Lecture 1: Instant Gratification

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
14.127BehavioralEconomics. Lecture 9 Xavier Gabaix April8, 2004.
Advertisements

Instant Gratification, Multiple Selves, & Self-Control: How to Control Your Selves David Laibson Harvard University November 2010.
Factor Markets: Introduction and Factor Demand
Decision Theory. Plan for today (ambitious) 1.Time inconsistency problem 2.Riskiness measures and gambling wealth  Riskiness measures – the idea and.
Copyright © 2002 by The McGraw-Hill Companies, Inc. All rights reserved. 6-1 CHAPTER 6 Building Blocks of the Flexible-Price Model.
PROCRASTINATION, PRESENT-BIASED PREFERENCES AND FINANCIAL BEHAVIORS Jeffrey R. Brown University of Illinois and NBER Alessandro Previtero Ivey Business.
1 The Psychology and Economics of Household Investment Decisions David Laibson Harvard University and NBER July 2008.
John Beshears James J. Choi Christopher Clayton Christopher Harris David Laibson Brigitte C. Madrian August 8, 2014.
Empirical evidence on quasi-hyperbolic discounting AEA, January 2010 David Laibson Harvard University and NBER or Laibson Lecture 1.
Behavioral Finance David Laibson Robert I. Goldman Professor of Economics Harvard College Professor Harvard University National Bureau of Economic Research.
Behavioral Economics and Aging David Laibson Harvard University and NBER July 8, 2009 RAND.
Chapter 22: TAXATION AND SAVINGS – THEORY AND EVIDENCE
Behavioral Economics Udayan Roy ECO54 History of Economic Thought.
Can We Control Our Selves? David Laibson Robert I. Goldman Professor of Economics Harvard University March 27, 2013.
Intertemporal Choice Applications and Behavioral Mechanism Design July 1, 2014 David Laibson Harvard University and NBER or.
Sample XYZ Company Employee 401(k) Retirement Plan Transamerica Insurance & Investments.
Expectations and our IS-LM model In this lecture we will examine how expectations about the future will impact investment and consumption today. We will.
Finance, Financial Markets, and NPV
Labor Supply over Time Labor Supply over Time We make labor supply decisions continuously over the life cycle, and our current decisions influence economic.
23 © 2004 Prentice Hall Business PublishingPrinciples of Economics, 7/eKarl Case, Ray Fair Money Demand, the Equilibrium Interest Rate, and Monetary Policy.
L9: Consumption, Saving, and Investments 1 Lecture 9: Consumption, Saving, and Investments The following topics will be covered: –Consumption and Saving.
11 © 2004 Prentice Hall Business PublishingPrinciples of Economics, 7/eKarl Case, Ray Fair Money Demand, the Equilibrium Interest Rate, and Monetary Policy.
Two Papers on Intertemporal Choice and Self Control SS200 - Meghana Bhatt.
Lecture 3 Labor Supply over Time We make labor supply decisions continuously over the life cycle, and our current decisions influence economic opportunities.
Macroeconomics fifth edition N. Gregory Mankiw PowerPoint ® Slides by Ron Cronovich macro © 2002 Worth Publishers, all rights reserved CHAPTER SIXTEEN.
Exchange Rate “Fundamentals” FIN 40500: International Finance.
What You Need to Know to Help Maximize Your Retirement Income.
Behavioral Finance: Investment mistakes and solutions David Laibson Professor of Economics Harvard University National Bureau of Economic Research June,
David Laibson Robert I. Goldman Professor of Economics Harvard University Behavioral Economics and Behavior Change Second National Summit on Pension Reform.
Making the Most of Your District’s 403(b) Plan. General Information Only Please be aware that this information is intended to be general in nature and.
Your Retirement Your Retirement: Plan Today. Play Tomorrow About this presentation: This presentation includes the following plan: FedEx Kinko’s.
