PHIL/RS 335 Arguments for God’s Existence Pt. 1: The Cosmological Argument.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
The Cosmological Argument
Advertisements

Cosmological Argument What is it?. Cosmological Argument The simple starting point is that we know the universe exists (a posteriori) The simple starting.
Philosophy and the proof of God's existence
“… if (the best philosophy) doesn ’ t seem peculiar you haven ’ t understood it ” Edward Craig.
Aquinas’s First Way – highlights It’s impossible for something to put itself into motion. Therefore, anything in motion is put into motion by something.
The Cosmological Argument
Cosmological arguments for God’s existence.  Derived from the Greek terms cosmos (world or universe) and logos (reason or rational account).  First.
The Cosmological Proof Metaphysical Principles and Definitions Principle of Sufficient Reason (PSR): For every positive fact, whatsoever, there is a sufficient.
The Cosmological Argument. Aquinas’s Cosmological Argument Cosmological Argument is ‘a posteriori’ Attempts to prove the existence of God There are three.
The Cosmological Argument. Also known as ‘The First Cause Argument’ Unlike the Ontological Argument, it derives the conclusion from a posteriori premise.
The Cosmological Argument The idea that there is a first cause behind the existence of the universe.
Cosmological arguments from causation Michael Lacewing
The Cosmological Argument.
Cosmological arguments from contingency Michael Lacewing
History of Philosophy Lecture 12 Thomas Aquinas
Arguments for the existence of God. Ontological Argument Anselm.
The Cosmological Argument ► Aquinas presents the argument in three “ways” but the argument is a single one. ► First – All things are moved by something.
Why Does Anything at all Exist? Why is there something rather than nothing? Leibniz - the principle of sufficient reason.
1225 – 1274 (Aquinas notes created by Kevin Vallier) Dominican monk, born to Italian nobility. Worked ~150 years after Anselm. Student of Albert the Great.
Aquinas’ Proofs The five ways.
The Design Argument Introduction. This proof always deserves to be mentioned with respect. It is the oldest, clearest, and the most accordant with the.
The Problem of Evil: McCabe, “The Statement of the Problem”
The Teleological Proof A Posteriori Argument: A argument in which a key premise can only be known through experience of the actual world. Principle of.
Philosophy 224 Divine Persons: Broad on Personal Belief.
Evidently the Cosmological argument as proposed by Aquinas is open to both interpretation and criticism. The Cosmological argument demands an explanation.
THE EVIDENTIAL CHALLENGE: FLEW’S A-THEISM PHIL/RS 335.
Philosophy 224 Divine Persons Pt. 2. Legenhausen, “Is God a Person?” Legenhausen uses the little observed fact that Islam is a religion in which the majority.
CLARKE & ROWE (pp ) IS A NECESSARY BEING REALLY NECESSARY?
Why Does Anything at all Exist? Why is there something rather than nothing? Leibniz - the principle of sufficient reason.
An argument for the existence of God based on the nature of God’s being Saint Anselm ( CE) relied purely on reason … if we were to conceive of.
PHIL/RS 335 God’s Existence Pt. 1: The Ontological Argument.
LECTURE 19 THE COSMOLOGICAL ARGUMENT CONTINUED. THE QUANTUM MECHANICAL OBJECTION DEPENDS UPON A PARTICULAR INTERPRETATION WE MIGHT REASONABLY SUSPEND.
HUME ON THE COSMOLOGICAL ARGUMENT Text source: Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion, part 9.
The Cosmological Argument for God’s Existence or how come we all exist? Is there a rational basis for belief in God?
Anselm’s “1st” ontological argument Something than which nothing greater can be thought of cannot exist only as an idea in the mind because, in addition.
Cosmological Argument The Basics. Science can offer us explanations of things that are within the universe, but does the universe as a whole have an explanation?
PHIL/RS 335 Divine Nature Pt. 2: Divine Omniscience.
Phil/RS 335 God’s Existence Pt. 2: The Moral Argument.
LECTURE 18 THE COSMOLOGICAL ARGUMENT: ANOTHER ATTEMPT TO PROVE THAT SOME THING NECESSSARILY EXISTS.
Starter - Without your notes – define these terms – 15 mins Synthetic Posteriori Inductive Primary movers Secondary movers Ex nihilo nihil fit Actual infinites.
Chapter 1: The cosmological argument AQA Religious Studies: Philosophy of Religion AS Level © Nelson Thornes Ltd 2008 Revision.
Medieval Islamic Theology. Ibn Sina (Avicenna; )
The Cosmological Argument Today’s lesson will be successful if: You have revised the ideas surrounding the cosmological argument and the arguments from.
The Copleston, Russell Debate Copleston’s Cosmological argument (1948 BBC radio debate)
Lesson Aim To recall and explore other forms of the Cosmological Argument.
Aquinas’ Proofs The five ways. Thomas Aquinas ( ) Joined Dominican order against the wishes of his family; led peripatetic existence thereafter.
The Cosmological Argument
The Cosmological Argument for God’s Existence
Starter: Mix-Pair-Share
Cosmological arguments from contingency
Philosophy of Religion
c) Strengths and weaknesses of Cosmological Arguments:
Cosmological Argument
The Cosmological Argument
Cosmological Argument: Philosophical Criticisms
THE COSMOLOGICAL ARGUMENT.
Explore the use of inductive reasoning in the cosmological argument
Think pair share What type of argument is the cosmological argument?
Anselm & Aquinas December 23, 2005.
THE COSMOLOGICAL ARGUMENT.
Cosmological Argument Essay planning
1 A The Cosmological Argument Kalam Argument
The Cosmological Argument
Or Can you?.
Or Can you?.
THE COSMOLOGICAL ARGUMENT.
Philosophy of Religion Arguments for the existence of God
Science can offer us explanations of things that are within the universe, but does the universe as a whole have an explanation? Think, pair, share.
Assess the strengths of the cosmological argument. (12 marks)
‘Assess the credibility of the cosmological argument’ (12 marks)
Presentation transcript:

PHIL/RS 335 Arguments for God’s Existence Pt. 1: The Cosmological Argument

Going back to the beginning.  The cosmological argument has its origin in Ancient Greek Philosophy.  We see versions of the argument in the work of both Plato and Aristotle.  There, of course, the argument was not aimed at proving the existence of a theistic divinity, but at explaining the origin of the world.

