The Meaning of Part Stefan Schulz Department of Medical Informatics University Hospital Freiburg (Germany) Ontology and Biomedical Informatics An International.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Enhancing GO for the sake of clinical bionformatics Anand Kumar IFOMIS, University of Leipzig/Saarbrücken.
Advertisements

Complex Occurrents in Clinical Terminologies Stefan Schulz, Kornél Markó Department of Medical Informatics, Freiburg University Hospital, Germany Boontawee.
The Ontology of the Radiographic Image: From RadLex to RadiO.
Relations in Anatomy and Image Ontologies Dirk Marwede Institute for Formal Ontology and Medical Information Science, Saarland University, Saarbruecken,
Temporally qualified continuants for BFO 2 OWL A bottom-up view Stefan Schulz, Janna Hastings, Fabian Neuhaus May 20, 2013 (updated)
Temporally qualified continuants for BFO 2 OWL A bottom-up view Stefan Schulz, Janna Hastings, Fabian Neuhaus Freiburg, 10 Oct 2013.
Temporally qualified continuants for BFO 2 OWL A bottom-up view Stefan Schulz, Janna Hastings July 10, 2013.
ECO R European Centre for Ontological Research Ontology-based Error Detection in SNOMED-CT ® Werner Ceusters European Centre for Ontological Research Universität.
Anatomical boundaries and immaterial objects Stefan Schulz Department of Medical Informatics University Hospital Freiburg (Germany)
Criteria for distinguishing parthood from spatial inclusion in biological objects Stefan Schulz, Philipp Daumke Department of Medical Informatics University.
A Description Logics Approach to Clinical Guidelines and Protocols Stefan Schulz Department of Med. Informatics Freiburg University Hospital Germany Udo.
Representing Part Relationships Between Developing Structures.
SNOMED CT’s Ontological Commitment Stefan Schulz University Medical Center, Freiburg, Germany Ronald Cornet Academic Medical Center, Amsterdam, The Netherlands.
Stefan Schulz Language and Information Engineering (JULIE) Lab, Jena University, Germany Representing Natural Kinds by Spatial Inclusion and Containment.
Towards a Computational Paradigm for Biological Structure Stefan Schulz Department of Medical Informatics University Hospital Freiburg (Germany) Udo Hahn.
Criteria for distinguishing parthood from spatial inclusion in biological objects Stefan Schulz, Philipp Daumke Department of Medical Informatics University.
1 An Ontology of Relations for Biomedical Informatics Barry Smith 10 January 2005.
The Role of Foundational Relations in the Alignment of Biomedical Ontologies Barry Smith and Cornelius Rosse.
1 Beyond Concepts Barry Smith
1 Ontology in 15 Minutes Barry Smith. 2 Main obstacle to integrating genetic and EHR data No facility for dealing with time and instances (particulars)
FMA: a domain reference ontology Comments on Cornelius Rosse’s talk Anita Burgun WG6 meeting, Rome 29 Apr- 2 May 2005.
The Meaning of Part (Discussion) Anand Kumar MBBS, PhD IFOMIS, Department of Medicine, Univ. of Saarland, Germany. BIOMEDICALONTOLOGYBIOMEDICALONTOLOGY.
1 Logical Tools and Theories in Contemporary Bioinformatics Barry Smith
A taxonomy of granular partitions Thomas Bittner and Barry Smith Northwestern University, NCGIA and SUNY Buffalo.
VT. From Basic Formal Ontology to Medicine Barry Smith and Anand Kumar.
Anatomical Information Science Barry Smith
1 The OBO Relation Ontology Genome Biology 2005, 6:R46 based on the fundamental distinction between instances and universals takes instances and time into.
GOL A General Ontological Language Barry Smith Heinrich Herre Barbara Heller.
1 SNAP and SPAN Barry Smith and Pierre Grenon University at Buffalo and Institute for Formal Ontology and Medical Information Science (ifomis.de) University.
A taxonomy of granular partitions Thomas Bittner and Barry Smith Northwestern University, NCGIA and SUNY Buffalo.
A Formal Theory for Spatial Representation and Reasoning in Biomedical Ontologies Maureen Donnelly Thomas Bittner.
Ontological Foundations for Biomedical Sciences Stefan Schulz, Kornél Markó, Udo Hahn Workshop on Ontologies and their Applications, September 28, 2004,
Reference Ontologies, Application Ontologies, Terminology Ontologies Barry Smith
