Uncertainty RUD, June 28, 2006, Peter P. Wakker Paper: Chapter for New Palgrave. Its didactical beginning is not optimal for this specialized audience.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Introduction à la théorie de la décision
Advertisements

Economics of Information (ECON3016)
Decisions under Uncertainty
1 EC9A4 Social Choice and Voting Lecture 3 EC9A4 Social Choice and Voting Lecture 3 Prof. Francesco Squintani
Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved.
1 12. Principles of Parameter Estimation The purpose of this lecture is to illustrate the usefulness of the various concepts introduced and studied in.
Rational choice: An introduction Political game theory reading group 3/ Carl Henrik Knutsen.
EC941 - Game Theory Prof. Francesco Squintani Lecture 8 1.
Behavioral Finance Uncertain Choices February 18, 2014 Behavioral Finance Economics 437.
Judgment and Decision Making in Information Systems Utility Functions, Utility Elicitation, and Risk Attitudes Yuval Shahar, M.D., Ph.D.
Lecture 4 on Individual Optimization Risk Aversion
Economics D10-1: Lecture 4 Classical Demand Theory: Preference-based approach to consumer behavior (MWG 3)
Using Prospect Theory to Study Unknown Probabilities ("Ambiguity") by Peter P. Wakker, Econ. Dept., Erasmus Univ. Rotterdam (joint with Mohammed Abdellaoui.
Making Rank-Dependent Utility Tractable for the Study of Ambiguity Peter P. Wakker, June 16, 2005 MSE, Université de Paris I Aim:Make rank-dependent utility.
No Free Lunch (NFL) Theorem Many slides are based on a presentation of Y.C. Ho Presentation by Kristian Nolde.
Combining Bayesian Beliefs and Willingness to Bet to Analyze Attitudes towards Uncertainty by Peter P. Wakker, Econ. Dept., Erasmus Univ. Rotterdam (joint.
Adapting de Finetti's Proper Scoring Rules for Measuring Subjective Beliefs to Modern Decision Theories of Ambiguity Gijs van de Kuilen, Theo Offerman,
Stochastic Dominance Michael H. Birnbaum Decision Research Center California State University, Fullerton.
Making Choquet Expected Utility Tractable for the Study of Ambiguity Peter P. Wakker, December 20, 2005 Tel-Aviv University Aim:Make Choquet-expected utility,
PSY 307 – Statistics for the Behavioral Sciences
PSY 5018H: Math Models Hum Behavior, Prof. Paul Schrater, Spring 2005 Rational Decision Making.
A new tool is presented for measuring beliefs/likelihoods under uncertainty. It will simplify:  preference axiomatizations;  quantitative measurements;
Judgment and Decision Making in Information Systems Probability, Utility, and Game Theory Yuval Shahar, M.D., Ph.D.
Lecture II.  Using the example from Birenens Chapter 1: Assume we are interested in the game Texas lotto (similar to Florida lotto).  In this game,
Combining Bayesian Beliefs and Willingness to Bet to Analyze Attitudes towards Uncertainty by Peter P. Wakker, Econ. Dept., Erasmus Univ. Rotterdam (joint.
Statistical Hypothesis Testing. Suppose you have a random variable X ( number of vehicle accidents in a year, stock market returns, time between el nino.
Behavior in the loss domain : an experiment using the probability trade-off consistency condition Olivier L’Haridon GRID, ESTP-ENSAM.
Professor : Soe-Tsyr, Yuan Presenter : Sherry Endogenizing Prospect Theory’s Reference Point by Ulrich Schmidt and Horst Zank.
1 CSI5388: Functional Elements of Statistics for Machine Learning Part I.
Thinking and Decision Making
Adapting de Finetti's Proper Scoring Rules for Measuring Bayesian Subjective Probabilities when Those Probabilities Are not Bayesian Peter P. Wakker (&
On the smooth ambiguity model and Machina’s reflection example Robert Nau Fuqua School of Business Duke University.
Basics of Probability. A Bit Math A Probability Space is a triple, where  is the sample space: a non-empty set of possible outcomes; F is an algebra.
Microeconomics 2 John Hey. Chapters 23, 24 and 25 CHOICE UNDER RISK Chapter 23: The Budget Constraint. Chapter 24: The Expected Utility Model. Chapter.
