Chapter 2 The criminal investigation process. In this chapter, you will look at the role of police and the courts in the criminal investigation process.
Legal Reasoning and Argumentation Douglas Walton University of Windsor CRRAR McMaster University October 8, 2012.
English II Chapter 13: Argument & Persuasion © Jeffrey Markowitz/CORBIS. All Rights Reserved.
MODELING CRITICAL QUESTIONS AS ADDITIONAL PREMISES Douglas Walton CRRAR OSSA, May 19, 2011.
Debate: Reasoning. Claims & Evidence Review Claims are statements that serve to support your conclusion. Evidence is information discovered through.
Argument Visualization Tools for Corroborative Evidence 2 nd International Conference on Evidence Law and Forensic Science (ICELFS 2009) Beijing, China,
PROCEDURES IN THE JUSTICE SYSTEM, 8 th ed. Roberson, Wallace, and Stuckey PRENTICE HALL ©2007 Pearson Education, Inc. Upper Saddle River, NJ
THE TRIAL IN CANADIAN COURTS – Part 3 RULES AND TYPES OF EVIDENCE LAW 12 MUNDY
Chapter 2 Legal Aspects of Investigation © 2009 McGraw-Hill Higher Education. All rights reserved. LEARNING OBJECTIVES Explain the historical evolution.
Search Incident to Arrest MNPD Training Academy Recruit Session 42 David Veile.
Logic. What is logic? Logic (from the Ancient Greek: λογική, logike) is the use and study of valid reasoning. The study of logic features most prominently.
Plain View Doctrine  Allows a police officer to seize evidence found in “plain view” during a search without a warrant. Also, when officers are carrying.
 What is the exclusionary rule  Explain stop and frisk  What is the plain view doctrine  What did Miranda v Arizona require police to do  What happens.
Kentucky Animal Care & Control Association 2014 Annual Training Conference Mock Trial.
CAN POLICE SEARCH A PERSON’S PHONE WITHOUT A WARRANT? Precedent Setting Charter Case.
Critical Thinking. Critical thinkers use reasons to back up their claims. What is a claim? ◦ A claim is a statement that is either true or false. It must.
{ Methods of Persuasion Speech class.  The audience perceives the speaker as having high credibility  The audience is won over by the speaker’s evidence.
Common Terms in AP Essay Prompts Since this is a college course, you are going to see many terms (in addition to vocab) that you might not know. Sometimes.
4 th Amendment: Search and Seizure. The Fourth Amendment to the U.S. Constitution protects personal privacy, and every citizen's right to be free from.
Debate Ch. 18 Group One.
The Investigation.  Right to remain silent  Right to an attorney  No interrogation should take place before they read  Are a result of the US Supreme.
Legal Studies * Mr. Marinello ARRESTS AND WARRANTS.
American Law and Legal Research Class One May 11, 2011 Jennifer Allison, Research Services Librarian Pepperdine Law School Library © 2011 Jennifer Allison.
Fourth Amendment And Probable Cause. By the end of this presentation you should be able to understand; ◦Fourth Amendment of the U.S. Constitution ◦How.
An answer is given on the slide following each question. Module 1: Check Your Understanding.
1 Book Cover Here Copyright © 2013, Elsevier Inc. All Rights Reserved Chapter 7 Search Incident to a Lawful Arrest, Hot Pursuit Criminal Justice Procedure.
Criminal Investigation: Laws of Arrest, Search and Seizure Chapter 12 Law and Government.
Criminal Procedure Practice Exam 11:30 am – 12:30 pm: Practice Exam 12:30 pm – 1:00 pm: Review DO NOT OPEN YOUR EXAM BOOKLET UNTIL INSTRUCTED TO DO SO.
Comparing the Inquisitorial and Adversarial Systems.
1 Book Cover Here Copyright © 2013, Elsevier Inc. All Rights Reserved Chapter 6 Exceptions to the Warrant Requirement: Plain View, Open Fields, Abandoned.
Unit 3 The Fourth Amendment. The Fourth Amendment To The United States Constitution The right of the people to be secure in their persons, houses, papers,
1 Book Cover Here Copyright © 2013, Elsevier Inc. All Rights Reserved Chapter 3 Arrests Criminal Justice Procedure 8 th Edition.
Recognizing the Client
Weapon of Legal Instruction
Chapter 5 Legal Issues in Criminal Investigation.
Chapter 2 The criminal investigation process
The Literature Review 3 edition
Analogizing and Distinguishing Cases
The Courts and the Constitution
Inductive and Deductive Logic
Argumentation Strategies
On Arguments from Testimony
Criminal Procedure: Theory and Practice, 2d.
Bell Work (Think of your response and be prepared to share)
THE TRIAL IN CANADIAN COURTS – Part 3
Presentation transcript:

An Overview of the Use of Argumentation Schemes in Case Modeling ICAIL 2009 June 8. Douglas Walton (CRRAR) University of Windsor

Argument from Analogy v1 315 Similarity Premise: Generally, case C1 is similar to case C2. Base Premise: A is true (false) in case C1. Conclusion: A is true (false) in case C2. Critical Questions CQ1: Are there differences between C1 and C2 that would tend to undermine the force of the similarity cited? CQ2: Is A true (false) in C1? CQ3: Is there some other case C3 that is also similar to C1, but in which A is false (true)?

