1 School of Economics University of East Anglia Norwich NR4 7TJ, United Kingdom Salience and tacit collusion Paper for conference ‘Cartels and Tacit Collusion’

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Strategic competition and collusion Oligopolists need to ensure that they all restrict output – collusion is sustained AND (in the same way as monopolists)
Advertisements

Nagel: Unraveling in Guessing Games: An Experimental Study Economics 328 Spring 2005.
Ultimatum Game Two players bargain (anonymously) to divide a fixed amount between them. P1 (proposer) offers a division of the “pie” P2 (responder) decides.
Nash’s Theorem Theorem (Nash, 1951): Every finite game (finite number of players, finite number of pure strategies) has at least one mixed-strategy Nash.
Game Theory Assignment For all of these games, P1 chooses between the columns, and P2 chooses between the rows.
Tacit versus overt collusion. Firm size asymmetries and numbers: overview of current CCP research Stephen Davies (drawing on research.
This Segment: Computational game theory Lecture 1: Game representations, solution concepts and complexity Tuomas Sandholm Computer Science Department Carnegie.
Chapter Twenty-Eight Game Theory. u Game theory models strategic behavior by agents who understand that their actions affect the actions of other agents.
Congestion Games with Player- Specific Payoff Functions Igal Milchtaich, Department of Mathematics, The Hebrew University of Jerusalem, 1993 Presentation.
The Stag Hunt Game. Introduction The stag hunt, first proposed by Rousseau, is a game which describes a conflict between safety and social cooperation.
Static Games and Cournot Competition
Chapter 6 Game Theory © 2006 Thomson Learning/South-Western.
Chapter 6 Game Theory © 2006 Thomson Learning/South-Western.
Game Theory Game theory is an attempt to model the way decisions are made in competitive situations. It has obvious applications in economics. But it.
Experimental evidence of the emergence of aesthetic rules in pure coordination games Federica Alberti University of East Anglia ESA World Meeting 2007.
4 Why Should we Believe Politicians? Lupia and McCubbins – The Democratic Dilemma GV917.
ECO290E: Game Theory Lecture 4 Applications in Industrial Organization.
Cheap Talk. When can cheap talk be believed? We have discussed costly signaling models like educational signaling. In these models, a signal of one’s.
Chapter 6 © 2006 Thomson Learning/South-Western Game Theory.
Language and Coordination. Convention in the Theory of Meaning.
1 Duke PhD Summer Camp August 2007 Outline  Motivation  Mutual Consistency: CH Model  Noisy Best-Response: QRE Model  Instant Convergence: EWA Learning.
A camper awakens to the growl of a hungry bear and sees his friend putting on a pair of running shoes, “You can’t outrun a bear,” scoffs the camper. His.
Focal Points (Schelling’s Points). Thomas C. Schelling Born in 1921 Ph.D. in Economics, Harvard University Currently – University of Maryland school of.
Oligopoly The challenge of analyzing interdependent strategic decisions.
David Bryce © Adapted from Baye © 2002 Game Theory: The Competitive Dynamics of Strategy MANEC 387 Economics of Strategy MANEC 387 Economics.
Economics 103 Lecture # 17 Interaction Among the Few.
2.6 The Question of Causation. The goal in many studies is to establish a causal link between a change in the explanatory variable and a change in the.
BEE3049 Behaviour, Decisions and Markets Miguel A. Fonseca.
1 School of Economics University of East Anglia Norwich NR4 7TJ, United Kingdom Focal points in tacit bargaining games Andrea Isoni #, Anders Poulsen *,
Static Games and Cournot Competition
THE PROBLEM OF MULTIPLE EQUILIBRIA NE is not enough by itself and must be supplemented by some other consideration that selects the one equilibrium with.
Evolutionary Games The solution concepts that we have discussed in some detail include strategically dominant solutions equilibrium solutions Pareto optimal.