Prospect Theory. 23A i 23B, reference point 23A) Your country is plagued with an outbreak of an exotic Asian disease, which may kill 600 people. You.
Axioms Let W be statements known to be true in a domain An axiom is a rule presumed to be true An axiomatic set is a collection of axioms Given an axiomatic.
1 TABLE OF CONTENTS PROBABILITY THEORY Lecture – 1Basics Lecture – 2 Independence and Bernoulli Trials Lecture – 3Random Variables Lecture – 4 Binomial.
Modern Ways to Model Risk and Uncertainty Peter P. Topic: prospect theory (  classical expected utility) for modeling risk/uncertainty/ambiguity.
Properties of OLS How Reliable is OLS?. Learning Objectives 1.Review of the idea that the OLS estimator is a random variable 2.How do we judge the quality.
1 On Interactions in the RM-ODP Guy Genilloud, Gonzalo Génova WODPEC’2005 Workshop on ODP for Enterprise Computing * Information Engineering Group Departamento.
Paul Milgrom and Nancy Stokey Journal of Economic Thoery,1982.
Ambiguity Made Operational by Peter P. Wakker, Econ. Dept., Erasmus Univ. Rotterdam (joint with Mohammed Abdellaoui & Aurélien Baillon) ESA, Tucson, Oct.
Ellsberg’s paradoxes: Problems for rank- dependent utility explanations Cherng-Horng Lan & Nigel Harvey Department of Psychology University College London.
PROBABILITY AND STATISTICS FOR ENGINEERING Hossein Sameti Department of Computer Engineering Sharif University of Technology Principles of Parameter Estimation.
Diversification of Parameter Uncertainty Eric R. Ulm Georgia State University.
What properties would expect preferences to exhibit?
Lecture 3 on Individual Optimization Uncertainty Up until now we have been treating bidders as expected wealth maximizers, and in that way treating their.
Decision theory under uncertainty
Axiomatic Theory of Probabilistic Decision Making under Risk Pavlo R. Blavatskyy University of Zurich April 21st, 2007.
Inference: Probabilities and Distributions Feb , 2012.
Algebra Problems… Solutions Algebra Problems… Solutions © 2007 Herbert I. Gross Set 17 part 2 By Herbert I. Gross and Richard A. Medeiros next.
Expected Value, Expected Utility & the Allais and Ellsberg Paradoxes
Allais Paradox, Ellsberg Paradox, and the Common Consequence Principle Then: Introduction to Prospect Theory Psychology 466: Judgment & Decision Making.
Auctions serve the dual purpose of eliciting preferences and allocating resources between competing uses. A less fundamental but more practical reason.
Adapting de Finetti's proper scoring rules for Measuring Subjective Beliefs to Modern Decision Theories ofAmbiguity Peter P. Wakker (& Gijs van de Kuilen,
How Should Presidents Be Elected? E. Maskin Institute for Advanced Study.
Uncertainty and confidence Although the sample mean,, is a unique number for any particular sample, if you pick a different sample you will probably get.
Copyright © 2009 Pearson Education, Inc. 9.2 Hypothesis Tests for Population Means LEARNING GOAL Understand and interpret one- and two-tailed hypothesis.
Risk Efficiency Criteria Lecture XV. Expected Utility Versus Risk Efficiency In this course, we started with the precept that individual’s choose between.
Social Choice Lectures 14 and 15 John Hey. Lectures 14 and 15: Arrow’s Impossibility Theorem and other matters Plan of lecture: Aggregation of individual.
Does risk aversion give us a good reason to diversify our charitable portfolio? James Snowden.
Updating Ambiguity Averse Preferences Eran Hanany Peter Klibanoff Tel Aviv UniversityNorthwestern University Faculty of EngineeringKellogg School of Management.
Von Neumann-Morgenstern Lecture II. Utility and different views of risk Knightian – Frank Knight Risk – known probabilities of events Uncertainty – unknown.
12. Principles of Parameter Estimation
CHAPTER 1 FOUNDATIONS OF FINANCE I: EXPECTED UTILITY THEORY
What properties would we expect preferences to exhibit?
Ascertaining certain certainties in choices under uncertainty
Risk Chapter 11.
Behavioral Finance Economics 437.
12. Principles of Parameter Estimation
Presentation transcript:

Uncertainty RUD, June 28, 2006, Peter P. Wakker Paper: Chapter for New Palgrave. Its didactical beginning is not optimal for this specialized audience. Paper does contain opinions about current and future directions in the field. Opinions and discussion is the purpose of this lecture. Abstract:

1. Probabilistic sophistication does not signal ambiguity neutrality, but ambiguity uniformity. An endogenous definition of unambiguous seems to be impossible. 2. Unambiguity is best defined through given objective probabilities. 3. Convexity (say; or inverse-S) of capacities for unknown probabilities is primarily implied by the Allais paradox and not by the Ellsberg paradox. 4. The Ellsberg paradox generates deviations from expected utility in a relative sense, not suggesting that capacities for unknown probabilities are convex, but that capacities for unknown probabilities are more convex than they are for known probabilities. 5. In Schmeidler (1989), where capacities are linear for known probabilities, "more-convex-for-unknown-probabilities" happens to coincide with "convex," which has led to many misunderstandings. 6. The main novelty of the Ellsberg paradox is not the introduction of ambiguity aversion, but the introduction of within-person comparisons (as opposed to between-person comparisons as by Pratt, Arrow, Yaari) of behavior across different sources of uncertainty. 2

Survey Part I. Endogenous versus Exogenous Ambiguity Part II. Group Discussion on Terminology Part III. New Views on Ambiguity, Ellsberg, and Allais 3

1. Ambiguity; Definitions Urn 1... Urn i... Each urn contains 1000 balls ("=" continuum). Each ball has # between 1 and Contents can be irregular, with some #'s double, others missing (partially unknown compositions). One ball drawn at random, its # inspected; # i : the number drawn from urn i. For each urn i, info symmetric w.r.t. 1,…,1000 ("exchangeable", "strongly uniform partitions"). We define a uniform "mathematical" probability measure P on each urn i (P(j) = for each j). 4

Outcomes: $ Acts: as usual. Throughout, I assume Choquet expected utility (CEU). Always U is linear. For each urn i, W i = w i o P. Probabilistic sophistication within each urn! w i may be nonlinear. As soon as some w i 's are different, there cannot be a "joint" probabilistic sophistication. 5 Contrary to misunderstandings in the literature (strongly uniform partitions) E&Z'01, footnote 18)

CEU: w 1 (0.5)  100 = 0.5  100 = 50 6 (# 1  500: $100) (# 2  500: $100) EXAMPLE. w 1 (p) = p; w 2 (p) = p 2. w 2 lower, more convex, more pessimistic, than w 1. (# 1  500: $100) (# 2  500: $100)!  > ? Similarly: (# 1 > 500: $100) (# 2 > 500: $100)  Ellsberg-type dislike for urn 2. Tversky: source preference for urn 1. CEU: w 2 (0.5)  100 =  100 = 25

Question: How determine whether urns are (un)ambiguous? 2. Only Endogenous Info 2.1. Observe choices for one urn only My answer: (Un)ambiguity cannot be determined. No way to separate ambiguity from ambiguity attitude unless strong extra assumptions. E&Z: Epstein (& Zhang 2001) G&M: Ghirardato & Marinacci (2002) 7 Example a minute ago was two urns. Forget about that. Now only one urn.