Relevance and Factors This apple is red and tastes good. This ball is red. Therefore this ball will taste good. The observed similarity is not relevant to the further similarity that is in question (Weinreb, 2005, 32). Ashley (2006, 41) relevance is on- pointedness (sharing factors).

Argument from Analogy v2 58 Similarity Premise: Generally, case C1 is similar to case C2. Base Premise: A is true (false) in case C1. Relevant Similarity Premise: The similarity between C1 and C2 observed so far is relevant to the further similarity that is in question. Conclusion: A is true (false) in case C2.

Argument from Verbal Classification 319 Individual Premise: a has property F. Classification Premise: For all x, if x has property F, then x can be classified as having property G. Conclusion: a has property G. Critical Questions CQ1: What evidence is there that a definitely has property F, as opposed to evidence indicating room for doubt on whether it should be so classified? CQ2: Is the verbal classification in the classification premise based merely on an assumption about word usage that is subject to doubt?

Example of Drug-Sniffing Dog The example of the drug-sniffing dog (Brewer, 1996) shows how an argument that has been classified in the law literature as argument from analogy is really an instance of arguing from analogy to a verbal classification. If a trained dog sniffs luggage left in a public place and signals to the police that it contains drugs, should this event be classified as a search according to the Fourth Amendment? If it can be classified as a search, information obtained as a result of the dog sniffing the luggage is not admissible as evidence.

Argument from Precedent 343 Major Premise: Generally, according to the established rule, if x has property F, then x also has property G. Minor Premise: In this legitimate case, a has F but does not have G. Conclusion: Therefore an exception to the rule must be recognized, and the rule appropriately modified or qualified. Critical Questions CQ1: Does the established rule really apply to this case? CQ2: Is the case cited legitimate, or can it be explained as only an apparent violation of the rule? CQ3: Can the case cited be dealt with under an already recognized category of exception that does not require a change in the rule?

Wyner & Bench-Capon (2207) The tool for CBR they devised is a set of six argument structures they describe as argumentation schemes. For example (143) their main scheme (AS1), looks like this, where P is the plaintiff, D the defendant, Pi are the factors, CC is the current case and PC is the precedent case. P Factors Premise: P1 are reasons or P. D Factors Premise: P2 are reasons for D. Factors Preference Premise: P1 was preferred to P2 in PCi. CC Weaker Exception: The priority in PCi does not decide CC. Conclusion: Decide CC for P. These six schemes look like factor-based species of argument from precedent.

Argument from an Established Rule 343 Major Premise: If carrying out types of actions including the state of affairs A is the established rule for x, then (unless the case is an exception), x must carry out A. Minor Premise: Carrying out types of actions including state of affairs A is the established rule for a. Conclusion: Therefore a must carry out A. Critical Questions CQ1: Does the rule require carrying out types of actions that include A as an instance? CQ2: Are there other established rules that might conflict with, or override this one? CQ3: Is this case an exceptional one, that is, could there be extenuating circumstances or an excuse for noncompliance?

Scheme for Argument from Rules Premise 1: R is a legal rule with antecedents A1, …, An and conclusion C. Premise 2: Each Ai in A1,..., An is presumably true. Conclusion: C is presumably true. Critical Questions Does some exception to R apply? Is some assumption of R not met? Is R a valid legal rule? Does some rule excluding R apply in this case? Does some conflicting rule of higher priority than R apply in this case?

Applying Schemes to Cases We now have a group of schemes, comprising argument from analogy, argument from classification, argument from definition to classification, argument from precedent, and argument from an established rule. Now let’s briefly discuss some problems with attempting to apply these schemes to typical instances of legal case-based reasoning

Open-Textured Terms in Law In Hart’s famous example of deciding whether a skateboard is a vehicle that ought to be banned from the park is a case in point (Hart, 1949; 1961; Loui, 1995), it looks like all we have to do is to define the concept of vehicle. It is not possible to give a legal definition, certainly in hard cases, that provides sufficient support by itself to arrive at a decision. The reason, of course, is that legal concepts like vehicle are open-textured, to use Hart’s term, or defeasible, to use the current term.