The Impact of Behavioral Economics on Investor Decision-Making.
Save More Tomorrow Nudge, Chapter 6 Behavioral Economics Udayan Roy.
The Age of Reason: Financial Decisions Over the Lifecycle Sumit Agarwal Federal Reserve Bank of Chicago John Driscoll Federal Reserve Board Xavier Gabaix.
CHAPTER 16 Consumption slide 0 Class Slides for EC 204 To Accompany Chapter 16.
Macroeconomics fifth edition N. Gregory Mankiw PowerPoint ® Slides by Ron Cronovich macro © 2002 Worth Publishers, all rights reserved Topic 13: Consumption.
The Economics and Neuroeconomics of Instant Gratification Canadian Economic Association “State of the Art Lecture” David Laibson Harvard University and.
2013 Retirement Confidence Survey Mathew Greenwald Mathew Greenwald & Associates Presented to American Savings Education Council Washington, DC April 10,
Getting More From Retirement Savings Programs Alexander Gelber Harvard University and NBER May 19, 2009.
401(k)’s can partially solve two more public policy problems Brookings Institution September 18, 2015 John Beshears, Harvard Business School James Choi,
Copyright © 2001 by The McGraw-Hill Companies, Inc. All rights reserved. Slide Stabilizing Aggregate Demand: The Role of the Fed.
Chapter 6 Investment Decision Rules
The Fundamentals of Investing
Chapter 10 Choices Involving Time Copyright © 2014 McGraw-Hill Education. All rights reserved. No reproduction or distribution without the prior written.
$100 Dollar Bills on the Sidewalk: Sub Optimal Savings in 401(k) Plans (Choi et al., 2005) Presented By Sylvia Sirivar and Ruth Gbor.
Fertility and Time Inconsistency Matthias Wrede RWTH Aachen University (presented by Jessica Schuring)
1 Fiscal Policy. The overall federal budget Deficit 2.
The Economics of Instant Gratification NIH Behavior Change Conference David Laibson Harvard University and NBER June 15-16, 2009 Bethesda, Maryland.
Behavioral biases and heuristics: a primer
Optimal Defaults David Laibson Harvard University July, 2008.
Capital, Investment, and DepreciationCapitalInvestment and DepreciationThe Capital MarketCapital Income: Interest and ProfitsFinancial Markets in ActionCapital.
Lecture 3 Consumption. John M. Keynes: Absolute Income Hypothesis Consumption is a linear function of disposable personal income, C = C + cY C = consumption.
Who is easier to nudge? John Beshears James J. Choi David Laibson Brigitte C. Madrian Sean (Yixiang) Wang.
Please be aware that this information is intended to be general in nature and is not intended to be legal or tax advice. Each of you should follow up.
Section 5. What You Will Learn in this Module Illustrate the relationship between the demand for money and the interest rate with a graph Explain why.
Is There Evidence Workers Are Rational in Preparing for Retirement? by Gary Burtless Senior Fellow and Whitehead Chair in Economics The Brookings Institution.
Policy Applications of Psychology and Economics Professor Sendhil Mullainathan Fall 2006.
12 Automatic enrolment myths & truths This guide to automatic myths and truths contains some of the misconceptions we have come across when speaking to.
Economics of Savings. Achieve Financial Goals? Spend less than you receive. Two ways: Receive more  Spend less.
Optimal illiquidity John Beshears James J. Choi Christopher Clayton
Intertemporal Choice Empirics
Revolutionizing Global Leadership
Procrastination and Impatience
Frames, Defaults, and Nudges with Applications to Household Finance
Intertemporal Choice - SS200 Behavioural Economics
David Laibson Harvard University January, 2010 AEA Mini-course
How are preferences revealed?
How Are Preferences Revealed? Beshears, Choi, Laibson, Madrian (2008)
Personal Finance Retirement Planning – 1 Employer Plans
Presentation transcript:

Lecture 1: Instant Gratification David Laibson Harvard University and NBER July 13, 2009 Mannheim Summer School

1. Motivating Experiments A Thought Experiment Would you like to have 15 minute massage now or B) 20 minute massage in an hour C) 15 minute massage in a week D) 20 minute massage in a week and an hour

Read and van Leeuwen (1998) Choosing Today Eating Next Week Time If you were deciding today, would you choose fruit or chocolate for next week?

Patient choices for the future: Choosing Today Eating Next Week Time Today, subjects typically choose fruit for next week. 74% choose fruit

Impatient choices for today: Choosing and Eating Simultaneously Time If you were deciding today, would you choose fruit or chocolate for today?

Time Inconsistent Preferences: Choosing and Eating Simultaneously Time 70% choose chocolate

Read, Loewenstein & Kalyanaraman (1999) Choose among 24 movie videos Some are “low brow”: Four Weddings and a Funeral Some are “high brow”: Schindler’s List Picking for tonight: 66% of subjects choose low brow. Picking for next Wednesday: 37% choose low brow. Picking for second Wednesday: 29% choose low brow. Tonight I want to have fun… next week I want things that are good for me.

Extremely thirsty subjects McClure, Ericson, Laibson, Loewenstein and Cohen (2007) Choosing between, juice now or 2x juice in 5 minutes 60% of subjects choose first option. Choosing between juice in 20 minutes or 2x juice in 25 minutes 30% of subjects choose first option. We estimate that the 5-minute discount rate is 50% and the “long-run” discount rate is 0%. Ramsey (1930s), Strotz (1950s), & Herrnstein (1960s) were the first to understand that discount rates are higher in the short run than in the long run.

Self-regulation Ariely and Wertenbroch (2002) Three proofreading tasks: "Sexual identity is intrinsically impossible," says Foucault; however, according to de Selby[1], it is not so much sexual identity that is intrinsically impossible, but rather the dialectic, and some would say the satsis, of sexual identity. Thus, D'Erlette[2] holds that we have to choose between premodern dialectic theory and subcultural feminism imputing the role of the observer as poet. Evenly spaced deadlines. [$20 earnings] Self-imposed deadlines -- subjects can adopt costly deadlines ($1/day) and most did so. [$13 earnings] End deadline. [$5 earnings]

Conceptual Outline First lecture People are not internally consistent decision-makers Internal conflicts can be modeled and measured Scalable, inexpensive policies can transform behavior Second lecture: Early understanding of neural foundations

Detailed Outline For Lecture 1 Motivating experimental evidence Theoretical framework Field evidence Policy A copy of these slides will soon be available on my Harvard website.

2. Theoretical Framework Classical functional form: exponential functions. D(t) = dt D(t) = 1, d, d2, d3, ... Ut = ut + d ut+1 + d2 ut+2 + d3 ut+3 + ... But exponential function does not show instant gratification effect. Discount function declines at a constant rate. Discount function does not decline more quickly in the short-run than in the long-run.

Constant rate of decline -D'(t)/D(t) = rate of decline of a discount function

Slow rate of decline in long run Rapid rate of decline in short run

An exponential discounting paradox. Suppose people discount at least 1% between today and tomorrow. Suppose their discount functions were exponential. Then 100 utils in t years are worth 100*e(-0.01)*365*t utils today. What is 100 today worth today? 100.00 What is 100 in a year worth today? 2.55 What is 100 in two years worth today? 0.07 What is 100 in three years worth today? 0.00

An Alternative Functional Form Quasi-hyperbolic discounting (Phelps and Pollak 1968, Laibson 1997) D(t) = 1, bd, bd2, bd3, ... Ut = ut + bdut+1 + bd2ut+2 + bd3ut+3 + ... Ut = ut + b [dut+1 + d2ut+2 + d3ut+3 + ...] b uniformly discounts all future periods. exponentially discounts all future periods. For continuous time: see Barro (2001), Luttmer and Marriotti (2003), and Harris and Laibson (2009)

Ut = ut + ½ [ut+1 + ut+2 + ut+3 + ...] Building intuition To build intuition, assume that b = ½ and d = 1. Discounted utility function becomes Ut = ut + ½ [ut+1 + ut+2 + ut+3 + ...] Discounted utility from the perspective of time t+1. Ut+1 = ut+1 + ½ [ut+2 + ut+3 + ...] Discount function reflects dynamic inconsistency: preferences held at date t do not agree with preferences held at date t+1.