E&Z:  i urn i is unambiguous. Remember: only 1 urn is observed! G&M: urn i is unambiguous iff w i is linear (EU) Observe Two (or More) Urns with Different w's (see previous example) Then no "joint" probabilistic sophistication. I: still can't disentangle ambiguity from ambiguity attitude. G&M: It is the one with w linear (if any); EU! Problem: Then all nonEU is ambiguity!? NonEU may also occur in absence of ambiguity (Allais etc.). 8 G&M is Internally coherent: If -only normatively interested -Assume that EU is normative for given probs. -Assume that EU is not normative for unknonw probs. Then terminology OK, does not harm. However, whoever disagrees with normative claims cannot follow this terminology. Descriptive work cannot follow this terminology either. G&M is Internally coherent: If -only normatively interested -Assume that EU is normative for given probs. -Assume that EU is not normative for unknonw probs. Then terminology OK, does not harm. However, whoever disagrees with normative claims cannot follow this terminology. Descriptive work cannot follow this terminology either. The fact that you can't observe whether it is ambiguous or unambiguous does not justify calling it unambiguous. Should say "I don't know." Ask Larry?

E&Z: You can't tell as long as no  's of different- urn events are considered. To wit: 9 is not violated for any event T on domain of no  's of different-urn events. So how can E&Z determine on (un)ambiguity? As follows. TcTc A x* B xB x E 1 ….E n h 1 ….h n Not Let x*>x. TcTc A xA x B x* E 1 ….E n h 1 ….h n  c´c´ x* x h 1 ….h n c´c´ x x* h 1 ….h n  T is unambiguous if (also for not-T):

10 1. Inspect acts for  's of different-urn events. E.g. for A,B, E j in: A: set of all events passing test (Dynkin system). 2. If A satisfies some extra axioms (mainly 4: richness; 6: strong-partition-neutrality), implying "global" probabilistic sophistication on A, then all of A is unambiguous. TcTc A x* B xB x E 1 ….E n h 1 ….h n Not Let x*>x. TcTc A xA x B x* E 1 ….E n h 1 ….h n  c´c´ x* x h 1 ….h n c´c´ x x* h 1 ….h n  T is unambiguous if (also for not-T): Really get complete algebra of events.

11 My opinion: There are difficulties for E&Z. - In many plausible situations, the extra axioms are not satisfied. Then E&Z does not help. - Extension to  's of different-urn events is crucial (contrary to Savage 1954), but often not natural. - In many situations, E&Z's definition of unambiguous does not capture that concept. - E&Z's theorem is an axiomatization of probabilistic sophistication, not more entitled to capture (un)ambiguity than any other axiomatization thereof on Dynkin systems. Later: Prob. soph. = uniformity of ambiguity,  absence of ambiguity.

3. Exogenous Info Available Again, assume two urns. EXAMPLE. Urn 1 : all #'s are present in urn; known composition; objective probabilities (I: "risk"). w 1 (p) =  p (optimism); w 2 (p) = (  p) 2 = p. I: Urn 1 is unambiguous. E&Z: ? G&M: ? 12

5. Probabilistic Sophistication as Uniform Ambiguity Each urn is a source (of uncertainty). (Tversky; Ergin & Gul: Issue; Chew & Sagi, 2004: small world). Strong source preference of Urn 1 over Urn 2 : For all partitions (A 1,…,A n ) for Urn 1 and (B 1,…,B n ) for Urn 2, A i  B i (in sense of betting on) for all i & A i  B i for some i may happen; converse cannot happen. 13

Uniform ambiguity of a source: the source exhibits strong source preference with respect to itself; so, "strong source indifference:" For all partitions (A 1,…,A n ) and (B 1,…,B n )  i  n  1: B j ~ A i  B n ~ A n. IMPLICATION: A 1 ~ B 1 & A 2 ~ B 2  A 1  A 2 ~ B 1  B 2 (disjunctions). PROOF: (A 1  A 2 ) c ~ (B 1  B 2 ) c 14 as reflexivity would have it

Implication: Probabilistic sophistication! We also have reversed implication. It is an equivalence. Conclusion: Probabilistic sophistication = uniform ambiguity. Can serve well to define sources ("small worlds"). 15

Btw: Above reasoning comprises not only source preference but also source sensitivity. 16