On the smooth ambiguity model and Machina’s reflection example Robert Nau Fuqua School of Business Duke University.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Choices Involving Risk
Advertisements

Economics of Information (ECON3016)
Decision Analysis (Decision Tables, Utility)
From risk to opportunity Lecture 10 John Hey and Carmen Pasca.
Utility Theory.
Confidence-Based Decision Making Climate Science and Response Strategies Discussion Grantham, February
1 Decision Making and Utility Introduction –The expected value criterion may not be appropriate if the decision is a one-time opportunity with substantial.
Chapter 15: Decisions Under Risk and Uncertainty McGraw-Hill/Irwin Copyright © 2011 by the McGraw-Hill Companies, Inc. All rights reserved.
Lecture 4 Environmental Cost - Benefit - Analysis under risk and uncertainty.
McGraw-Hill/Irwin Copyright © 2013 by The McGraw-Hill Companies, Inc. All rights reserved. Chapter 15 Decisions under Risk and Uncertainty.
Non-Probability-Multiple-Prior Models of Decision Making Under Ambiguity: new experimental evidence John Hey a and Noemi Pace b a University of York, UK.
Rational choice: An introduction Political game theory reading group 3/ Carl Henrik Knutsen.
Chapter 13 Risk Attitudes ..
Utility Axioms Axiom: something obvious, cannot be proven Utility axioms (rules for clear thinking)
1 Utility Theory. 2 Option 1: bet that pays $5,000,000 if a coin flipped comes up tails you get $0 if the coin comes up heads. Option 2: get $2,000,000.
Judgment and Decision Making in Information Systems Utility Functions, Utility Elicitation, and Risk Attitudes Yuval Shahar, M.D., Ph.D.
L3: Risk and Risk Measurement 1 Risk and Risk Measurement (L3) Following topics are covered: –Risk –Defining “More Risk Averse” Utility functions Absolute.
Lecture 4 on Individual Optimization Risk Aversion