An introduction to game theory Today: The fundamentals of game theory, including Nash equilibrium.
An introduction to game theory Today: The fundamentals of game theory, including Nash equilibrium.
Introduction to Game Theory and Behavior Networked Life CIS 112 Spring 2009 Prof. Michael Kearns.
QR 38, 2/22/07 Strategic form: dominant strategies I.Strategic form II.Finding Nash equilibria III.Strategic form games in IR.
Game Applications Chapter 29. Nash Equilibrium In any Nash equilibrium (NE) each player chooses a “best” response to the choices made by all of the other.
Evolutionary Games The solution concepts that we have discussed in some detail include strategically dominant solutions equilibrium solutions Pareto optimal.
An introduction to game theory Today: The fundamentals of game theory, including Nash equilibrium.
Introduction to Game Theory and Strategic Interactions.
Thinking Actively in a Social Context T A S C.
Data Management Grade 7. What’s the Story? Secondary data is information that was collected by someone else. Referring to information that was published.
Social Choice Session 7 Carmen Pasca and John Hey.
Microeconomics 2 John Hey. Game theory (and a bit of bargaining theory) A homage to John Nash. Born Still alive (as far as Google knows). Spent.
Chapter 9: Static Games and Cournot Competition 1 Static Games and Cournot Competition.
McGraw-Hill/Irwin Copyright  2008 by The McGraw-Hill Companies, Inc. All rights reserved. GAME THEORY, STRATEGIC DECISION MAKING, AND BEHAVIORAL ECONOMICS.
Game-theoretic analysis tools Tuomas Sandholm Professor Computer Science Department Carnegie Mellon University.
Chapters 29, 30 Game Theory A good time to talk about game theory since we have actually seen some types of equilibria last time. Game theory is concerned.
Experimental Economics NSF short course David Laibson August 11, 2005.
Salience Tarek Rached. Overview David Gauthier proposes salience as a criterion for equilibrium selection in his paper Coordination, published in in Dialogue,
Experimental evidence of the emergence of aesthetic rules in pure coordination games Federica Alberti (Uea) Creed/Cedex/Uea Meeting Experimental Economics.
Data Analysis Econ 176, Fall Populations When we run an experiment, we are always measuring an outcome, x. We say that an outcome belongs to some.
3.1.4 Types of Games. Strategic Behavior in Business and Econ Outline 3.1. What is a Game ? The elements of a Game The Rules of the Game:
Frank Cowell: Microeconomics Game Theory: Basics MICROECONOMICS Principles and Analysis Frank Cowell March 2004.
Strategic Behavior in Business and Econ Static Games of complete information: Dominant Strategies and Nash Equilibrium in pure and mixed strategies.
1 Choosing a Computer Science Research Problem. 2 Choosing a Computer Science Research Problem One of the hardest problems with doing research in any.
Multiplication of Common Fractions © Math As A Second Language All Rights Reserved next #6 Taking the Fear out of Math 1 3 ×1 3 Applying.
1 School of Economics University of East Anglia Norwich NR4 7TJ, United Kingdom How inductive inferences can be grounded on salience alone: some reflections.
Lec 23 Chapter 28 Game Theory.
Cheap Talk. When can cheap talk be believed? We have discussed costly signaling models like educational signaling. In these models, a signal of one’s.
Dynamic Game Theory and the Stackelberg Model. Dynamic Game Theory So far we have focused on static games. However, for many important economic applications.
Tacit collusion, firm asymmetries and numbers: evidence from EC merger cases M. Olczak & S. Davies with H. Coles Royal Economic Society.
Chapter 12 Game Theory Presented by Nahakpam PhD Student 1Game Theory.
Replicator Dynamics.
Game Theory: The Competitive Dynamics of Strategy
Simultaneous Move Games: Discrete Strategies
Unit 4 SOCIAL INTERACTIONS.
Chapter 29 Game Theory Key Concept: Nash equilibrium and Subgame Perfect Nash equilibrium (SPNE)
Molly W. Dahl Georgetown University Econ 101 – Spring 2009
Lecture Game Theory.
Presentation transcript:

1 School of Economics University of East Anglia Norwich NR4 7TJ, United Kingdom Salience and tacit collusion Paper for conference ‘Cartels and Tacit Collusion’ Centre for Competition Policy University of East Anglia, 18 – 19 June 2009 Robert Sugden

2 This research is about tacit collusion, considered in abstract terms. Question to be investigated: can salience be used to resolve tacit bargaining problems? ‘Tacit bargaining problem’ (:Schelling) = two (or more) players face a set of alternative payoff distributions; each of these is better for both players than the no-agreement point; but some favour one player, some another [as in Battle of the Sexes]; no communication.

3 Schelling’s main reason for analysing tacit bargaining is modelling simplicity: he argues that many of the factors which influence tacit bargaining are operative in ‘explicit’ bargaining too. But some real-world bargaining problems are tacit. Decision- making within illegal cartels may be an example. Schelling argues that tacit bargaining problems are typically resolved by players converging on a focal point, i.e. an equilibrium that is distinguished by its prominence or salience. Salience may depend on features of games that conventional game theory treats as irrelevant labelling. Schelling argues that game- theoretic ‘bargaining solutions’ (e.g. Nash bargaining solution) are just equilibria that happen to be salient to game theorists – so we shouldn’t expect these solutions to predict behaviour of ordinary people, even people who are very rational (in a pragmatic sense).

4 Schelling’s hypothesis wasn’t new in Hume, Treatise of Human Nature, 1740: Hume argued that disputes over possession of goods are resolved by appeal to associations of ideas, especially association between claimant and object (first possession, long possession, ‘contiguity’ [‘closeness’]) and between unowned object and owned object (‘accession’). Suppose a German, a Frenchman, and a Spaniard to come into a room, where there are plac’d upon the table three bottles of wine, Rheinish, Burgundy, and Port; and suppose they shou’d fall a quarelling about the division of them; a person, who was chosen for umpire, wou’d naturally, to shew his impartiality, give every one the product of his own country: And this from a principle, which, in some measure, is the source of those laws of nature, that ascribe orioperty to occupation, prescription and accession ( ).

5 However, very little experimental evidence on effects of salience in tacit bargaining games. Most research on salience has focused on pure coordination games. Schelling treats pure coordination games as simple models for investigating factors which (he thinks) influence tacit bargaining problems too. But do they?

6 I’ll review two experimental investigations which seem to point in opposite directions, then tell you what ‘our’ research group (Andrea Isoni, Anders Poulsen, Kei Tsutsui, me) is doing to try to resolve the issue. 1. An experiment done at UEA many years ago: Judith Mehta, Chris Starmer and Robert Sugden, AER An experiment by Crawford, Gneezy and Rottenstreich, AER 2008.

7 Our AER 1994 experiment The first (?) attempt to replicate Schelling’s ‘informal’ experiments in a controlled setting, with incentives. A set of 20 pure coordination games, presented in two treatments: Coordination: as in Schelling’s games: two players simultaneously face the same task (e.g. ‘name any British town or city’); they are rewarded for giving the same answer. Picking: same task, but instruction is: ‘We are conducting a survey... You may respond to these questions in any way you wish.’ Point of the picking treatment is is to find out how much coordination is explained by ‘primary salience’, i.e. correlation between unthinking responses of different individuals.

8 We included some questions which we thought might evoke forms of salience that would be relevant to bargaining problems – even though these questions were presented as pure coordination games.

9 Coordination treatment: ‘You must assign each circle to one or other of the squares. You will score a point if this assignment is exactly the same as the other person’s.’ Picking treatment: ‘You must assign each circle to one or other of the squares’ [with no effect on payoff] Our thought: this display may evoke ideas relevant to problem of dividing valuable objects between claimants.

10 Coordination treatment: 67% per cent chose this assignment (= closeness + equality). Picking treatment: 31% chose this. [16 possible responses.]