Some comments on Granularity Scale & Collectivity by Rector & Rogers Thomas Bittner IFOMIS Saarbruecken.
Temporally qualified continuants for BFO 2 OWL A bottom-up view Stefan Schulz, Janna Hastings, Fabian Neuhaus July 10, 2013.
Ontology-based Convergence of Medical Terminologies: SNOMED CT and ICD-11 Institute for Medical Informatics, Statistics and Documentation, Medical University.
Semantic Relations in the Environmental Domain Gerhard Budin.
Standardization of Anatomy Parts and Wholes – From Function to Location Stefan Schulz Department of Medical Informatics University Hospital Freiburg (Germany)
The Foundational Model of Anatomy and its Ontological Commitment(s) Stefan Schulz University Medical Center, Freiburg, Germany FMA in OWL meeting November.
Stefan Schulz Medical Informatics Research Group
The ICPS process: Typology of a novel terminological system Stefan SCHULZ IMBI, University Medical Center, Freiburg, Germany Daniel KARLSSON Department.
Core 6 (University at Buffalo) Dissemination of Ontology Best Practices Barry Smith (PI) Fabian Neuhaus (Post-Doc) Werner.
A CompuGroup Software GmbH, Koblenz, Germany b IMBI, University Medical Center Freiburg, Germany c Semfinder AG, Kreuzlingen, Switzerland d OntoMed Research.
American Medical Informatics Association Annual Symposium 2001 The Role of Definitions in Biomedical Concept Representation Joshua Michael, José L. V.
Ontological Foundations of Biological Continuants Stefan Schulz, Udo Hahn Text Knowledge Engineering Lab University of Jena (Germany) Department of Medical.
Semantic Clarification of the Representation of Procedures and Diseases in SNOMED CT Stefan Schulz Medical Informatics, Freiburg University Hospital (Germany)
Ontological Analysis, Ontological Commitment, and Epistemic Contexts Stefan Schulz WHO – IHTSDO Joint Advisory Group First Face-to-Face Meeting Heathrow,
The ICPS: A taxonomy, a classification, an ontology or an information model? Stefan SCHULZ IMBI, University Medical Center, Freiburg, Germany.
The ICPS: A taxonomy, a classification, an ontology or an information model? Stefan SCHULZ IMBI, University Medical Center, Freiburg, Germany.
Sharing Ontologies in the Biomedical Domain Alexa T. McCray National Library of Medicine National Institutes of Health Department of Health & Human Services.
How to Distinguish Parthood from Location in Bio-Ontologies Stefan Schulz a,b, Philipp Daumke a, Barry Smith c,d, Udo Hahn e a Department of Medical Informatics,
How much formality do we need ? Stefan Schulz MedInfo 2007 Workshop: MedSemWeb 2007 What Semantics Do We Need for A Semantic Web for Medicine? University.
Basic Formal Ontology Barry Smith August 26, 2013.
New York State Center of Excellence in Bioinformatics & Life Sciences R T U New York State Center of Excellence in Bioinformatics & Life Sciences R T U.
New York State Center of Excellence in Bioinformatics & Life Sciences R T U New York State Center of Excellence in Bioinformatics & Life Sciences R T U.
Stefan Schulz, Martin Boeker, Holger Stenzhorn: How Granularity Issues Concern Biomedical Ontology Integration Stefan Schulz, Martin Boeker, Holger Stenzhorn.
New York State Center of Excellence in Bioinformatics & Life Sciences R T U Discovery Seminar /UE 141 MMM – Spring 2008 Solving Crimes using Referent.
1 The Future of (Biomedical) Ontology: Overcoming Obstacles to Information Integration Barry Smith (IFOMIS) Manchester
Anatomy redesign statistics
Towards a Computational Paradigm for Biological Structure
Text Knowledge Engineering Lab University of Jena (Germany)
Representing Natural Kinds by Spatial Inclusion and Containment
Ontological Foundations for Biomedical Sciences
A Description Logics Approach to Clinical Guidelines and Protocols
Stefan SCHULZ IMBI, University Medical Center, Freiburg, Germany
Michael Lacewing Physicalism Michael Lacewing
Stefan Schulz, Philipp Daumke
Standardization of Anatomy Parts and Wholes – From Function to Location Stefan Schulz Department of Medical Informatics University Hospital Freiburg (Germany)
Standardization of Anatomy Parts and Wholes – From Function to Location Stefan Schulz Department of Medical Informatics University Hospital Freiburg (Germany)
The Foundational Model of Anatomy
Presentation transcript:

The Meaning of Part Stefan Schulz Department of Medical Informatics University Hospital Freiburg (Germany) Ontology and Biomedical Informatics An International Conference organized by the Network of Excellence Semantic Interoperability and Data Mining in Biomedicine under the auspices of Working Group 6 of the International Medical Informatics Association Rome 29 April – 2 May 2005

Relations in Biomedical Terminologies / Ontologies Purpose- Specific Relations in Clinical Terminologies Foundational Relations in Formal Ontologies Part-Of

Individuals Part-Of Algebraic Properties: Part-of : Transitive, Reflexive, Antisymmetric Proper-Part-Of :Transitive, Irreflexive, Asymmetric Mereological Principles: Sum, Product, Supplementation, Extensionality, Proper Part Principle… P.Simons, Casati & Varzi Subrelations: direct-part-of, functional-part-of, component-of, subdivision-of, boundary-of, … GALEN, FMA

Individuals Part-Of Algebraic Properties: Part-of : Transitive, Reflexive, Antisymmetric Proper-Part-Of :Transitive, Irreflexive, Asymmetric Mereological Principles: Sum, Product, Supplementation, Extensionality, Proper Part Principle… P.Simons, Casati & Varzi Subrelations: direct-part-of, functional-part-of, component-of, subdivision-of, boundary-of, … GALEN, FMA Continuants Occurrents

Algebraic Properties: Part-of : Transitive, Reflexive, Antisymmetric Proper-Part-Of :Transitive, Irreflexive, Asymmetric Mereological Principles: Sum, Product, Supplementation, Extensionality, Proper Part Principle… P.Simons, Casati & Varzi Subrelations: direct-part-of, functional-part-of, component-of, subdivision-of, boundary-of, … GALEN, FMA Continuants Occurrents Individuals Classes, Part-Of

Continuants Occurrents Individuals Classes Parts and Time Parts and Region s Parts and Classes Parts and Processes Part-Of

Continuants Occurrents Individuals Classes Parts and Time Parts and Region s Parts and Classes Parts and Processes Part-Of

Example I t 1 t 2 t 3 t 4 t 5 Parts and Time

Example II t1t1 t2t2 Parts and Time d d’ t

Two views 1. The tooth is no longer considered part of the dental arcade after extraction: d = d’ Problem: it has still some kind of relation with the dental arcade. Which one ? 2. The tooth continues being considered a (now disconnected) part of the dental arcade even after extraction: d = d’+ t  d  d’ Problem: what is then the spatial extension of the dentition? Is the dental arcade no longer the same ? Parts and Time

Historic Parthood Don’t take historic parthood for parthood “bone (in an archeologic site) forming part of a skeleton…” “transplanting part of a liver…” “sample of gastric mucosa of patient X was examined” Time-indexed parthood: part-of (a, b, t) Historic parthood: hist-part-of (a, b) =def  t,u: part-of (a, b, t)   part-of (a, b, u)  earlier(t, u) Parts and Time

Continuants Occurrents Individuals Classes Parts and Time Parts and Region s Parts and Classes Parts and Processes Part-Of

Regions At every moment in time a spatial object is located in a single region of space At different moments spatial objects may be located in different regions Parts and Region s t1t1 t5t5 t2t2 t3t3 t4t4 r1r1 r5r5 r2r2 c r4r4 r3r3

Regions At every moment in time a spatial object is located in a single region of space At different moments spatial objects may be located in different regions Parts and Region s t1t1 t5t5 t2t2 t3t3 t4t4 r1r1 r5r5 r2r2 c r4r4 r3r3