L1: Risk and Risk Measurement1 Lecture 1: Risk and Risk Measurement We cover the following topics in this part –Risk –Risk Aversion Absolute risk aversion.
Uncertainty and Consumer Behavior
Using Prospect Theory to Study Unknown Probabilities ("Ambiguity") by Peter P. Wakker, Econ. Dept., Erasmus Univ. Rotterdam (joint with Mohammed Abdellaoui.
Uncertain Outcomes Here we study projects that have uncertain outcomes and we view various ways people may deal with the uncertain situations.
Making Simple Decisions Copyright, 1996 © Dale Carnegie & Associates, Inc. Chapter 16.
Combining Bayesian Beliefs and Willingness to Bet to Analyze Attitudes towards Uncertainty by Peter P. Wakker, Econ. Dept., Erasmus Univ. Rotterdam (joint.
Uncertainty RUD, June 28, 2006, Peter P. Wakker Paper: Chapter for New Palgrave. Its didactical beginning is not optimal for this specialized audience.
Lecture 3: Arrow-Debreu Economy
Investment Analysis and Portfolio Management
1 1 Slide © 2001 South-Western College Publishing/Thomson Learning Anderson Sweeney Williams Anderson Sweeney Williams Slides Prepared by JOHN LOUCKS QUANTITATIVE.
Frank Cowell : Risk RISK MICROECONOMICS Principles and Analysis Frank Cowell Almost essential Consumption and Uncertainty Almost essential Consumption.
Copyright © 2005 by the McGraw-Hill Companies, Inc. All rights reserved. McGraw-Hill/Irwin Managerial Economics Thomas Maurice eighth edition Chapter 15.
On the relationship between Keynes’s conception of evidential weight and the Ellsberg paradox Alberto Feduzi University of Cambridge and University of.
Combining Bayesian Beliefs and Willingness to Bet to Analyze Attitudes towards Uncertainty by Peter P. Wakker, Econ. Dept., Erasmus Univ. Rotterdam (joint.
STOCHASTIC DOMINANCE APPROACH TO PORTFOLIO OPTIMIZATION Nesrin Alptekin Anadolu University, TURKEY.
1 Bayesianism Without Priors, Acts Without Consequences Robert Nau Fuqua School of Business Duke University ISIPTA 2005.
Agata Michalaszek Warsaw School of Social Psychology Information search patterns in risk judgment and in risky choices.
Thinking and Decision Making
Chapter 15 Risk Analysis. Frequency definition of probability zGiven a situation in which a number of possible outcomes might occur, the probability of.
Stochastic choice under risk Pavlo Blavatskyy June 24, 2006.
Chapter 5 Uncertainty and Consumer Behavior. ©2005 Pearson Education, Inc.Chapter 52 Q: Value of Stock Investment in offshore drilling exploration: Two.
RISK, AMBIGUITY, GAINS, LOSSES Sujoy Chakravarty Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Hauz Khas, New Delhi ,
Chapter 5 Choice Under Uncertainty. Chapter 5Slide 2 Topics to be Discussed Describing Risk Preferences Toward Risk Reducing Risk The Demand for Risky.
Ambiguity Made Operational by Peter P. Wakker, Econ. Dept., Erasmus Univ. Rotterdam (joint with Mohammed Abdellaoui & Aurélien Baillon) ESA, Tucson, Oct.
Ellsberg’s paradoxes: Problems for rank- dependent utility explanations Cherng-Horng Lan & Nigel Harvey Department of Psychology University College London.
Choice under uncertainty Assistant professor Bojan Georgievski PhD 1.
Lecture 3 on Individual Optimization Uncertainty Up until now we have been treating bidders as expected wealth maximizers, and in that way treating their.
Statistical Decision Theory Bayes’ theorem: For discrete events For probability density functions.
Decision theory under uncertainty
© 2005 Pearson Education Canada Inc Chapter 17 Choice Making Under Uncertainty.
Axiomatic Theory of Probabilistic Decision Making under Risk Pavlo R. Blavatskyy University of Zurich April 21st, 2007.
Allais Paradox, Ellsberg Paradox, and the Common Consequence Principle Then: Introduction to Prospect Theory Psychology 466: Judgment & Decision Making.
1 Optimizing Decisions over the Long-term in the Presence of Uncertain Response Edward Kambour.
Scoring Rules, Generalized Entropy and Utility Maximization Victor Richmond R. Jose Robert F. Nau Robert L. Winkler The Fuqua School of Business Duke University.
Evaluating Hypotheses. Outline Empirically evaluating the accuracy of hypotheses is fundamental to machine learning – How well does this estimate its.
Risk and Uncertainty When we represent outcomes as possibilities rather than a deterministic outcome, we must address feelings about risk. Why would risk.
1 Decision Analysis Without Consequences, Bayesianism Without Probabilities Robert Nau Fuqua School of Business Duke University Presentation for RUD 2005.
DADSS Lecture 11: Decision Analysis with Utility Elicitation and Use.
Updating Ambiguity Averse Preferences Eran Hanany Peter Klibanoff Tel Aviv UniversityNorthwestern University Faculty of EngineeringKellogg School of Management.
Von Neumann-Morgenstern Lecture II. Utility and different views of risk Knightian – Frank Knight Risk – known probabilities of events Uncertainty – unknown.
Chapter 15: Decisions Under Risk and Uncertainty
Portfolio Theory & Related Topics
Decisions Under Risk and Uncertainty
CHAPTER 1 FOUNDATIONS OF FINANCE I: EXPECTED UTILITY THEORY
Microeconomics 2 John Hey.
Ascertaining certain certainties in choices under uncertainty
Risk Chapter 11.
Choices Involving Risk
Chapter 15 Decisions under Risk and Uncertainty
Chapter 15: Decisions Under Risk and Uncertainty
Making Simple Decisions
Presentation transcript:

On the smooth ambiguity model and Machina’s reflection example Robert Nau Fuqua School of Business Duke University

Machina’s reflection example If the decision maker is not indifferent among all the alternatives, then, by symmetry, preferences among the first two and last two alternatives ought to be reflected, i.e., f 5  f 6 [resp. f 6  f 5 ] ought to imply f 8  f 7 [resp. f 7  f 8 ] Rank-dependent models do not allow this: indifference is required. But... which of the reflected patterns is more representative of ambiguity aversion? For each act there are 3 possible payoffs f 6 and f 7 are left-right reflections of f 5 and f 8, respectively.

Baillon et al show that the following 4 models allow only one of the two reflected patterns: f 5  f 6 and f 8  f 7 – Maxmin expected utility (Gilboa-Schmeidler) –  maxmin expected utility (Ghirardato et. all 2004) – Variational prefererences (Maccheroni et al. 2006) – Smooth model (Klibanoff et al. 2005, Nau 2001, 2006) Should the opposite pattern be allowed, or even required? If so, it might considered as a “paradox” for those models

In experiments conducted by L’Haridon and Placido (2010) a plurality of subjects exhibited the opposite pattern – 46% said f 6  f 5 and f 7  f 8, contrary to the 4 models – 28% said f 5  and f 8  f 7 Baillon et al. 2011: f 6  f 5 and f 7  f 8 “can be justified in light of Ellsberg because f 6 and f 7 assign known probabilities to at least one outcome (100). Furthermore f 6 and f 7 are less exposed to ambiguity than f 5 and f 8.” Recently, Dillenberger and Segal (2014) and Dominiak and Lefort have presented examples whose parameters can be chosen to rationalize, f 6  f 5 and f 7  f 8, contrary to the other 4 models

Baillon et al. do also observe that the opposite pattern might be justified on the basis of aversion to mean-preserving spreads in utility. In what follows, I will argue aversion to mean-preserving spreads in the presence of multiple sources of ambiguity is rather compelling. A simple example of the smooth model will be used for demonstrations, but it captures the intuition of the other models as well.