How Law Solves the Problem What law does is to articulate rules or principles that are sometimes established by the courts based on (1) previous cases, and (2) in other instances may even be based on commonly accepted practices that have found their way into law is supporting the formulation of such rules. A set of such rules can provide necessary or sufficient conditions that function as partial definitions. These rules help the argumentation to move forward even in the absence of a fixed definition that is complete and that can be mechanically applied to hard cases.

Example of Prior Legal Rules Weinreb (2005, p. 24) cited three general rules established by prior court decisions that can be applied to Brewer’s case of the drug-sniffing dog. Rule 1: If a police officer sees something in plain view in a public place, the information collected is not classified as a search. Rule 2: If a police officer opens luggage and then observes something inside the luggage, the information collected is classified as a search Rule 3: If a police officer listens surreptitiously to a conversation in a private place, it is classified as a search.

More General Rule There is also a more general rule that Brewer called an analogy warranting rule (AWR) formulated by Weinreb (2005, p. 24) as follows. AWR: If a police officer obtains information about a person or thing in a public place without intrusion on the person or taking possession of or interfering with the use of the thing, it is not a search for purposes of the Fourth Amendment.

Accepted Rules of First Possession of Baseballs Gray (2002, 6) formulated six important rules about the understanding of first possession of baseballs excepted by fence and other participants in the sport of baseball. Two of these rules can be used to illustrate how each rule acts as a partial of definition of the notion of a catch. One is the negative rule that a catch does not occur simply because the ball hits the fan on the hands or enters the pocket or webbing of the fan’s baseball glove. Another is the positive rule stating that a catch does occur when the fan has the ball in his hand or glove, the ball remains there after its momentum has ceased, and even remains there after the fan makes incidental contact with a railing, wall, the ground or other fans who are attempting to catch the baseball or get out of the way.

Rules of Practice from Whaling Gray (2002) showed how an excellent example of this kind of judicial decision making can be found in rulings on whaling. It was found in Anglo-American cases where the ownership of the whale carcass was contested that judges deferred to commonly accepted principles used by the whalers themselves. These principles or rules in effect offered partial definitions of what it is to possess a wild animal. Different kinds of rules depended on different kinds of whales and the circumstances under which they were caught, like the depth of water and how fast a type of whale can swim.

Argument from Popular Practice 314 Major Premise: A is a popular practice among those who are familiar with what is acceptable or not in regard to A. Minor Premise: If A is a popular practice among those familiar with what is acceptable or not with regard to A, that gives a reason to think that A is acceptable. Conclusion: Therefore, A is acceptable in this case Critical Questions CQ1: What actions or other indications show that a large majority accepts A? CQ2: Even if large majority accepts A as true, what grounds might here be there for thinking they are justified in accepting A?

Defeasible Definitions From cases like this we can see that law is not in a position to offer complete definitions of fundamental concepts like search and possession that offer jointly necessary and sufficient conditions that can be applied to any new case to solve the problem and make a ruling. So-called essential definitions are not available, but this absence should not be too surprising given from what we already know from Hart about the open-textured nature of legal concepts. Defeasible (tentative) definitions that make classifications are possible.

How Does of Applying Schemes to Cases Work? The process uses general rules derived from legally authoritative sources by statutory interpretation. It uses arguments from analogy to previous decided cases. Argument from precedent is based on argument from analogy. It uses argument from established rule from these sources. In some instances, it uses argument from generally accepted practices in specific kinds of practical activity domains. It uses and arrives at classifications based on these rules. Instead of fixed definitions, it uses defeasible partial definitions in the form of necessary and sufficient condition rules. It applies these rules to the problematic case that needs to be decided by examining and weighing the arguments pro and contra based on the evidence from these and other sources.

References Kevin Ashley, ‘Case-Based Reasoning’, Information Technology and Lawyers, ed. Arno R. Lodder and Anja Oskamp, Berlin, Springer, 2006, Brian E. Gray, ‘Reported and Recommendations on the Law of Capture and First Possession: Popov v. Hayashi’, Superior of the State of California for the City and County of San Francisco, Case no , November 6, Available May 24, 2009 at: H. L. A. Hart, ‘The Ascription of Responsibility and Rights’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 49, 1949, Reprinted in Logic and Language, ed. A. Flew, Oxford, Blackwell, 1951, H. L. A. Hart, The Concept of Law, Oxford, Oxford University Press, Ronald P. Loui, ‘Hart’s Critics on Defeasible Concepts and Ascriptivism’, Proceedings of the Fifth International Conference on Artificial Intelligence and Law, New York, ACM Press, 1995, Available at: Douglas Walton, Chris Reed and Fabrizio Macagno, Argumentation Schemes, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, Lloyd L. Weinreb, Legal Reason: The Use of Analogy in Legal Argument, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2005.