11 A more difficult task...

12 Coordination treatment: 29% chose this (= accession). (Picking treatment: 13%.)

13 Coordination treatment: 26% chose this (= closeness). (Picking treatment: 30%.)

14 Coordination treatment: 21% chose this (= equality, with closeness as tie-breaker). (Picking treatment: 9%.) [Note: there are 16 possible responses; the three most common responses (accession, closeness, equality) collect 76% of coordinators’ responses.]

15 Implication of these (and other tasks in the experiment): when ‘assign objects to claimants’ problems are presented as pure coordination games, players use principles of salience that are potentially relevant to tacit bargaining problems (equality, closeness, accession). But: we don’t know whether these principles would be used in games that really were tacit bargaining problems.

16 Crawford et al: the title of their paper tells you what they found: ‘The power of focal points is limited: even minute payoff asymmetry may yield large coordination failures’.

17 Crawford, Gneezy and Rottenstreich (AER, 2008): symmetrical pie game 5, 5 (In experiment, whole slice shaded or unshaded.) Instruction: You are player 1 [first payoff; or player 2: second payoff]. Choose a slice. If both players choose the same slice, you get the payoffs shown on the slice; otherwise, you both get nothing.

18 symmetrical pie game: 5, 5 0% 6% 94% Expected coordination rate: 89% ‘Odd one out’ rule used to coordinate.

19 assymmetrical pie game 5, 66, 5 (In experiment, whole slice shaded or unshaded.) Instruction: You are player 1 [first payoff; or player 2: second payoff]. Choose a slice. If both players choose the same slice, you get the payoffs shown on the slice; otherwise, you both get nothing.

20 asymmetrical pie game: 5, 66, 5 Player 1: 16% Player 2: 33% Player 1: 53% Player 2: 21% Player 1: 32% Player 2: 46% Expected coordination rate: 31% Notice tendency to choose 5 – this produces discoordinaton.

21 Implication: pure coordination games are resolved effectively by salience; but salience is not used in tacit bargaining games (resulting in lack of coordination). Intuitively: asymmetry in payoffs diverts players’ attention from salience. [Crawford et al explain this by adapting cognitive hierarchy theory.]

22 Our plans for a new experiment Main idea: to use the ‘circles and squares’ display of the 1994 AER paper, but with the payoff structure of a tacit bargaining game. Our hunch (following Hume): in tacit bargaining games, the most salient solutions evoke associations between claimants and objects (rather than giving salient labels to payoff distributions, as in Crawford et al).

23 Instruction: You are Blue [Red]. Claim as many discs as you like by ‘lassoing’ them to your square. If no disc is claimed by both players, you will each be paid the value of the discs you have claimed; otherwise, you both get nothing. 56 A tacit bargaining game with same payoff structure (after elimination of dominated strategies) as Crawford et al’s game: What players might do...

24 Here any integer division of 10 is possible. E.g. equal division (with closeness as tie-breaker) Another game with the same rules...

25... or unequal division suggested by closeness and accession

26 My expectation is that spatial concepts of salience will be used in these games, and will sometimes trump payoff-based principles (especially equality of payoff). Mixed signals from pilot experiments – we must wait and see what happens when we run the experiments for real...

27 Thank you for listening.

28 A more difficult task with the same rules.

29 Coordination treatment: 41% chose this (= closeness). (Picking treatment: 26%.)

30 Coordination treatment: 32% chose this (= equality, with closeness as tie-breaker). (Picking treatment: 14%.)

31 Cognitive hierarchy theory ‘Level 0’ players ‘choose the salient’ – interpreted as best payoff to them, or odd one out as tie-breaker. ‘Level 1’ players choose best replies to level 0. ‘Level 2’ players choose best replies to level 1. Most common level = 1, followed by 2. In symmetrical games, everyone chooses the odd one out (so 100% coordination). In asymmetrical games, level 1 players choose 5, level 2 players choose 6 (so low rate of coordination, with most common choice = 5).

32