Philosophy 220 The Moral Significance of the More than Human World: Virtues, the Environment and Consumerism.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
The Death Penalty Nathanson
Advertisements

The Moral Status of the Non- Human World: Matheny
Do We Need a Philosophical Account of Human Rights? Rorty ER 11, Gov E-1040 Spring 2012.
Ethical Theory.
ARISTOTLE: Background
Computer Ethics PHILOSOPHICAL BELIEF SYSTEMS Chapter 1 Computer Ethics PHILOSOPHICAL BELIEF SYSTEMS Chapter 1 Hassan Ismail.
Philosophy 223 Relativism and Egoism. Remember This Slide? Ethical reflection on the dictates of morality can address these sorts of issues in at least.
The Moral Status of the Non- Human World: Singer and Cohen.
Philosophy 220 The Moral Status of the Non-Human World: Cohen and Warren.
Hume on Taste Hume's account of judgments of taste parallels his discussion of judgments or moral right and wrong.  Both accounts use the internal/external.
Virtue Ethics. Virtue ethics focuses not so much on principles or the consequences of action, nor even the action itself so much as on the agent, the.
Boaz and Wilson on the Moral Status of Non-Medical Psychotropic Drug Use.
Philosophy 220 Boaz and De Marneffe on the Moral and Legal Status of Non- Medical Psychotropic Drug Use.
Virtue Theory Rels 300 / Nurs Sep What is a virtue? Virtue = a strength of character that promotes human well-being (self and others) often.
“Philosophy and the Search of wisdom”
MORAL THEORY: INTRODUCTION PHILOSOPHY 224. THE ROLE OF REASONS A fundamental feature of philosophy's contribution to our understanding of the contested.
Natural Law/Virtue Ethics. Morality and Human Nature  Natural Law Theory  Based upon assumption that the good is consistent with fundamental design.
Philosophy 223. Corporate Social Responsibility: Some Background  A common assumption: corporations don’t have any responsibilities.  Officers of corporations.
Philosophy 220 The Moral Significance of the More than Human World: Consumerism.
Philosophy 224 Person As Passion: Kierkegaard and Nietzsche.
Philosophy 224 Midgley on Dolphins (and Data). Sample Reading Quiz True or False: The Judge in the dolphin rescue case found that dolphins were persons,
Unit 4: Morality.
Deontological & Consequential Ethics
Morality and Virtues: Cultivating Character. In This Chapter…  Virtues: Habits of the Heart  The Theological Virtues: Faith, Hope, and Charity  The.
“A man without ethics is a wild beast loosed upon this world.”
MEM 604: Social, Legal and Ethical Considerations for Engineering Managing Safety and Liability.
PHIL/RS 335 The Problem of Evil Pt. 2. Hick, “Soul-Making Theodicy”  Hick begins by owning up. Unlike Cleanthes, Hick is willing to testify to the vast.
Faith as a Dimension of the Human
Philosophy 220 The Moral Status of the More Than Human World: The Environment.
Philosophy 220 Introducing Moral Theory (and the Topic of Sexual Morality)
Unit 4 The Aims of Law. Aims of Law  The proper aims of law and the common good are not the same thing. The appropriate aims of law are those aspects.
MEM 604: Social, Legal and Ethical Considerations for Engineering Engineers and the Environmental Challenge.
Virtue Ethics and Moral Pluralism
Frankena - A Critique of Virtue-Based Ethics
Ethical Theories Unit 9 Ethical Awareness. What Are Ethical Theories? - Explain what makes an action right or wrong - Have an overview of major ethical.
Philosophy 224 Moral Theory: Introduction. The Role of Reasons A fundamental feature of philosophy's contribution to our understanding of the contested.
Normative Ethical Theory: Utilitarianism and Kantian Deontology
KANT ANTHROPOLOGY FROM A PRAGMATIC POINT OF VIEW PHILOSOPHY 224.
Philosophy 220 The Moral Status of the More Than Human World: The Environment.
Welcome to Ethics Ethics and citizens rights DR. BURTON A. AGGABAO Professorial lecturer
Virtue Theories and Adultery. Character vs. Acts  Though historically speaking, Virtue Ethics is the first systematic, philosophical ethical position,
Philosophy 220 Rights-Based Moral Theories and Pornography.
ENGM 604: Social, Legal and Ethical Considerations for Engineering Responding to the Call of Morality: Identifying Relevant Facts, Principles and Solutions.
Cooley’s Human Nature & The Social Order Pt: 2. The Various Phases of the I Self and self-seeking are healthy and respectable traits of human nature.
Critical Social Theory
The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel’s Idealism.
Basic Framework of Normative Ethics. Normative Ethics ‘Normative’ means something that ‘guides’ or ‘controls’ ‘Normative’ means something that ‘guides’
MEM 604: Social, Legal and Ethical Considerations for Engineering Managing Safety and Liability.
Philosophy 223 Normative Ethical Theory: Challenges to the Dominant Theories.
Chapter 14: The Environment, Consumption, and Global Warming William F. Baxter, “People or Penguins: The Case for Optimal Pollution” – Baxter defends an.
Chapter 10: Cloning and Genetic Enhancement John Robertson, “Liberty, Identity, and Human Cloning” – Robertson's main 3-part argumentative strategy Part.
MNU Five Other Ethical Systems Dr. Judy Martin Session 7 – February 18, 2014.
The Ethics Of Environment Businesses have been ignoring their impact on the natural environment for centuries, largely because the economic costs and harmful.
Philosophy 224 Moral Theory: Introduction. The Role of Reasons A fundamental feature of philosophy ' s contribution to our understanding of the contested.
Relativism, Divine Command Theory, and Particularism A closer look at some prominent views of ethical theory.
For this exam you must learn how to apply virtue ethics to an ethical dilemma. You can pick any ethical dilemma you wish except for the issues in science.
Philosophy 219 Introduction to Moral Theory. Theoretical vs. Practical  One of the ways in which philosophers (since Aristotle) subdivide the field of.
Peter Wenz, “Environmental Virtues:Consumerism and Human Flourishing”
Basic concepts in Ethics
Introduction to Moral Theory
Moral Arguments.
Introduction to Moral Theory
Introduction to Moral Theory
Philosophy 224 Divine Persons: Pt. 1.
Environmental Ethics Do other animals have rights? Do we have duties and obligations to them? Or are they simply there to be used however we see fit.?
Outline the naturalistic fallacy
Kant Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View
Wisdom,Knowledge and Information
Person As Passion: Kierkegaard and Nietzsche
Presentation transcript:

Philosophy 220 The Moral Significance of the More than Human World: Virtues, the Environment and Consumerism

Hill, Jr., “Ideals of Human Excellence” Hill begins with the interesting example of the ‘wealthy eccentric.’ The question the example prompts is, “What sort of person would do a thing like that?” (624c1) This question points in the direction that Hill’s essay takes us. Though, as he argues, there is no suitably convincing way to prove that the destruction of nature is morally wrong, that’s not the end of the story. The focus on the rightness and wrongness of acts misses the morally significant analysis of the virtues indicated or highlighted by destructive actions. Our question about the eccentric points to a different sort of moral concern.

Wrongness? Typical analyses of actions like those of the eccentric isolate relevant features of the action for scrutiny. We could contest certain sorts of conclusions about overall utility. We could consider the welfare and interests of non-animal life (plant rights?). We could argue from religious convictions about what God requires of us. All of these approaches, more or less plausible, ignore a question relevant to the virtuousness of the agents involved; namely, what the willingness to engage in the acts reveals about the character of the individuals involved.

An Answer Hill’s response is not to insist that such a person lacks virtue (is not a virtuous person) but rather that, “…indifference to non-sentient nature…often signals the absence of certain traits which we want to encourage because they are, in most cases, a natural basis for the development of certain virtues” (626c1). Thus, though he is not willing to affirm that our eccentric necessarily lacks humility (the proper appreciation for one’s place in the natural order), the eccentric’s actions do indicate a certain kind of ignorance or narrowness of appreciation which is a likely precursor to humility.

Some Responses Hill imagines a critic of his claim who would reject the idea that the eccentric's disdain for non-sentient nature is rooted in a kind of ignorance or failure of appreciation. A first response: knowledge of nature does not necessarily require moral concern (naturalistic fallacy). Hill: logical point is granted, but it is the case that familiarity typically increases concern. A second response: it is not knowledge that the destroyer is lacking, it is the proper perspective and this cosmic perspective doesn’t guarantee concern either Hill: true, but indifference is still usually a sign that one fails to see oneself as a part of the natural order. Furthermore, an appreciation of one's place in nature is not just an intellectual understanding, it requires humility.

