The Critique of Pure Reason (1781, 1787)

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Meditation IV God is not a Deceiver, Truth Criterion & Problem of Error.
Advertisements

Modern Philosophy PART FOUR. David Hume Background  General Background  Life & Writings  Other publications & career  Goals  Motivation  Goal.
Kant Career Köningsberg in East-Prussia Professor at the University Lutheran rationalist The categorical imperative One of the most influential.
The Concept of God and the Role of Ideas in Kant Charlotte Alderwick University of Sheffield
The Categorical Imperative
Moral Reasoning Making appropriate use of facts and opinions to decide the right thing to do Quotations from Jacob Needleman’s The American Soul A Crucial.
Seminar “Kant: Critique of the Power of Judgment” University of Iceland Session 2 19/9/2007 Text: Introduction (I-II) Claus Beisbart How the first two.
Kant’s Ethical Theory.
Computer Ethics PHILOSOPHICAL BELIEF SYSTEMS Chapter 1 Computer Ethics PHILOSOPHICAL BELIEF SYSTEMS Chapter 1 Hassan Ismail.
Newton and psychology Thanks to Newton, scientists and philosophers know that the world is controlled by absolute natural laws, so the inconsistencies.
Kant’s Transcendental Idealism according to Henry E. Allison Itzel Gonzalez Phil 4191 March 2, 2009.
Chapter 9 Kant’s Transcendental Idealism. How did Hume influence Kant? What is the distinction between the noumenal and the phenomenal worlds? What are.
Idealism.
Humanities March 2014 Enlightenment: Copernicus to Kant Matthew Gumpert.
Plato BC The Republic Updated, 10/3/07.
Kant, Transcendental Aesthetic
The Universalist: Immanuel Kant
Immanuel Kant Basic Kantian Terms A POSTERIORI (to come after in time): That which follows upon or depends upon sense experience; a knowledge.
Critique of Pure Reason Philosophy 1 Spring, 2002 G. J. Mattey.
KANT 1 IMMORALITY IS IRRATIONAL. Immanuel Kant Rationalist until age of 50, then read Hume, who, in his own words, “awakened me from my dogmatic.
 Derives from Greek words meaning Love of Wisdom.
CHAPTER FIVE: THE SOURCES OF KNOWLEDGE P H I L O S O P H Y A Text with Readings ELEVENTH EDITION M A N U E L V E L A S Q U E Z.
Parsing Categories of Belief Why Early Modern M&E divides belief into two types: Sensory & Mathematical.
More categories for our mental maps  How we understand knowledge has repercussions for how we understand our place in the world.  How we understand.
Why a third Critique? Seminar “Kant: Critique of the Power of Judgment” University of Iceland Session 1 18/9/2007 Text: Preface Claus Beisbart.
Epistemology Revision
Immanuel Kant Critique of Pure Reason. Historical Context Kant lived during the age of enlightenment The spirit of enlightenment (Aufklaerung): 1. Universalism:
Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason Preface B, Introductions A & B.
 According to philosophical skepticism, we can’t have knowledge of the external world.
9/18/2015 Modern Philosophy PHIL320 1 Kant I Charles Manekin.
© Michael Lacewing Reason and experience Michael Lacewing
Philosophy 1050: Introduction to Philosophy Week 10: Descartes and the Subject: The way of Ideas.
Archetypes of Wisdom Douglas J. Soccio Chapter 12: The Universalist: Immanuel Kant.
Chapter 3: Knowledge Kant’s Revolution Introducing Philosophy, 10th edition Robert C. Solomon, Kathleen Higgins, and Clancy Martin.
WHAT IS HIS DUTY? Duty - something that one is expected or required to do by moral or legal obligation. Your response:
© Michael Lacewing Hume and Kant Michael Lacewing co.uk.
The Turn to the Science The problem with substance dualism is that, given what we know about how the world works, it is hard to take it seriously as a.
David Hume ( ) An Inquiry Concerning Human Understanding Revised, 11/21/03.
11/26/2015 Modern Philosophy PHIL320 1 Kant III Charles Manekin.
Chapter 7 The Problem of Skepticism and Knowledge
An Inquiry Concerning Human Understanding
© Michael Lacewing Kant on conceptual schemes Michael Lacewing osophy.co.uk.
KANT ON THE SYNTHETIC A PRIORI
1/9/2016 Modern Philosophy PHIL320 1 Kant II Charles Manekin.
KNOWLEDGE IS A PRIORI AND A POSTERIORI By: Fatima Fuad Azeem.
L ECTURE 15: C ERTAINTY. T ODAY ’ S L ECTURE In Today’s Lecture we will: 1.Review Hume’s radical empiricism and its consequences 2.Outline and investigate.
Immanuel Kant and the moral law. Kant (1) Kant’s ethics are those of the deist, rather than the theist. He was an important thinker in the deist project,
An analysis of Kant’s argument against the Cartesian skeptic in his ‘Refutation of Idealism” Note: Audio links to youtube are found on my blog at matthewnevius.wordpress.com.
Immanuel Kant ( ) “ The Synthesizer ”. Synthesized Rationalism and Empiricism We learn through our senses, but we also must use reason to make.
BC The Republic is one of Plato’s longer works (more than 450 pages in length). It is written in dialogue form (as are most of Plato’s books),
Philosophy 224 Kant and Humans and Morality. Immanuel Kant Immanuel Kant ( ) was one of the most important philosophers of the modern era. His.
Standard Form ► 1. State your position ► 2. 1 st Premise (Fact 1: State fact and source) ► 3. 2 nd Premise (Fact 2: State fact and source) ► 4. 3 rd Premise.
KANT ON THE POSSIBILITY OF METAPHYSICS Text source: Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics, introduction.
Kant and the Role of Reason Two things fill me with constantly increasing admiration and awe, the longer and more earnestly I reflect on them: the starry.
Chapter 7: Ethics Morality and Practical Reason: Kant
Kant. The Good Will and Duty Kant did not believe that any outcome was inherently good. Pleasure or happiness could result out of the most evil acts.
Lesson Objective Key Words Lesson outcomes Hypothetical Categorical Imperatives Freedom To evaluate the differences between the Hypothetical and Categorical.
JUDGMENTS. Transcendental Aesthetic of Time “Time is not an empirical concept deduced from any experience, for neither co-existence nor succession would.
SEARCHING FOR BALANCE 1.
Natural Law What is beyond?. Who is he? Sapere Aude (Dare to be wise, dare to know) Born in 1724 in Konigsberg, Prusia (Kaliningrad) German philosopher.
From Pyrrhonian Skepticism to Justification for Belief.
The Search for Knowledge
Immanuel Kant ( ).
Philosophy of Mathematics 1: Geometry
Michael Lacewing Hume and Kant Michael Lacewing © Michael Lacewing.
Kant’s Categorical Imperative - revision
EXAM WEEK DATES THE FINAL EXAM IS 12 NOON, THURS 9th
Immanuel Kant A Compromise
Critique of Practical Reason [Kritik der reinen Vernunft]
Logic, A priori and A posteriori, Analytic and Synthetic.
Presentation transcript:

The Critique of Pure Reason (1781, 1787) 11/27/06 Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) The Critique of Pure Reason (1781, 1787) (Text, pp. 341-363)

Anthem

Topics covered in the reading The nature, scope, & limits of human knowledge a priori & a posteriori knowledge analytic & synthetic judgments synthetic a priori judgments & how they are possible phenomena, noumena, & the "transcendental ideas of pure reason" The transcendental ideas of pure reason: self, cosmos, & God Morality & metaphysics: freedom, immortality, & God

Introductory Note What is knowledge? Answer: Knowledge is verified ("justified") true belief. To know is to believe; the belief must be true (rather than false); and the belief must be verified ("justified"), i.e., proved true.

The Rationalist-Empiricist Dispute According to Kant, all knowledge begins with sense experience, but not all knowledge arises out of sense experience.

There are two basic types of human knowledge: a priori knowledge, which arises from the operations of the mind & is independent of sense experience a posteriori knowledge, which arises from & depends on sense experience; and

The distinguishing characteristics of pure a priori knowledge: Necessity and Strict universality (no possibility of an exception)

A priori judgments are necessarily & universally true (or false), whereas a posteriori (empirical) judgments are never necessarily or universally true (or false).* *They are contingently true (or false).

A further Kantian distinction Analytic Judgments vs. Synthetic Judgments

It's all about subjects & predicates

In an analytic judgment or proposition, the predicate makes explicit (explicates) meanings that are already implicit in the subject (e.g., "a triangle is three-sided").

