Week 2: Nietzsche. What are the internal motivations for action in Nietzsche and Kierkegaard’s theories?

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Immanuel Kant ( ) Theory of Aesthetics
Advertisements

Anselm On the Existence of God. “Nor do I seek to understand so that I can believe, but rather I believe so that I can understand. For I believe this.
The Challenges of Darwinism. Dear Mr Darwin….. Imagine you are a 19 th century Christian who believes Darwin has it all wrong. Write a letter to him in.
Morality As Overcoming Self-Interest
German Philosophy: Kant and Hegel
Ben Gerke. Lived French existentialist philosopher, influenced by Kant, Hegel, and Kierkegaard, among others Father Jean-Baptiste Sartre was.
SARTRE, FROM “EXISTENTIALISM IS A HUMANISM” PHILOSOPHY 224.
ETHICS BOWL kantian ETHICS.
LECTURE. ‘An Oak Tree’ Michael Craig-Martin Jacques Derrida Gilles Deleuze.
POSITIVE LAW. Imagine a powerful sovereign who issues commands to his or her subjects. They are under a duty to comply with his wishes. The notion of.
Phil 160 Kant.
Hume on Taste Hume's account of judgments of taste parallels his discussion of judgments or moral right and wrong.  Both accounts use the internal/external.
REALISM Realism is the artistic response to the Civil War and the industrial/economic revolution that swept Europe and America in the last part of the.
1 Philosophy 151 Nineteenth Century European Philosophy Winter, 2004 G. J. Mattey.
BACKGROUND AND MEANING BASIC ASSUMPTIONS EXISTENTIALISM AND EDUCATION
Friedrich Nietzsche ( ) Tommy MacMeekin Kayla Seiler.
Friedrich Nietzsche ( ). Biogra phy -Born: 1844 in Prussia to a Lutheran Minister -Studied at University of Bonn and Univeristy of Liepzig specializing.
Larval Stage Born the son of a Lutheran pastor in Röcken, Saxony, Friedrich Nietzsche was raised by female relatives after his father's death in 1849.
Friedrich Nietzsche Giorgina Paiella. Brief Biography German philosopher Born in Prussian province of Saxony in 1844 Family of many Lutheran ministers.
CHAPTER FIVE: THE SOURCES OF KNOWLEDGE P H I L O S O P H Y A Text with Readings ELEVENTH EDITION M A N U E L V E L A S Q U E Z.
Parsing Categories of Belief Why Early Modern M&E divides belief into two types: Sensory & Mathematical.
Signs and Symbols.
Nietzsche and the denial of moral truth Michael Lacewing
Philosophy 224 Person As Passion: Kierkegaard and Nietzsche.
The Cosmological Argument (Causation or ‘first cause’ theory)
Essay Writing in Philosophy
Unit 4: Morality.
Dynamics of Theology Faith and the Community of Beliefs.
1 Critical Approaches to Literature Created by Mr. Smithmier
Sartre, from “Existentialism is a Humanism”
The Aesthetics of Natural Environments- Arnold Berleant Presentation by: Cody Shoemaker.
We are unknown to ourselves, we men of knowledge-and with good reason. We have never sought ourselves... (Nietzsche, On the Genealogy of Morals, 1887:
Morality and Responsibility Traditional and Modernist.
Through the Literary Looking Glass: Critical Theory in Practice 1301.
By : Hasina Islam.  The Age of Enlightenment (or simply the Enlightenment) is the era in Western philosophy and intellectual, scientific, and cultural.
Philosophy 1050: Introduction to Philosophy Week 10: Descartes and the Subject: The way of Ideas.
KANT ANTHROPOLOGY FROM A PRAGMATIC POINT OF VIEW PHILOSOPHY 224.
State of Nature Continued Three Approaches on the Subject: Locke, Rousseau and Anarchism.
Nietzsche and the Slave Revolt in Morals Critiques of Religion and Morality.
Evidential Challenge: Kierkegaard and Adams
Ways of Studying Religion. The Academic Study of Religion - Assumptions - One religion is neither better nor worse than another religion; they are simply.
Chapter 7: Ethics Nietzsche and Existentialism; Sartre; Ethics and Gender Introducing Philosophy, 10th edition Robert C. Solomon, Kathleen Higgins, and.
EXISTENTIALISM A philosophical movement in the 19 th and 20 th centuries.
The Moral Philosophy of Immanuel Kant The Ethics of Duty and Reason
Critical Social Theory
HUME’S ASSESSMENT OF NATURAL RELIGION --Summing up Text source: Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion, part 12.
Morality in the Modern World
Allegory of the Cave. What is an Allegory? “A form of extended metaphor, in which objects, persons, and actions in a narrative, are equated with meanings.
Radical Poetry 1. The Romantics
Immanuel Kant and the moral law. Kant (1) Kant’s ethics are those of the deist, rather than the theist. He was an important thinker in the deist project,
Philosophy 4610 Philosophy of Mind Week 1: Introduction.
And the Existential Framework
Philosophy An introduction. What is philosophy? Ancient Greek philosopher Aristotle said that philosophy is ‘the science which considers truth’
UNIT6: PHILOSOPHY: PERSONAL IDENTITY
Chapter 7: Ethics Morality and Practical Reason: Kant
Stuart Hall Who Needs ‘Identity’?.
Instructor: Todd Ganson.  Φιλοσοφία (philo-sophia)
Friedrich Nietzsche’s Moral Theory 1. Friedrich Nietzsche ( ) German Philosopher The Birth of Tragedy (1871) Human, Too Human (1878) Thus Spoke.
Chapter 1: The cosmological argument AQA Religious Studies: Philosophy of Religion AS Level © Nelson Thornes Ltd 2008 Revision.
ORIENTALISM Edward Said.  Edward Said surveys the history and nature of Western attitudes towards the East, considering Orientalism as a powerful European.
The Nature of God Nancy Parsons. Attributes- Nature of God Candidates should be able to demonstrate knowledge and understanding of: 1.God as eternal,
The Argument  In modern times Philosophy has shifted from an interest in God to an interest in religion (from “Philosophical Theology” to “Philosophy.
KANTIANISM AND EUTHANASIA ATTITUDES TO KEY ISSUES.
Understanding Literary Theory and Critical Lenses
Why Be Ethical?/You are what You Do
Post- Structuralist.
Conclusion – Truth and wisdom
Person As Passion: Kierkegaard and Nietzsche
The Philosophy of Hegel
Presentation transcript:

Week 2: Nietzsche

What are the internal motivations for action in Nietzsche and Kierkegaard’s theories?

Nietzsche was a German philosopher whose ideas have not ceased to be controversial since their initial publication in his most famous texts: The Birth of Tragedy, 1872 Human, All Too Human, 1878 Daybreak, 1881 The Gay Science, 1882 Thus Spake Zarathustra, 1885 (seen by many as his magnum opus) Beyond Good and Evil, 1886 The Genealogy of Morals, 1887 Twilight of the Idols, 1888 The Anti-Christ, 1888 And Ecce Homo, 1888 (a kind of autobiography)

Perhaps given the short time between publishing the majority of his major texts, there are a large number of intersections and connections drawn between the concepts outlined and problems explored in these texts. However, Beyond Good and Evil is the text which most rigorously and systematically outlines his concept of the ‘will to power’ (the later text, The Will to Power, is a collection edited by his sister from his late notebooks and has received strong criticism for a variety of reasons). This week we will explore secondary readings of Nietzsche’s ideas surrounding the ‘will to power’, so as to better ground our own readings for next week, where we will get to the text itself. Before we do so, we can remind ourselves of some of the characteristics of the ‘will’ and the ‘will to power’ outlined last week:

The ‘will’ that Nietzsche argues as being a motivation for action is not the ‘free will’ as in Kant Rather the will is comprised of conflicting forces which construct us as individuals We are always subject to other forces and so there is no ‘pure subjectivity’, autonomy, or free will The ‘will’ for Nietzsche is precisely not free Part of Nietzsche’s project is to understand and, more significantly, affirm, the forces which affect on us and direct our ‘will’. That affirmation is an act of ‘power’. He asks the question of whether or not we are strong enough to affirm our ‘will’ if it takes us against herd morality. Are we strong enough to let our actions be dictated by our will or are we rather subject to hard rationality and morality?

James Winchester interprets Nietzsche’s will to power as opposed to individual or subject ‘will’: ‘Within the system of will to power from Beyond Good and Evil there is a theory of subjectivity. Nietzsche uses the word “will” in two ways. He argues that the inorganic world and all living things, including humans, are comprised of forces. These forces of his antiatomistic world are called wills. In addition, the word also represents a common prejudice: many people believe that humans have a will that serves as the author of their voluntary actions.’ (Winchester: 1994, 45) ‘…Nietzsche uses the will to power as a basis for a system of evaluation. As a standard of evaluation Nietzsche employs it to measure the worth of, among other things, individuals, moral systems, cultural phenomena, and entire cultures. Often it is used to argue that the evaluation has a physiological base.’ (Winchester: 1994, 53)

Nietzsche’s ‘will to power’ was a concept which was explicitly challenging a history of philosophical enquiry into what the primary motivation for human action is or should be. Its most direct challenge was levelled at Schopenhauer (a great influence on Nietzsche’s early thought), whose concept of the ‘will to live’ could perhaps best be understood as a simple desire for living beings to survive – this may remind us of Hobbes’ basis for political action as well as Darwin. The first aphorism of Beyond Good and Evil not only undermines Schopenhauer but also any ‘will to truth’ or philosophy which seeks objective, unquestionable truths. For Nietzsche, perception and the ‘apparent world’ was made up of a relation of wills and the ‘power’ which controlled or is controlled by them.