Regions At every moment in time a spatial object is located in a single region of space At different moments spatial objects may be located in different regions Parts and Region s t1t1 t5t5 t2t2 t3t3 t4t4 r1r1 r5r5 r2r2 c r4r4

Regions At every moment in time a spatial object is located in a single region of space At different moments spatial objects may be located in different regions Parts and Region s t1t1 t5t5 t2t2 t3t3 t4t4 r1r1 r5r5 r2r2 c r3r3

Regions At every moment in time a spatial object is located in a single region of space At different moments spatial objects may be located in different regions Parts and Region s t1t1 t5t5 t2t2 t3t3 t4t4 r1r1 r5r5 r2r2 c r4r4 r3r3

Parthood and Spatial Inclusion Parts and Region s R(z) z is a region in space z = r (x, t) z is the region where x is located at t part-of (x, y, t)  part-of (r (x,t), r (y, t)) (Donnelly, IJCAI 03) Spatial inclusion (coverage, (partly) location,…) spatially-included (x, y, t) = def part-of (r (x, t), r (y,t)) x is spatially included by y at t

Phagocytosis / Digestion v c t 1 t 2 t 3 t 4 t 5 Parts and Region s virus cell Objects: Cell, Virus

Phagocytosis / Digestion t 1 t 2 t 3 t 4 t 5 Parts and Region s r (c, t 1 ) r (c, t 2 ) r (c, t 3 )r (c, t 4 )r (c, t 5 ) r (v, t 1 ) r (v, t 2 ) r (v, t 3 ) part-of (r (v, t 3 ), r (c, t3)) Regions: Space occupied by Cell, space occupied by Virus

General Problem Parthood always implies spatial inclusion, but spatial inclusion does not always imply parthood: part-of (x, y, t)  spatially-included (x, y, t) Under which circumstances  can we infer parthood from spatial inclusion ? When does inclusion without parthood obtain ? spatially-included (x, y, t)    part-of (x, y, t) spatially-included (x, y, t)   ‘   part-of (x, y, t) Parts and Region s

Inferring part from spatial inclusion: 1. Sortality Rules out objects of certain sort as parts: x is material, y is immaterial: Solid (x)  Hole  (y)  spatially-included (x, y)   part-of (x, y) spatially-included (myBrain, myCranialCavity)   part-of (myBrain, myCranialCavity) x is an non-biological artifact: spatially-included (myPacemaker, myBody)   part-of (myPacemaker, myBody) spatially-included (myInlay, myTooth)   part-of (myInlay, myTooth) Parts and Region s

Inferring part from spatial inclusion: 2. Genetic Identity Rules out objects of different genetic origin: Symbionts: spatially-included (anEcoliBacterium, myIntestine)   part-of (anEcoliBacterium, myIntestine) Parasites: spatially-included (anEchinococcus, myLiver)   part-of (anEchinococcus, myLiver) Preys: spatially-included (anElephant, aSnake)   part-of (anElephant, aSnake) Embryos, Fetuses: spatially-included (Leonardo, Caterina)   p (Leonardo, Caterina) Parts and Region s

Inferring part from spatial inclusion: 3. Life Cycle 3.Life Cycle patterns which allow to assert parthood: Parts and Region s t 1 t 2 t 3 NOW aGlycinMolecule, aCollagenFiber aCytoplasm, aCell aGlioblastoma, aBrain

3.Life Cycle patterns which allow to rule out parthood: Parts and Region s t 1 t 2 t 3 NOW aWaterMolecule, aCell aBrainMetastasis, aBrain but : part-of what ? Inferring part from spatial inclusion: 3. Life Cycle

4.Essential for function Transplants functionally_related (aTransplant, anOrganism)  spatially-included (aTransplant, anOrganism)  part-of (aTransplant, anOrganism) Body Substances: functionally_related (myCSF, myCNS)  spatially-included (myCSF, myCNS)  part-of (myCSF, myCNS) Parts and Region s … but not: part-of (thisVolumeOfUrine, myBladder), because not essential for function Inferring part from spatial inclusion: 4. Function

Parts and Region s Inferring part from spatial inclusion: Decision algorithm

Continuants Occurrents Individuals Classes Parts and Time Parts and Region s Parts and Classes Parts and Processes Part-Of