Application to massages b = ½ and d = 1 NPV in current minutes 15 minutes now 10 minutes now 7.5 minutes now A 15 minutes now B 20 minutes in 1 hour C 15 minutes in 1 week D 20 minutes in 1 week plus 1 hour

Application to massages b = ½ and d = 1 NPV in current minutes 15 minutes now 10 minutes now 7.5 minutes now A 15 minutes now B 20 minutes in 1 hour C 15 minutes in 1 week D 20 minutes in 1 week plus 1 hour

Exercise Assume that b = ½ and d = 1. Suppose exercise (current effort 6) generates delayed benefits (health improvement 8). Will you exercise? Exercise Today: -6 + ½ [8] = -2 Exercise Tomorrow: 0 + ½ [-6 + 8] = +1 Agent would like to relax today and exercise tomorrow. Agent won’t follow through without commitment.

Beliefs about the future? Sophisticates: know that their plans to be patient tomorrow won’t pan out (Strotz, 1957). “I won’t quit smoking next week, though I would like to do so.” Naifs: mistakenly believe that their plans to be patient will be perfectly carried out (Strotz, 1957). Think that β=1 in the future. “I will quit smoking next week, though I’ve failed to do so every week for five years.” Partial naifs: mistakenly believe that β=β* in the future where β < β* < 1 (O’Donoghue and Rabin, 2001).

Example 1. A model of procrastination Carroll et al (2009) Agent needs to do a task (once). For example, switch to a lower cost cell phone. Until task is done, agent losses θ units per period. Doing task costs c units of effort now. Think of c as opportunity cost of time Each period c is drawn from a uniform distribution on [0,1]. Agent has quasi-hyperbolic discount function with β < 1 and δ = 1. So weighting function is: 1, β, β, β, … Agent has sophisticated (rational) forecast of her own future behavior. She knows that next period, she will again have the weighting function 1, β, β, β, …

Timing of game Period begins (assume task not yet done) Pay cost θ (since task not yet done) Observe current value of opportunity cost c (drawn from uniform) Do task this period or choose to delay again. It task is done, game ends. If task remains undone, next period starts. Pay cost θ Observe current value of c Do task or delay again Period t-1 Period t Period t+1

Sophisticated procrastination There are many equilibria of this game. Let’s study the equilibrium in which sophisticates act whenever c < c*. We need to solve for c*. This is sometimes called the action threshold. Let V represent the expected undiscounted cost if the agent decides not to do the task at the end of the current period t: Likelihood of doing it in t+1 Likelihood of not doing it in t+1 Cost you’ll pay for certain in t+1, since job not yet done Expected cost conditional on drawing a low enough c* so that you do it in t+1 Expected cost starting in t+2 if project was not done in t+1

In equilibrium, the sophisticate needs to be exactly indifferent between acting now and waiting. Solving for c*, we find: So expected delay is:

How does introducing β<1 change the expected delay time? If β=2/3, then the delay time is scaled up by a factor of

Example 2. A model of procrastination: naifs Same assumptions as before, but… Agent has naive forecasts of her own future behavior. She thinks that future selves will act as if β = 1. So she (falsely) thinks that future selves will pick an action threshold of

In equilibrium, the naif needs to be exactly indifferent between acting now and waiting. To solve for V, recall that:

Substituting in for V: So the naif uses an action threshold (today) of But anticipates that in the future, she will use a higher threshold of

So her (naïve) forecast of delay is: And her actual delay will be: Her actual delay time exceeds her predicted delay time by the factor of 1/β.