Nietzsche also opposes ‘philosophical labourers’ (like Kant and Hegel) who ‘subdue’ to ‘philosophers’ who ‘create’. - read Para 211. Deleuze and Guattari suggest that: ‘…Nietzsche succeeded in making us understand, thought is creation, not will to truth. But if, contrary to what seemed to be the case in the classical image, there is no will to truth, this is because thought constitutes a simple “possibility” of thinking without yet defining a thinker “capable” of it and able to say “I”: what violence of an infinite movement must be exerted on thought for us to become capable of thinking; what violence of an infinite movement thus, at the same time, takes from us our power to say “I”?’ (Deleuze & Guattari: 2011, 54-55)

Georges Bataille, a famous philosopher in his own right, provides an intriguing reading of Nietzsche’s thought: ‘What is odd in Nietzsche’s doctrines is that they cannot be followed. Ahead of you are unfocused, at times dazzling radiances. Though the way to them remains untraceable. Nietzsche the prophet of new paths? But superman and eternal return are empty as motives of excitement or action, are inadequate compared to Christian and Buddhist motives. The will to power is in fact a paltry subject for consideration. Having it is one thing – but this doesn’t mean you should give it your attention.’ (Bataille: 2008, 85) What is important in the will to power is its basis as system; it is what is being evaluated and the evaluation itself which is of importance (and both end up being the same thing).

One of Nietzsche’s most respected readers was the philosopher Gilles Deleuze, who argued strongly that: ‘The relation of force to force is called “will.” That is why we must avoid at all costs the misinterpretations of the Nietzschean principle of the will to power. This principle doesn’t mean (or at least doesn’t primarily mean that the will wants power or wishes to dominate...The will to power, says Nietzsche, consists not in coveting or even in taking but in creating and giving.’ (Deleuze: 2001, 73)

Our will and our power constitutes and is constituted by a variety of wills and powers – at the basis of all this is ‘the will to power’. ‘We should not be surprised by the double aspect of the will to power: from the standpoint of the genesis or production of forces it determines that relation between forces but, from the standpoint of its own manifestations, it is determined by relating forces. This is why the will to power is always determined at the same time as it determines, qualified at the same time as it qualifies. In the first place, therefore, the will to power is manifested as the capacity for being affected, as the determinate capacity of force for being affected.’ (Deleuze: 1983, 62 [my emphasis])

A will seeks power and overflow of power strengthens will. David Walsh unravels how the two complement each other: ‘We do not have thoughts; it is rather thoughts that have us. Nietzsche’s own philosophical symbols must be read in this way as efforts to identify what lies beyond the boundary of consciousness because it provides the fecundity of what emerges in consciousness. The “will to power” is thus neither a will nor a power but the source of both.’ (Walsh: 2008, )

It is not will that roots that individual engagement with other wills but power. It is a power to evaluate wills and create new values and interpretations as well as action. Herd determined morality and values are principles imposed on life, not determined from it. They are weak and reactive rather than active and creative. The will to power affirms life and re-evaluates all value in terms of living experience. Different wills (or ‘forces’) are in constant conflict and can not simply be reduced to one aim or understanding. This is why there is no end to philosophical understanding and no system which can incorporate everything Philosophical evaluation of experience (which is an evaluation of wills) must also take into account the instincts, desires and passions of the evaluator.

Paras: 6 (philosophy as autobiography) 13 (the venting of strength) 19 (from ‘Willing seems to me…) 36(internal motivations for action: desire and passions), 43 (subjective interpretations of good – friend of truth, not owning truth), Derrida interprets this as follows: The friends of truth are without the truth, even if friends cannot function without truth. The truth – that of the thinkers to come – it is impossible to be it, to be there, to have it; one must only be its friend.’ (Derrida:2005, 43) 51 (the subversive ‘will to power’ of saints), 134 (truth of the sense) 187 (morality as sign language of the emotions), 259 (exploitation and using as primordial fact)

Bataille, G. (2008) On Nietzsche London: Continuum Deleuze, G. and Guattari, F. (2011) What is Philosophy London: Verso Deleuze, G. (2001) Pure Immanence New York: Zone Deleuze, G. (1983) Nietzsche and Philosophy London: Athlone Derrida, J. (2005) The Politics of Friendship London: Verso Llewelyn, J. (2009) Margins of Religion Bloomington: Indiana Unviersity Press Nietzsche, F. (2003) Beyond Good and Evil, London: Penguin Raffoul, F. (2010) The Origins of Responsibility Bloomington: Indiana University Press Walsh, D. (2008) The Modern Philosophical Revolution Cambridge: Cambridge University Press Winchester, J. (1994) Nietzsche’s Aesthetic Turn New York: SUNY Press