In a synthetic judgment or proposition, the predicate adds to our knowledge of the subject in a way that logical analysis, by itself, cannot (e.g., "some houses are white"). The predicate of a synthetic proposition augments & amplifies our knowledge of the subject.

The relationships between analytic, synthetic, a priori, & a posteriori judgments

Analytic judgments express a priori knowledge, i. e Analytic judgments express a priori knowledge, i.e., they are necessarily & universally true (or false), & they can be verified or falsified independently of sense experience, i.e., by logical analysis alone. (There is no need to test them a posteriori.)

"Material objects are extended in space." This proposition is both analytic & a priori.

are always synthetic (e.g., "material objects have weight"). A posteriori judgments (which must be verified or falsified on the basis of sense experience, not through logical analysis) are always synthetic (e.g., "material objects have weight").

So . . . .

there are (uncontroversially) analytic a priori judgments, synthetic a posteriori judgments, and analytic a posteriori judgments (which are a waste of time, since analytic judgments can be verified or falsified by logical analysis alone). In addition to these, Kant claims . . . .

synthetic a priori judgments that there are synthetic a priori judgments (This is controversial!)

A synthetic a priori judgment is one that is necessarily & universally true (& thus not derived from sense experience, i.e., it is a priori) and in which the predicate adds something to our knowledge of the subject that could not be known merely by logical analysis of the subject.

Examples of synthetic a priori judgments (according to Kant) "Everything that happens has a cause." "7 + 5 = 12" "A straight line is the shortest distance between two points [in space]." "In all changes of the material world, the quantity of matter remains unchanged." "In all communication of motion, action and reaction must always be equal." "The world must have a beginning."

This leads to what Kant calls "the general problem of pure reason"

How are synthetic a priori judgments possible?

To this general question, Kant adds several subsidiary questions: "How is pure mathematical science possible?" "How is pure natural science [physics] possible?" "How is metaphysics as a natural disposition possible?" "How is metaphysics as a science possible?" (We will not at this time pursue answers to these questions.)

How are synthetic a priori judgments possible? Kant's solution of the general problem of pure reason How are synthetic a priori judgments possible?

Kant's "Copernican Revolution in Philosophy" The relationship between the mind & its objects Objects ? Mind

According to Kant, the mind does not conform to its objects. On the contrary, the objects of consciousness conform to the structure & operations of the mind itself.

The structure of the mind Pure Reason (Vernunft) Understanding (Verstand) Categories Sensibility (Sinnlichkeit) Categories of the Under- standing Forms of space & time Forms of Sensibility

Kant's overall view (Rational Belief) (Vernunft) Mind (Knowledge) Transcendental Ideas & Moral Postulates (Rational Belief) Noumena Reason (Vernunft) Objects of Consciousness Understanding (Verstand) Categories Phenomena Mind Sensibility (Sinnlichkeit) Forms of space & time (Knowledge)

Categories of the Understanding Of Quantity Unity (Singularity) Plurality (Particularity) Totality (Universality) Of Quality Affirmation Negation Limitation Of Relation Substance-Attribute Cause-&-Effect Community (Interaction) Of Modality Possibility-Impossibility Existence-Nonexistence Necessity-Contingency

The categories of the understanding are applicable only to phenomena that appear to us under the forms of sensibility (space & time); they have no legitimate application to noumena, i.e., realities or alleged realities that transcend the realm of space & time.

However, in an effort to construct a totally unified, coherent, & systematic world-view, human reason (Vernunft) thinks beyond the phenomenal realm and formulates ideas of realities (i.e., possible realities) that transcend the world of experience.

This takes us

rational belief from knowledge to The transcendental metaphysics of Pure Reason

The Transcendental Ideas of Pure Reason Self, Cosmos, & God

The content of the transcendental ideas

The Transcendental Idea of the Self a thinking substance (soul) simple & unchangeable has a personal identity that persists through time exists in relation to other real things outside it experiencer & thinker

The Transcendental Idea of the Cosmos (or world-in-general) a unified and infinitely long series of events the totality of all causal series

The Transcendental Idea of God  The primordial, single, self-subsistent, all-sufficient, supreme ground of being Supreme creative & purposive reason as the cause of the universe 

The Justification of the Transcendental Ideas They are the foundations for reason's construction & account of the systematic unity of experience.

