PLAYING GAMES Topic #2. THE SOCIAL COORDINATION GAME You are in a group of six people, each of whom has an initial holding of $50 (just enough to guarantee.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
The Basics of Game Theory
Advertisements

GAMES IN EEXTENSIVE AND STRATEGIC FORM Topic #7. Review: A Best Reply Given a strategy choice by the other player, your best reply to it is the strategy.
Nash Equilibrium: Illustrations
Arbitration. Introduction In this section we will consider the impact of outside arbitration on coordination games Specifically, we will consider two.
3.1 Fair Division: To divide S into shares (one for each player) in such a way that each player gets a fair share. Fair Division: To divide S into shares.
WONG TO YEUNG LEO WONG KA WANG KELVIN LAI CHUNG YIN ROY How to play games?
1 Game Theory. 2 Definitions Game theory -- formal way to analyze interactions among a group of rational agents behaving strategically Agents – players.
Game theory (Sections )
VARIATIONS ON SIMPLE PAYOFF MATRICES Topic #6. The Payoff Matrix Given any payoff matrix, the standard assumption is – that the players choose their strategies.
Non-Cooperative Game Theory To define a game, you need to know three things: –The set of players –The strategy sets of the players (i.e., the actions they.
Chapter 6 Game Theory © 2006 Thomson Learning/South-Western.
EC941 - Game Theory Lecture 7 Prof. Francesco Squintani
Economic Analysis for Business Session XIII: Oligopoly Instructor Sandeep Basnyat
Game theory (Sections ). Game theory Game theory deals with systems of interacting agents where the outcome for an agent depends on the actions.
4 Why Should we Believe Politicians? Lupia and McCubbins – The Democratic Dilemma GV917.
Excursions in Modern Mathematics Sixth Edition
Social Choice Topics to be covered:
Chapter 6 © 2006 Thomson Learning/South-Western Game Theory.
Game Theory Analysis Sidney Gautrau. John von Neumann is looked at as the father of modern game theory. Many other theorists, such as John Nash and John.
GAME THEORY By Ben Cutting & Rohit Venkat. Game Theory: General Definition  Mathematical decision making tool  Used to analyze a competitive situation.
EC941 - Game Theory Prof. Francesco Squintani Lecture 8 1.
A camper awakens to the growl of a hungry bear and sees his friend putting on a pair of running shoes, “You can’t outrun a bear,” scoffs the camper. His.
Chapter 12 Choices Involving Strategy McGraw-Hill/Irwin Copyright © 2008 by The McGraw-Hill Companies, Inc. All Rights Reserved.
Todd and Steven Divide the Estate Problem Bargaining over 100 pounds of gold Round 1: Todd makes offer of Division. Steven accepts or rejects. Round.
Objectives © Pearson Education, 2005 Oligopoly LUBS1940: Topic 7.
David Bryce © Adapted from Baye © 2002 Game Theory: The Competitive Dynamics of Strategy MANEC 387 Economics of Strategy MANEC 387 Economics.
More on Extensive Form Games. Histories and subhistories A terminal history is a listing of every play in a possible course of the game, all the way to.
ECON6036 1st semester Format of final exam Same as the mid term
Review: Game theory Dominant strategy Nash equilibrium
THE PROBLEM OF MULTIPLE EQUILIBRIA NE is not enough by itself and must be supplemented by some other consideration that selects the one equilibrium with.
Developing Principles in Bargaining. Motivation Consider a purely distributive bargaining situation where impasse is costly to both sides How should we.
Game Theory Objectives:
Quantitative Reasoning 38 The Strategy of International Politics Professor Lisa Martin Head TF Yev Kirpichevsky TF Dilyan Donchev.
UNIT II: The Basic Theory Zero-sum Games Nonzero-sum Games Nash Equilibrium: Properties and Problems Bargaining Games Bargaining and Negotiation Review.
Game Theory Statistics 802. Lecture Agenda Overview of games 2 player games representations 2 player zero-sum games Render/Stair/Hanna text CD QM for.
C H A P T E R 13 Game Theory and Competitive Strategy CHAPTER OUTLINE
Game Theory.
Introduction to Game Theory
Chapter 12 & Module E Decision Theory & Game Theory.
Social Choice Session 7 Carmen Pasca and John Hey.
Game Theory, Strategic Decision Making, and Behavioral Economics 11 Game Theory, Strategic Decision Making, and Behavioral Economics All men can see the.
Chapter 3 Arbitrage and Financial Decision Making
Chapter 14: Fair Division Part 4 – Divide and Choose for more than two players.
McGraw-Hill/Irwin Copyright  2008 by The McGraw-Hill Companies, Inc. All rights reserved. GAME THEORY, STRATEGIC DECISION MAKING, AND BEHAVIORAL ECONOMICS.
Todd and Steven Divide the Estate Problem Bargaining over 100 pounds of gold Round 1: Todd makes offer of Division. Steven accepts or rejects. Round.
THE “CLASSIC” 2 x 2 SIMULTANEOUS CHOICE GAMES Topic #4.
Negotiation 101 Fairness and the importance of looking ahead.
Chapter 3 Fair Division.
Excursions in Modern Mathematics, 7e: Copyright © 2010 Pearson Education, Inc. 3 The Mathematics of Sharing 3.1Fair-Division Games 3.2Two Players:
KRUGMAN'S MICROECONOMICS for AP* Game Theory Margaret Ray and David Anderson Micro: Econ: Module.
제 10 장 게임이론 Game Theory: Inside Oligopoly
Sample: Probability “Fair Game” Project (borrowed from Intel®, then adjusted)
Lecture 1 on Bargaining Setting the Agenda This lecture focuses on the well known problem of how to split the gains from trade or, more generally, mutual.
Intermediate Microeconomics Game Theory and Oligopoly.
Game theory (Sections )
Chapter 16 Oligopoly and Game Theory. “Game theory is the study of how people behave in strategic situations. By ‘strategic’ we mean a situation in which.
Statistics Overview of games 2 player games representations 2 player zero-sum games Render/Stair/Hanna text CD QM for Windows software Modeling.
Managerial Economics Game Theory Aalto University School of Science Department of Industrial Engineering and Management January 12 – 28, 2016 Dr. Arto.
Bargaining games Econ 414. General bargaining games A common application of repeated games is to examine situations of two or more parties bargaining.
Oligopoly CHAPTER 13B. Oligopoly IRL In some markets there are only two firms. Computer chips are an example. The chips that drive most PCs are made by.
Dynamic Game Theory and the Stackelberg Model. Dynamic Game Theory So far we have focused on static games. However, for many important economic applications.
Lecture 4 on Auctions Multiunit Auctions We begin this lecture by comparing auctions with monopolies. We then discuss different pricing schemes for selling.
Game Theory By Ben Cutting & Rohit Venkat.
Management support systems II
How to think about strategic games
Game Theory: The Competitive Dynamics of Strategy
Games & Politics Evgeniya Lukinova.
THE ECONOMY: THE CORE PROJECT
Lecture 10 Coordination and Reputation
Excursions in Modern Mathematics Sixth Edition
Presentation transcript:

PLAYING GAMES Topic #2

THE SOCIAL COORDINATION GAME You are in a group of six people, each of whom has an initial holding of $50 (just enough to guarantee that no one ends up with a net loss, regardless of the outcome of the game). You have the opportunity, based on your own actions and those of the others in the group, to earn an additional amount or to lose some or all of your initial holding. You (and each other member of the group) must choose between two actions, designated LEFT and RIGHT (no political connotations intended), which have these consequences: –(A) If you choose LEFT, you earn $10 for each other member of the group who chooses LEFT but you lose $10 for each other member of the group who chooses RIGHT. –(B) If you choose RIGHT, you earn $10 for each other member of the group who chooses RIGHT but you lose $10 for each other member of the group who chooses LEFT. In general, you earn more (or lose less) to the extent that others make the same choice you do.

SOCIAL COORDINATION GAME (cont.) Your goal is to maximize your own earnings, and you know that everyone else is similarly motivated. Version 1.Each player must make his or her choice in isolation, without talking to other players. Version 2. Players can talk among themselves (make deals or whatever) prior to making their choices. But, in both versions, final choices are made by “secret ballot,” i.e., it is a “simultaneous move” game. Do you choose LEFT or RIGHT?

SOCIAL COORDINATION GAME (cont.)

Coordination Games Coordination Games are non-trivial only if they are simultaneous choice games of imperfect information. They are perhaps “solved” by “[Shelling] focal points.” They are certainly “solved” by –sequential moves with perfect information –prior communication and there is no incentive for deception, no reason to break a promise –repeated play follow majority choice in previous play is “focal point” but problem with n = 2 –convention (drive on right/left) Two-player coordination with conflicting interests: –neither player wins anything if the fail to cooperate; –If they coordinate on LEFT, P1 wins $200 and P1 wins $100; –If they coordinate on RIGHT, P1 wins $100 and P2 wins $200.