Humility For Hill, humility is an ability to measure importance without relation to oneself or something one identifies with (628c1). In this context, the critic has one more objection: to assert that an ideal humility requires us to view non-sentient nature as important for its own sake begs the question. Hill’s response is to specify the nature of this requirement: it is not conceptual but developmental. A positive expression of this sense of humility is self-acceptance as part of the natural order, subject to the same natural forces and limits of all other elements of the whole (629c2). Hill insists that experiencing nature promotes such a self- acceptance. The eccentric's failure may be one of refusing to see himself in this way.

In Summary If Hill is right, though acts of natural destruction cannot be argued to be morally wrong, they can be criticized as resulting from defects in agents like the eccentric. These defects (ignorance, self-importance, and lack of self- acceptance, the latter two entailing a lack of the humility crucial to understanding one's place in the world) while not necessarily vicious in themselves do raise morally relevant questions about the character of these agents. Thus, Hill's environmental ethics focus not so much on the state of the environment itself, or on the rightness or wrongness of acts with environmental significance, but on human beings and their proper attitudes and dispositions to their environment.

Wenz, “Environmental Virtues” Wenz begins by noting that from a virtue ethical standpoint, there doesn’t appear to be any conflict between anthropocentric and non-anthropocentric moral standpoints. For both, the traditional virtues produce agents whose actions are consistent with human and non-human flourishing. However, our economic system’s reliance on consumerism is inconsistent with these virtues, inasmuch as it presumes a range of dispositions inconsistent with virtue (vices). Thus, virtue ethics of either anthropocentric or non-anthropocentric varieties support the conclusion that consumerism is immoral. The fact that these perspectives support and enhance each other is the ‘synergy’ of the title.

What is Consumerism? Consumerism is not the same as consumption. Consumption is an ineliminable part of life, as all living things need to consume energy to sustain themselves. Consumerism: “the ideology that society should maximize consumption, pursue consumption without limit” (632). This is the ideology that dominates much of global economic policy. It is also an ideology that pervades much of our thinking about ourselves and the world.

Consumerism and the More than Human World A non-anthropocentric moral standpoint is committed to the DMS of the more than human world. As Wenz demonstrates (631c1-2), consumerism causes significant degradation of the more than human world. Global warming Pollution, resource use, species extinction Thus, from a non-anthropocentric moral standpoint, consumerism is immoral.

Consumerism and Anthropocentrism For the anthropocentric moral view, human beings are the primary bearers of moral value. Wenz demonstrates that consumerism harms human beings apart from any collateral damage that might be done to the natural world. His argument here proceeds in two stages: he first discusses how consumerism harms poor people in the third world ( ), He then considers how consumerism harms “industrial people” in the developed world as well (635-37). The harm done to both these groups by a consumption- driven lifestyle, leads to the conclusion that from the anthropocentric standpoint, consumerism is wrong.

What about Virtue? Up to this point, much of the focus has been on the consequences for nature and for humans of the rampant consumerism which dominates our form of life. However, Wenz’s claim to a synergy between anthropocentric and non-anthropocentric moral views is ultimately tied to a common virtue ethical perspective. To close the loop, Wenz focuses our attention on the vices that consumerism encourages and the virtues that are common to both A and non-A views.

The Vices Consumerism is rooted in what for ancient Greek virtue ethicists was a unifying vice: outdoing. Consumerism, in its call for endless progress, encourages us all to grab a much of the good stuff as possible, to see ourselves as competing against each other, “The Person with the Most Toys Wins” More specific vices that this ‘master vice’ encourage include: greed, avarice, gluttony, envy, pride, intemperance, selfishness and indifference.

The Virtues By contrast, both anthropocentric and non-anthropocentric virtue ethical perspectives typically articulate a set of virtues (habits or dispositions to act), that are at odds with the goals and practices of consumerism. These virtues include: frugality, appreciation, temperance, self-development, dedication, generosity, benevolence. Though these virtues may be essentially human capacities, to the extent that they are consistent with the good of the more than human world, they receive non-anthropocentric support.

A Philosophical Conclusion Though much of the energy of Wenz’s analysis is dedicated to the critique of consumerism, the primary philosophical accomplishment of the essay is to bridge the gap between anthropocentric and non- anthropocentric moral views. Though in the context of the question of the moral status of the more than human world, this gap looms large, Wenz argues that in particular cases (like the critique of consumerism) they overlap significantly and can be mutually reinforcing.