The CA in the History of Philosophy  In the forms more familiar to us, the aim of the argument is proving the existence of the God of the traditional monotheisms.  Historically, there are two periods of particularly intense interest in the cosmological argument.  The first is in the 13 th century, due to the influence of Thomas Aquinas, whose first 3 proofs for the existence of God in the section of the text entitled “The Five Ways,” are various versions of the cosmological proof.  The second is in the 18 th century, when the work of two prominent advocates of the argument, Leibniz and Samuel Clarke was at the zenith of its influence.  Though there continue to be advocates of versions of the CA, most contemporary philosophical theists have voiced skepticism about the argument.

What is it?  As should already be apparent, the cosmological argument is really a family of arguments which share a basic structure.  Though there are significant variations which we will have to account for, the various versions of the CA begin with certain relatively non- controversial descriptions of the natural world and infer from them the existence of a necessary being, which they then argue must be understood as God.

Aquinas’s Five Ways  As already noted, only the first three arguments offered by Aquinas are versions of the cosmological argument. 1.Argument from Motion 2.Argument from Efficient Causality 3.Argument from the Existence of Contingent Beings  An examination of these three arguments reveals a common set of elements.  They are all a posteriori arguments, starting with observation and reasoning to conditions.  They all assume the impossibility of infinite regress.  Strictly speaking, they don’t quite get us to God, but rather, to what, “…everyone understands to be God.”

Evaluation of these elements.  The class of arguments we are calling a posteriori arguments are common and generally non-controversial, though they are most frequently developed as inductive, rather than deductive arguments.  The claim of the impossibility of infinite regress is much more controversial. Copleston, in the inset on p. 62, tries to rescue this claim by insisting that Aquinas’s assertion is an ontological rather than temporal or genetic claim, but set-theoretic mathematics provides the resources for serious reservations here.  The point of the last observation is to highlight that even if we grant the force of the arguments offered by Aquinas, we don’t seem to get the God of theism. We might get a first mover, a first efficient cause, or a necessary being, but not the loving, personal God which traditional theism is committed to.

A More Modern Version  Both Leibniz and Clarke combined an attempt to use the principle of sufficient reason to establish the existence of a self-existent being and then argue that such a being is best understood as the God of theism.  The first step in the argument can be summarized as follows. 1.Every being is either a dependent being or a self-existent being. 2.Not every being can be a dependent being. __________________________ Conclusion: There exists a self-existent being.  Definitions  Dependent Being: a being whose existence is accounted for by the causal activity of other things.  Self-Existent Being: a being whose existence is accounted for by its own nature (what the Yandell’s refer to as “existential security”).

Explanation of Premise 1  For Leibniz and Clarke (and the Yandells) the truth of the first premise is established by the Principle of Sufficient Reason.  The PSR is commonly formulated as “Everything has a reason,” though it can be formulated in a number of more specific ways (see 69c2). What does this mean? There are a number of possibilities.  There must be an explanation a)for the existence of any being; b)of any positive fact whatsoever (73c2); c)of the cosmic whole.

Explanation of Premise 2  There are two ways commonly employed to establish the second premise.  The first is Aquinas’s: there can be no infinite series.  The second is the assertion that there are no brute facts. That is, there has to be an explanation of why there is anything at all (82c1).  Consider the following causal chain A 1 —A 2 —A 3 —A n —A n+1  Relative to any A, the PSR is satisfied, but what about the chain as a whole?  Only the assertion of the second premise would seem to satisfy the PSR for the chain.

Criticisms of the 2 nd Premise  Makes a category mistake. Assumes that the series is of the same ontological order of the elements of the series.  Commits the Part/Whole Fallacy. All humans have mouths, but that doesn’t mean that the category “human being” has a mouth.  Hume, Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion, Pt. IX, “Did I show you the particular cause of each individual in a collection of twenty particles of matter, I should think it very unreasonable, should you afterwards ask me, what was the cause of the whole twenty. This is sufficiently explained in explaining the cause of the parts.”

Criticisms of Premise 1  Why should we accept the PSR?  Is it intuitively true? Does reason presuppose it? If an explanation seems possible, does that mean there is one (Yandells 76c1)?  Mackie identifies a number of arguments which call these justifications into question (79c2-81c2). 1.Contra Clarke, the PSR doesn’t seem to fit with what we know of human behavior. 2.What about the requirements of reason? Scientific inquiry (philosophical or otherwise) requires causal inquiry of the intra-series sort, but all such inquiry begins in posits, and these don’t seem to require the PSR. 3.What about purposiveness? We often desire that there be an absolute purpose, but surely thinking of our lives as purposeful doesn’t require an absolute purpose.  “We have no right to assume that the universe will comply with our intellectual preferences” (81c2).  See also the Rowe inset on p. 80.