The Idea of the Self enables reason to construe all of "my" subjective experiences as existing in a single subject (my "self"), all of "my" powers of perception & thought as derived from a single source (my "self"), all changes within "me" as belonging to the states of one & the same permanent being (my "self"), and all phenomena in space as entirely different from the activity of thought (i.e., as other than my "self").

In other words, the idea of the Self provides me with a metaphysical foundation for the unity of my experience.

The Idea of the Cosmos enables reason to think of the world as if it were a unified collection or totality of infinitely long causal series that can be endlessly investigated by science. In other words, the idea of the cosmos-as-a-whole is a stimulus to scientific inquiry.

The Idea of God enables reason to see nature as a system grounded in reason and pervaded with purpose since God is Supreme Reason aiming at the ultimate good of all things.

In other words, the idea that God (a supremely rational & purposive being) is the cause (creator) of the universe enables us to see the world as a teleological unity in which everything (absolutely every-thing) serves some purpose.

Kant seems to be saying that, unless we assume the existence of the Self (transcendental ego), the Cosmos-as-a-whole, & God, the world & our experience of the world will lack systematic unity & coherence. In other words, the world & our experience of the world cannot be completely intelligible (or meaningful) without the transcendental ideas of pure reason.

However . . . ,

the transcendental ideas are "regulative," not "constitutive." That is, they guide or "regulate" our study of the world by leading us to proceed AS IF the Self, the Cosmos-as-a-whole, & God are real. However, the objects of the transcendental ideas (Self, Cosmos, & God) do not "constitute" actual objects of experience; they are "merely" ideal objects, which, if real, add systematic unity & coherence to our experience of the phenomenal world.

But we cannot KNOW whether or not the Self, the Cosmos, & God are real because they are "transcendental" (noumenal) objects, i.e., they are not phenomena that appear in space & time & to which the categories of the understanding can be applied.

Morality, Happiness, & Metaphysics Freedom, Immortality, & God (The Postulates of Practical Reason)

Kant's distinction between theoretical reason (reasoning about the universe, the world of nature) and practical reason (reasoning about human existence & action)

As we have seen, Similarly . . . , pure reason (i.e., pure theoretical reason), in seeking to understand the universe as a whole, formulates certain "transcendental ideas" (of Self, Cosmos, & God). Similarly . . . ,

pure practical reason, in an effort to see human existence & human moral effort as meaningful, postulates the reality of moral freedom, the immortality of the soul, & the existence of God. (In the Critique of Practical Reason (1788), Kant calls freedom, immortality, & God "the postulates of practical reason.")

morality (the moral law) tells us what we OUGHT to do. Freedom of the Will According to Kant, morality (the moral law) tells us what we OUGHT to do. Thus, morality presupposes freedom of the will because, logically speaking, "ought" implies "can."

The existence & nature of the moral law In the Critique of Pure Reason, Kant assumes the existence of pure a priori moral laws that determine what we ought and ought not do. In his later works on ethical theory (see footnote on p. 358 in text), he seeks to deduce the moral law from the concept of moral duty (or obligation).

reason discerns a relationship between morality & happiness. According to Kant, reason discerns a relationship between morality & happiness. What is the nature of that relationship?

On this subject, there is a difference between the pragmatic law & the moral law. The pragmatic law answers the question, "What must I do in order to become happy?" The moral law answers the question, "What must I do in order to deserve (be worthy of) happiness?"

Moral laws are categorical imperatives, i.e., absolute & unconditional moral commands (e.g., "Be honest"); they are NOT hypothetical imperatives (e.g., "If you wish to have a good reputation, be honest").

In general, the moral law says, "Do that through which you become worthy of happiness."

Reason is not satisfied with morality all by itself, nor with happiness all by itself. In a completely good world, "a system in which happiness is tied and proportioned to morality [which makes one worthy of happiness] would be necessary."

"What . . . is the supreme good of the moral world that a pure but practical reason commands us to occupy?" "It is happiness in exact proportion to the moral worth of the rational beings who populate that world."

For such an ideal world to exist, two things are necessary: the existence of God; and the immortality of the soul. Only God can guarantee the ideal proportionality of morality & happiness. If happiness & unhappiness are to be necessary consequences of our conduct in the empirical world, then there must be a future world in which the soul lives on.

That’s all, folks!