Consider the following variation of Machina’s example involving the same events with different payoffs: g 1 arguably be preferred because it diversifies exposure to both risk and ambiguity. Even an EU maximizer will prefer g 1

Now add y to the payoff in the first two columns, which increases the objective expected payoff of both acts by ½y: These are the same choices as Machina’s example when x = y = $4000 g 3 and g 4 are equally risky from the perspective of EU theory, but the relative exposure to ambiguity is the same as in g 1 and g 2. If you preferred g 1 to g 2 at least partly on the basis of a desire to diversify your exposure to ambiguity, shouldn’t you prefer g 3 here?

KMM version of smooth model (2005) The probability measure  represents first-order risk The utility function u represents aversion to risk The probability measure  represents ambiguity (uncertainty about first-order risk) The utility function  represents aversion to ambiguity

Properties of KMM model Separates risk from risk attitude and separates ambiguity from ambiguity attitude, by analogy with SEU model In principle, requires elicitation of preferences for “2 nd -order acts”: mappings from hypothetical probability distributions to consequences. In Machina’s example, or even Ellsberg’s 2-urn problem, what second-order distribution would you use to represent your perception of ambiguity about the proportion of red balls in the unknown urn? – Binary? Uniform? Binomial...? – Was the experimenter “out to get me”?

My version (2001, 2006) The setting is the general state-preference framework with arbitrary smooth indifference curves in finite-dimensional state space, represented by an ordinal utility function U(x) Acts are mappings from states to amounts of money—no counterfactuals. In general, does not separate beliefs, states, and background risk Observable parameters of preferences (up to 2 nd -order effects) are the vector of local risk neutral probabilities (betting rates on states, denoted by  ) and its matrix of derivatives (denoted by D  ) Risk premium of a neutral act z is -½ z  D  z This quadratic form generalizes the Arrow-Pratt measure to settings involving background risk state-dependence, non-EU...

My version (2001, 2006) Ambiguity aversion is manifested as source-dependent risk aversion, as determined by the structure of D  Easy for the decision maker to choose a functional form for U(x) to represent a simple situation such as Ellsberg’s 2-run problem: – By symmetry, probabilities of all 4 states are the same. – The utility function can be given a nested form involving 2 Bernoulli utility functions that measure attitudes toward the 2 sources of risk. – Preferences among simple bets reveal which source of risk is more aversive (interpretable as more ambiguous)

The following functional form yields EU preferences separately for the bets on only one of the two sources of uncertainty:...but the decision need not exhibit the same risk attitude toward both.

If the certainty-equivalent form is used for the utility functions, the two Bernoulli utility functions u and v both have $$ as their arguments and if is easy to compare the source-dependent risk aversion that they induce: If u(v -1 (x)) is convex [concave] then the decision maker is more averse to the second [first] source of risk

Let the balls be renumbered {E 11, E 12, E 21, E 22 } respectively Ellsberg’s 2-urn experiment can be replicated with Machina’s single urn, by allowing only pure bets on the first digit or on the second digit:

Using the nested form of the utility function, the certainty equivalents for f 1 and f 2 are: Transparently, f 1 is preferred if u is less risk averse than v at every x, which is true if u(v -1 (x)) is convex.

Now consider Machina’s example, which involves 3 distinct payoffs:

Suppressing the probabilities (because they are uniform) and the outer u -1 function (because it is increasing), the comparison of f 5 and f 6 becomes equivalent to a comparison of the following two expressions: Letting w(x) = u(v -1 (x)), this becomes:

This yields f 5  f 6 and f 8  f 7 for all positive x and y if w(x) is convex, which is true if v(x) is more risk averse than u(x), i.e., if the decision maker is more averse toward the ambiguous source of risk than toward the unambiguous one. The opposite pattern is obtained if w(x) is concave. If w(x) is neither convex nor concave, there is not a conclusive identification of one source as being more averse, and the specific values of x and y would matter. Again, the comparison of f 5 vs. f 6 reduces to a comparison of the following expressions (bigger = better), where w(x) = u(v -1 (x)):

This result is intuitive if you take a closer look at the payoff table: f 5 and f 8 diversify the exposure to ambiguity so that it depends on the unknown proportions of differently-labeled balls in both urns. f 6 and f 7 “bet the farm” on just one of the two sources. This is the intuition behind all the models that favor f 5 and f 8 – Not paradoxical at all to me!

Why did a plurality (not a decisive one!) exhibit the opposite preferences? My conjecture: the example is tricky and the diversification angle is hard to see at first, precisely because it involves thinking of two sources of ambiguity at once.