3. Field Evidence Della Vigna and Malmendier (2004, 2006) Average cost of gym membership: $75 per month Average number of visits: 4 Average cost per vist: $19 Cost of “pay per visit”: $10

Choi, Laibson, Madrian, Metrick (2002) Self-reports about undersaving. Survey Mailed to 590 employees (random sample) Matched to administrative data on actual savings behavior

Typical breakdown among 100 employees Out of every 100 surveyed employees 68 self-report saving too little 24 plan to raise savings rate in next 2 months 3 actually follow through

Laibson, Repetto, and Tobacman (2007) Use MSM to estimate discounting parameters: Substantial illiquid retirement wealth: W/Y = 3.9. Extensive credit card borrowing: 68% didn’t pay their credit card in full last month Average credit card interest rate is 14% Credit card debt averages 13% of annual income Consumption-income comovement: Marginal Propensity to Consume = 0.23 (i.e. consumption tracks income)

LRT Simulation Model Stochastic Income Lifecycle variation in labor supply (e.g. retirement) Social Security system Life-cycle variation in household dependents Bequests Illiquid asset Liquid asset Credit card debt Numerical solution (backwards induction) of 90 period lifecycle problem.

Ut = ut + b [dut+1 + d2ut+2 + d3ut+3 + ...] LRT Results: Ut = ut + b [dut+1 + d2ut+2 + d3ut+3 + ...] b = 0.70 (s.e. 0.11) d = 0.96 (s.e. 0.01) Null hypothesis of b = 1 rejected (t-stat of 3). Specification test accepted. Moments: Empirical Simulated (Hyperbolic) %Visa: 68% 63% Visa/Y: 13% 17% MPC: 23% 31% f(W/Y): 2.6 2.7

Kaur, Kremer, and Mullainathan (2009): Compare two piece-rate contracts: Linear piece-rate contract (“Control contract”) Earn w per unit produced Linear piece-rate contract with penalty if worker does not achieve production target T (“Commitment contract”) Earn w for each unit produced if production>=T, earn w/2 for each unit produced if production<T T Earnings Production Consider an employee working on a simple piece rate activity – like a repetitive task done many times Many examples like this: supermarket checkout / cashier, assembly line worker, delivery person, salesperson, data entry operator, just to name a few. Compare 2 types of contracts the employee could be offered: Give the employee wage w for every unit of work that she does (blue line on the graph) Give the employee w if she meets some production target T, give her w/2 if she falls below target (red line on the graph) - Notice the employee can never earn more under the commitment contract, and may earn much less if she fails to meet target Never earn more under commitment contract May earn much less

Kaur, Kremer, and Mullainathan (2009): Demand for Commitment (non-paydays) Commitment contract (Target>0) chosen 39% of the time Workers are 11 percentage points more likely to choose commitment contract the evening before Effect on Production (non-paydays) Being offered contract choice increases average production by 5 percentage points relative to control Implies 13 percentage point productivity increase for those that actually take up commitment contract No effects on quality of output (accuracy) Payday Effects (behavior on paydays) Workers 21 percentage points more likely to choose commitment (Target>0) morning of payday Production is 5 percentage points higher on paydays These are coefficient estimates from regressions with controls Demand for commitment regression – evening/morning inference: chose_commitment = const + eve_choice_dummy + lag_prodn + lag_prodn*eve_choice + {controls including FE for employees, day of week, week #} Effect on production regression – effect on output: production = const + choice_dummy + lag_prodn + lag_prodn*choice + {controls including FE for employees, day of week, week #} Payday results: Overall, there is not a huge difference in average demand for commitment contracts on paydays vs non-paydays. However, there is a big difference in the likelihood of picking in the morning/evening on paydays vs. non-paydays. Basically, on non-paydays, people are more likely to choose commitment in advance (i.e. the evening before). However, the opposite is true on paydays – if people know Tuesday is their payday, they are much more likely to choose a commitment contract for Tuesday on Tuesday morning than on Monday evening.