Part-of between individuals and universals (classes) Thumb part-of Hand Italy part-of EuropemyThumb part-of myHand Parts and Classes IndividualsClasses

Do Classes or Concepts Have Parts ? Parts and Classes C |A |AUI|CHD|C |A |AUI|part_of|R ||UWDA|UWDA|||N|| C |A |AUI|RN|C |A |AUI|part_of|R ||UWDA|UWDA|||N|| C |A |AUI|RN|C |A |AUI|part_of|R ||UWDA|UWDA|||N|| C |A |AUI|RN|C |A |AUI|part_of|R ||UWDA|UWDA|||N|| C |A |AUI|RN|C |A |AUI|part_of|R ||UWDA|UWDA|||N|| C |A |AUI|RN|C |A |AUI|part_of|R ||UWDA|UWDA|||N|| C |A |AUI|RN|C |A |AUI|part_of|R ||UWDA|UWDA|||N|| C |A |SCUI|RN|C |A |SCUI|part_of|R | |SNOMEDCT|SNOMEDCT|0|Y|N|| C |A |SCUI|RN|C |A |SCUI|part_of|R | |SNOMEDCT|SNOMEDCT|0|Y|N|| C |A |AUI|CHD|C |A |AUI|part_of|R ||GO|GO||N|N|| C |A |AUI|CHD|C |A |AUI|part_of|R ||GO|GO||N|N|| C |A |AUI|CHD|C |A |AUI|part_of|R ||GO|GO||N|N|| C |A |AUI|CHD|C |A |AUI|part_of|R ||UWDA|UWDA|||N|| C |A |AUI|CHD|C |A |AUI|part_of|R ||UWDA|UWDA|||N|| C |A |AUI|CHD|C |A |AUI|part_of|R ||UWDA|UWDA|||N|| C |A |AUI|CHD|C |A |AUI|part_of|R ||UWDA|UWDA|||N|| C |A |AUI|RN|C |A |AUI|part_of|R ||UWDA|UWDA|||N|| C |A |AUI|RN|C |A |AUI|part_of|R ||UWDA|UWDA|||N|| C |A |AUI|RN|C |A |AUI|part_of|R ||UWDA|UWDA|||N|| C |A |AUI|RN|C |A |AUI|part_of|R ||UWDA|UWDA|||N|| C |A |AUI|CHD|C |A |AUI|part_of|R ||UWDA|UWDA|||N|| C |A |AUI|CHD|C |A |AUI|part_of|R ||UWDA|UWDA|||N|| CUI1 CUI2 RELA UMLS Metathesurus: MRREL table

Do Classes Have Parts ? “Axon part-of Neuron” (FMA) Does every neuron has an axon? “Axon part-of Cell ” (Gene Ontology) Do cells without axons exist ? Do axons without cells exist ? Parts and Classes

“Axon part-of Neuron” (FMA) Does every neuron has an axon? “Axon part-of cell” (Gene Ontology) Do cells without axons exist ? Do axons without cells exist ? “Keep in mind that part_of means can be a part of, not is always a part of “ GO Editorial Style Guide, Oct 2003 “The part_of relationship (…) is usually “necessarily is_part”” GO Editorial Style Guide, May 2005 “A part_of B if and only if: for any instance x of A there is some instance y of B which is such that x stands to y in the instance-level part relation, and vice versa”. Rosse & Smith MEDINFO 2004 Do Classes Have Parts ? Parts and Classes

Class-level Part-Of : Different Interpretations One-sided Dependency Part on Whole Mutual Mereological Dependency Mereological Independency Class A (part) Class B (whole) Examples Cell Nucleus – Cell Uterus – Human Body Prostate Tumor – Prostate Sulfur – Methionin Cell – Human Body Connective Tissue – Liver Cell Membrane – Cell Vertebra – Vertebrate Brain - Head Uterus – Mammal Sulfur – Amino Acid Tooth – Human One-sided Dependency Whole on Part Parts and Classes

One-sided Dependency Part on Whole Mutual Mereological Dependency Mereological Independency Class A (part) Class B (whole) Examples Cell Nucleus – Cell Uterus – Human Body Prostate Tumor – Prostate Sulfur – Methionin Cell – Human Body Connective Tissue – Liver Cell Membrane – Cell Vertebra – Vertebrate Brain - Head Uterus – Mammal Sulfur – Amino Acid Tooth – Human One-sided Dependency Whole on Part GALEN, Gene Ontology 05 / 2005 FMA Gene Ontology 11 / 2003 Class-level Part-Of : Different Interpretations Parts and Classes