Fair Division Children know how to divide a piece of cake “fair and square”: –One kid cuts, the other chooses. –The game has perfect information. –Both kids know each other’s preferences: they are both greedy cake maximizers. –So the cutting kid knows the choosing kid will take the larger piece. –“Look ahead and Reason Back” [Dixit and Nalebuff, Rule 1 (p. 34) –So the cutting kid follows the maximin principle, i.e., the cutting kid aims to make the smaller piece as big as possible (i.e., make the two pieces as equal as possible). Pre-play communication makes no difference in Fair Division –This a zero-sum (or constant-sum) game. If we turn it into a simultaneous move game (without perfect information), it character changes considerably, –though maximin is still appealing for the cutter. The n-player generalization Fair Division by Tacit Coordination

“The Bank” puts up a sum of money ($100) which two players can share if they can tacitly coordinate on how to divide it. This is a simultaneous move game but it is not constant-sum. Each player writes down (on a “secret ballot”) his requested share. –If the sum of the two requests does not exceed $100, each player get his requested share (and the bank keeps any residual share). –If the sum of the two requests exceeds $100, neither player gets anything. Discrete choice variant: can choose only 100-0, 80-20, 60-40, 40-60, 20-80, splits If the players can communicate in advance, this turns into a bargaining game –side payments (with enforceable agreements?)

The Ultimatum Game “The Bank” puts up a sum of money ($100), which two players can share (or not). P1 makes a proposal to P2 as to how to divide the $100 between them. P2 accepts or rejects P1’s proposal. If P1 accepts the proposal, the $100 is divided accordingly. If P2 rejects the proposal, neither player gets anything. If you’re P1, what do you offer? If you’re P2, what do you accept?

THE SOCIAL DILEMMA GAME You are in a group of five people, each of whom has an initial holding of $15 (just enough to guarantee to no one ends up with a net loss, regardless of the outcome of the game). You have the opportunity, based on your own actions and those of the others in the group, to earn an additional amount or to lose some or all of your initial holding. You (and each other member of the group) must choose between two actions, designated LEFT and RIGHT (no political connotations intended), which have these consequences: –(A) If you choose LEFT, you earn $25 and your action has no effect on any other group member; –(B) If you choose RIGHT, you earn $50 but your action also imposes a cost of $10 on each member of the group (yourself included, so you net $40). So, holding constant the choices of all others, you earn $25 more by choosing RIGHT rather than LEFT.

SOCIAL DILEMMA GAME (cont.) Your goal is to maximize your own earnings, and you know that everyone else is similarly motivated. Version 1. Each player must make his or her choice in isolation, without talking to other players. Version 2. Players can talk among themselves (and make deals or whatever) prior to making their choices. But, in both versions, final choices are made by "secret ballot.” Do you choose LEFT or RIGHT?

SOCIAL DILEMMA GAME (cont.)

Dilemma Games Dilemma Games are not solved by sequential moves. –Regardless of what you see other people doing, you are but off choosing RIGHT (or ‘‘defect.” –With prior communication, probably everything would promise to chose LEFT (or “Cooperate’), but everyone has an incentive to break this promise. –What is needed to “solve” the game is an binding agreement (or “enforceable contract” to cooperate. –However, repeated play may lead to more cooperation, even in the absence of a binding agreement.

Dilemma Games (cont.) Cars and trucks used to emit large quantities of pollutants, resulting in air pollution that was both unpleasant and unhealthful. In the 1970s, it became possible to reduce such pollution greatly by installing fairly inexpensive pollution-control devices on car and truck engines. Suppose in fact that everyone prefers –(a) the state of affairs in which everyone pays for and installs the devices and the air is clean to –(b) the state of affairs in which no one pays for and installs the devices and the air is polluted. Would (almost) everyone voluntarily install the devices? Would a law requiring everyone to install the devices pass in a referendum?

Common Pool Resources Garrett Hardin, “The Tragedy of the Commons,” Science, 1968 common pasture land vs. enclosure/common pool resources

The Centipede Game Initially there are two piles of money $$$ and $. P1 can either: –(a) take the $$$ pile and give the $ pile to P2, or –(b) take neither pile. If P1 chooses (a), the game is over. If P1 chooses (b), the piles are augmented to $$$$ and $$, and P2 chooses between (a) and (b). The game continues until a player chooses (a) or until 100 (hence centipede) rounds (or some other fixed number) have been played Implications of “look ahead and reason back” (the “subgame perfect equilibrium”) as in Fair Division Game

The Dollar Auction Game The Bank tells P1 and P2 that one of them will win a prize of $100. Each of P1 and P2 alternately pays $5 or more to the Bank until one player decides to stop paying and to pull out of the competition, at which point the other player wins the $100 prize. This can be thought of as auctioning off the prize to the highest bidder (hence the name of the game), –with the twist that both bidders must pay their final offers, though only the player who made the higher final offer gets the prize. How will this game end up? What would happen if the players can make an enforceable agreement before the bidding starts? So the Bank wants to make sure that P1 and P2 cannot enter into an enforceable agreement before the bidding starts.