Some other field evidence Ashraf and Karlan (2004): commitment savings Della Vigna and Paserman (2005): job search Duflo (2009): immunization Duflo, Kremer, Robinson (2009): commitment fertilizer Karlan and Zinman (2009): commitment to stop smoking Milkman et al (2008): video rentals return sequencing Oster and Scott-Morton (2005): magazine marketing/sales Sapienza and Zingales (2008,2009): procrastination Shapiro (????); monthly food stamp cycle Thornton (2005): HIV testing Trope & Fischbach (2000): commitment to medical adherence Wertenbroch (1998): individual packaging

Small immediate rewards: Thornton (2005) Dollar reward for picking up results

Small immediate costs: Thornton (2005) Fraction picking up info on HIV status Randomized distance (miles) to pick up info

Outline Experimental evidence for dynamic inconsistency. Theoretical framework: quasi-hyperbolic discounting. Field evidence: dynamic decisions. Policy and interventions

4. Policy Defaults in the savings domain Welcome to the company If you don’t do anything You are automatically enrolled in the 401(k) You save 2% of your pay Your contributions go into a default fund Call this phone number to opt out of enrollment or change your investment allocations

Madrian and Shea (2001) Choi, Laibson, Madrian, Metrick (2004) Automatic enrollment Standard enrollment

Fraction of Participants at different contribution rates: Employees enrolled under automatic enrollment cluster at default contribution rate. Fraction of Participants at different contribution rates: Default contribution rate under automatic enrollment

Participants stay at the automatic enrollment defaults for a long time. Fraction of Participants Hired Under Automatic Enrollment who are still at both Default Contribution Rate and Asset Allocation Company B Company C Company D Fraction of Participants Tenure at Company (Months)

Do people like a little paternalism? Survey given to workers who were subject to automatic enrollment: “You are glad your company offers automatic enrollment.” Agree? Disagree? Enrolled employees: 98% agree Non-enrolled employees: 79% agree All employees: 97% agree Source: Harris Interactive Inc.

The power of deadlines: Active decisions Carroll, Choi, Laibson, Madrian, Metrick (2004) Active decision mechanisms require employees to make an active choice about 401(k) participation. Welcome to the company You are required to submit this form within 30 days of hire, regardless of your 401(k) participation choice If you don’t want to participate, indicate that decision If you want to participate, indicate your contribution rate and asset allocation Being passive is not an option

Active Decision Cohort Standard enrollment cohort

Simplified enrollment raises participation Beshears, Choi, Laibson, Madrian (2006) 2005 2004 2003

Extensions to health domain Use automaticity and deadlines to nudge people to make better health decisions One early example: Home delivery of chronic meds (e.g. maintenance drugs for diabetes and CVD) Pharmaceutical adherence is about 50% One problem: need to pick up your meds Idea: use active decision intervention to encourage workers on chronic meds to consider home delivery Early results: HD take up rises from 14% to 38%

Cost saving at test company (preliminary estimates) Rxs at Mail (annualized) Annualized Savings Plan $2,413,641 Members $1,872,263 Total Savings $4,285,904 Now need to measure effects on health.

Policy Debates Pension Protection Act (2006) Federal Thrift Savings Plan adopts autoenrollment (2009) Auto-IRA mandate (2009?) Consumer Financial Protection Agency (2009?) Default/privileged plain vanilla financial products Disclosure Simplicity Transparency Education

$100 bills on the sidewalk Choi, Laibson, Madrian (2004) Employer 401(k) match is an instantaneous, riskless return Particularly appealing if you are over 59½ years old Can withdraw money from 401(k) without penalty On average, half of employees over 59½ years old are not fully exploiting their employer match Educational intervention has no effect

Education and Disclosure Choi, Laibson, Madrian (2007) Experimental study with 400 subjects Subjects are Harvard staff members Subjects read prospectuses of four S&P 500 index funds Subjects allocate $10,000 across the four index funds Subjects get to keep their gains net of fees

Data from Harvard Staff Control Treatment Fees salient $518 $494 Fees from random allocation $431 3% of Harvard staff in Control Treatment put all $$$ in low-cost fund

Data from Harvard Staff Control Treatment Fees salient $518 $494 Fees from random allocation $431 3% of Harvard staff in Control Treatment put all $$$ in low-cost fund 9% of Harvard staff in Fee Treatment put all $$$ in low-cost fund

Outline Motivating experimental evidence Theoretical framework Field evidence Policy applications A copy of these slides will soon be available on my Harvard website.