One-sided Dependency Part on Whole Mutual Mereological Dependency Mereological Independency One-sided Dependency Whole on Part Possible-Part (A, B) = def  x,y: inst-of (x, A)  inst-of (y, B)  part-of (x, y) * Notation according to Donnelly & Bittner(forthcoming) Part-Of 1 (A, B) = def*  x: inst-of (x, A)   y: inst-of (y, B)  part-of (x, y) Part-Of 2 (A, B) = def*  y: inst-of (y, B)   x: inst-of (x, A)  part-of (x, y) Part-Of 12 (A, B) = def* Part-Of 1 (A, B)  Part-Of 2 (A, B) Class-level Part-Of : Different Interpretations Parts and Classes

Continuants Occurrents Individuals Classes Parts and Time Parts and Region s Parts and Classes Parts and Processes Part-Of

Example Removal of foreign body from stomach Removal of foreign body from stomach by endoscopy Removal of foreign body from stomach by incision Preparation for Endoscopy Introduction of Endoscope Exploration Removal of foreign body Extraction of Endoscope Preparation for Surgery Incision Exploration Removal of foreign body Closure t t Parts and Processes Surgical Procedure

Example Removal of foreign body from stomach Removal of foreign body from stomach by endoscopy Removal of foreign body from stomach by incision Preparation for Endoscopy Introduction of Endoscope Exploration Removal of foreign body Extraction of Endoscope Preparation for Surgery Incision Exploration Removal of foreign body Closure t t Parts and Processes Surgical Procedure Taxonomy of Processes

Example Removal of foreign body from stomach Removal of foreign body from stomach by endoscopy Removal of foreign body from stomach by incision Preparation for Endoscopy Introduction of Endoscope Exploration Removal of foreign body Extraction of Endoscope Preparation for Surgery Incision Exploration Removal of foreign body Closure t t Parts and Processes Surgical Procedure Mereology of Processes

1. A process is (sequentially) instantiated by its subprocesses: Subprocesses do not exist simultaneously You are doing something even if you have not done it (completely) 2. A process is instantiated by its temporal parts: Before having performed the complete process it is open whether the process will really be completed An aborted (token) process does not fulfill the necessary conditions which define the (type) process What are the instances of processes? Concurrent views Parts and Processes

Theory 1: Process is instantiated by its subprocesses Parts and Processes P1P1 P2P2 P3P3 P4P4 P t P1P1 P2P2 P3P3 P4P4 P p P1P1 P2P2 P3P3 P4P4 P p P1P1 P2P2 P3P3 P4P4 P p P1P1 P2P2 P3P3 P4P4 P p      instance-of t1t1 t2t2 t3t3 t4t4 Boris Hennig, unpublished

Parts and Processes P1P1 P2P2 P‘‘‘P1P1 P‘‘P2P2 P1P1 P‘P3P3 P2P2 P1P1 P P3P3 P4P4 t t1t1 t2t2 t3t3 t4t4 pppp is-a instance-of  has-part Theory 2: Subprocesses are parts of their parent processes

Conflicting views in Medical Terminologies Parts and Processes Removal of foreign body from stomach by incision Removal of foreign body from stomach by incision Removal of foreign body from stomach Incision of Stomach Removal of foreign body from stomach Incision of Stomach is-a Most procedure classifications (roughly Theory 1) SNOMED CT (Theory 2) rg Subprocesses are parts of their parent processesProcess is subsumed by its subprocesses

SNOMED CT Rg (relation group) can be re-interpreted as has-part Parts and Processes

Conclusions Parthood has multiple meanings Interoperability between ontologies and ontology based systems requires normative measures to avoid conflict between different meanings Spatial inclusion may be a “better” foundational relation for describing biological continuants Parthood between occurrents still requires thorough ontological enquiry

Thanks

Meaning of Part in Biomedical Ontologies Mereological relations are fundamental for any formal ontological description of entities of the biomedical domain. A formal account of what part is and isn’t is an indispensable requirement for interoperability between human and software agents

Basics Mereology(-ies): Formal theory(-ies) of parts and wholes (P. Simons 1987, Casati & Varzi 1999) part-of: transitive, reflexive, antisymmetric relation between individuals: part-of (myThumb, myHand) & part-of (myHand, myBody) -> part-of (myThumb, myHand) part-of (myThumb, myHand) -> NOT part-of (myHand, myThumb) part-of (myThumb, myThumb)

Part-Of: derived relations proper-part-of: proper-part-of (myThumb, myHand) NOT proper-part-of (myThumb, myThumb) more suitable for the biomedical domain, e.g.: “partial resection of stomach”  “total resection of stomach” proper overlap sharing of proper parts overlap (myThorax, myVagusNerve) (“exclusive part-of”, cf. R. Schubert 1999) unorthodox understanding of parthood- not to be taken for parthood

Part-Of Subrelations (1) Partitions / Subdivisions: disjoint parts which jointly sum up to a whole (Bittner 2004) decomposition of the entire body or any anatomical structure in a given context (Mejino 2004) p1 = {my Body} p2 = {my head, my neck, my torso, my limbs} p3 = {my head, my neck, my torso, my left leg, my right leg, my left arm, my right arm} p4 = {my head, my neck, my thorax, my abdomen, my left leg, my right leg, my left upper arm, my left lower arm, my right upper arm, my right lower arm}

Part-Of Subrelations (2) (Functional) Components of integral compounds: The part contributes to the whole not just as a structural unit but as essential to the purposeful activity of the whole (Pat Lambrix) How to define function ?

Part-Of Variations (3) Collections, Partonomic Inclusion Uniform elements, e.g. blood, water, urine (Gerstl 1995, Bittner 2004) homomerous = parts are of the same sort

Part-of: Dimensionality part-of (a, b) requires dim(a)  dim(a): -> e.g. 2D boundaries can be part of 3D objects in Medicine: different conceptualizations, e.g. in the FMA boundaries cannot be part of 3D objects

One-sided Dependency Part on Whole Mutual Mereological Dependency Mereological Independency One-sided Dependency Whole on Part Part-Of 1 (A, B) = def*  x: inst-of (x, A)   y: inst-of (y, B)  part-of (x, y) * Notation according to Maureen Donnelly (forthcoming) Class-level Part-Of : Different Interpretations Parts and Classes

One-sided Dependency Part on Whole Mutual Mereological Dependency Mereological Independency One-sided Dependency Whole on Part Part-Of 1 (A, B) = def*  x: inst-of (x, A)   y: inst-of (y, B)  part-of (x, y) Part-Of 2 (A, B) = def*  y: inst-of (y, B)   x: inst-of (x, A)  part-of (x, y) * Notation according to Maureen Donnelly (forthcoming) Class-level Part-Of : Different Interpretations Parts and Classes

One-sided Dependency Part on Whole Mutual Mereological Dependency Mereological Independency One-sided Dependency Whole on Part Part-Of 1 (A, B) = def*  x: inst-of (x, A)   y: inst-of (y, B)  part-of (x, y) Part-Of 2 (A, B) = def*  y: inst-of (y, B)   x: inst-of (x, A)  part-of (x, y) Part-Of 12 (A, B) = def* Part-Of 1 (A, B)  Part-Of 2 (A, B) * Notation according to Maureen Donnelly (forthcoming) Class-level Part-Of : Different Interpretations Parts and Classes

One-sided Dependency Part on Whole Mutual Mereological Dependency Mereological Independency One-sided Dependency Whole on Part Possible-Part (A, B) = def  x,y: inst-of (x, A)  inst-of (y, B)  part-of (x, y) * Notation according to Maureen Donnelly (forthcoming) Part-Of 1 (A, B) = def*  x: inst-of (x, A)   y: inst-of (y, B)  part-of (x, y) Part-Of 2 (A, B) = def*  y: inst-of (y, B)   x: inst-of (x, A)  part-of (x, y) Part-Of 12 (A, B) = def* Part-Of 1 (A, B)  Part-Of 2 (A, B) Class-level Part-Of : Different Interpretations Parts and Classes