3. The Nature & Limits of Inductive Reasoning (the problem of induction)

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Immanuel Kant ( ) Theory of Aesthetics
Advertisements

Modernity European challenges to Christianity. Back in Europe Huge challenges posed to Christianity Huge challenges posed to Christianity Wars of Religion.
HUMAN NATURE AND MODERN PHILOSOPHY HUME PHILOSOPHY 224.
HUME AND EMPIRICISM  David Hume – Scottish philosopher – Epistemological approach set out in two key works:  A Treatise of Human Nature.
Immanuel Kant’s Epistemology Life – Born in Königsberg, Prussia (now part of Russia) in – His family was originally from Scotland. (The original.
© Michael Lacewing Hume’s scepticism Michael Lacewing
Newton and psychology Thanks to Newton, scientists and philosophers know that the world is controlled by absolute natural laws, so the inconsistencies.
Michael Lacewing Hume on causation Michael Lacewing © Michael Lacewing.
Chapter 9 Kant’s Transcendental Idealism. How did Hume influence Kant? What is the distinction between the noumenal and the phenomenal worlds? What are.
Idealism.
Chapter 25 Romanticism’s response to Enlightenment theology.
Hume on Taste Hume's account of judgments of taste parallels his discussion of judgments or moral right and wrong.  Both accounts use the internal/external.
What is the issue? SubjectObject IdeaEvent MindWorld Experiencer Experienced Inner Outer MeIt SubjectObject IdeaEvent MindWorld Experiencer Experienced.
INTRODUCTION TO CRITICAL THINKING. “There are multiple decisions which you have to make entirely by yourself. You can’t lean on anybody else. And a good.
David Hume ( )  Fame as a philosopher (for Treatise and Enquiry) followed fame as an historian (for A History of Britain)
The Cosmological Argument. Also known as ‘The First Cause Argument’ Unlike the Ontological Argument, it derives the conclusion from a posteriori premise.
Rationalism: Knowledge Is Acquired through Reason, not the Senses We know only that of which we are certain. Sense experience cannot guarantee certainty,
Chapter 3: Knowledge The Congenial Skeptic: David Hume
CHAPTER 3 – DIFFERENT EDUCATIONAL PHILOSOPHIES
Parsing Categories of Belief Why Early Modern M&E divides belief into two types: Sensory & Mathematical.
Modern Philosophers Rationalists –Descartes –Spinoza –Leibniz Empiricists –Locke –Berkeley –Hume Epistemology - the theory of knowledge (what and how we.
Why a third Critique? Seminar “Kant: Critique of the Power of Judgment” University of Iceland Session 1 18/9/2007 Text: Preface Claus Beisbart.
Philosophy of science Philosophers of science. Early Philosophers Plato ( B.C.) –Rationalist Aristotle ( B.C.) –Empiricist.
Looking at the Roots of Philosophy
Immanuel Kant Critique of Pure Reason. Historical Context Kant lived during the age of enlightenment The spirit of enlightenment (Aufklaerung): 1. Universalism:
 According to philosophical skepticism, we can’t have knowledge of the external world.
9/18/2015 Modern Philosophy PHIL320 1 Kant I Charles Manekin.
Why Does Anything at all Exist? Why is there something rather than nothing? Leibniz - the principle of sufficient reason.
Epistemology Section 1 What is knowledge?
Chapter 3: Knowledge Kant’s Revolution Introducing Philosophy, 10th edition Robert C. Solomon, Kathleen Higgins, and Clancy Martin.
The Sheriff’s Dilemma How to structure your answer.
Kant Deontology Categorical Imperative. Immanuel Kant Profile: Dead German Time of Berkley, Rousseau, Hume, Bentham Not a fan of music or arts.
© Michael Lacewing Hume and Kant Michael Lacewing co.uk.
The Turn to the Science The problem with substance dualism is that, given what we know about how the world works, it is hard to take it seriously as a.
Why Does Anything at all Exist? Why is there something rather than nothing? Leibniz - the principle of sufficient reason.
L ECTURE 14: H UME ’ S R ADICAL E MPIRICISM. T ODAY ’ S L ECTURE In Today’s Lecture we will: 1.Recap our investigation into empiricist theories of knowledge.
An Inquiry Concerning Human Understanding
© Michael Lacewing Kant on conceptual schemes Michael Lacewing osophy.co.uk.
Critical Social Theory “[O]ur age is … the age of enlightenment, and to criticism everything must submit” Kant, Critique of Pure Reason.
L ECTURE 15: C ERTAINTY. T ODAY ’ S L ECTURE In Today’s Lecture we will: 1.Review Hume’s radical empiricism and its consequences 2.Outline and investigate.
Epistemology (How do you know something?)  How do you know your science textbook is true?  How about your history textbook?  How about what your parents.
By: Lowell Ringel. Born in 1724 in Königsburg, East Prussia (modern day Kaliningrad, Russia) Was a longtime professor at the University of Königsburg.
1. 2 David Hume’s Theory of Knowledge ( ) Scottish Empiricist.
KANT ON THE POSSIBILITY OF METAPHYSICS Text source: Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics, introduction.
Chapter 3: Knowledge The Rationalist’s Confidence: Descartes Introducing Philosophy, 10th edition Robert C. Solomon, Kathleen Higgins, and Clancy Martin.
UNIT6: PHILOSOPHY: PERSONAL IDENTITY
Chapter 7: Ethics Morality and Practical Reason: Kant
The Nature of God Nancy Parsons. Attributes- Nature of God Candidates should be able to demonstrate knowledge and understanding of: 1.God as eternal,
Some Philosophical Orientations of Educational Research You Do What You Think, I Think.
The Cosmological Argument Today’s lesson will be successful if: You have revised the ideas surrounding the cosmological argument and the arguments from.
By: Ken Norris and Dane Sandt
The Cosmological Argument for God’s Existence
GRADING: First essay 25% Second essay 35% Exam 25%
Lecture 1 What is metaphysics?
Introduction to Philosophy Plato’s Republic Greek Philosophy Socrates Socratic Method: Admit ignorance. Never rely on tradition. Continuously question.
Starter: Mix-Pair-Share
Skepticism David Hume’s Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding and John Pollock’s “Brain in a vat” Monday, September 19th.
c) Strengths and weaknesses of Cosmological Arguments:
David Hume and Causation
Philosophy and History of Mathematics
Skepticism David Hume’s Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding
Major Periods of Western Philosophy
Michael Lacewing Hume and Kant Michael Lacewing © Michael Lacewing.
Rationalism.
Jez Echevarría 6th September 2013
Kant’s Categorical Imperative - revision
Reasoning about Reasoning
David Hume Trust Your Senses
Introduction to Epistemology
Presentation transcript:

3. The Nature & Limits of Inductive Reasoning (the problem of induction)

Hume on Induction  Induction is the process of drawing inferences from past experiences of cause & effect sequences to present or future events.  Hume's point is that an "effect" cannot be validly deduced from its "cause;"  the inference from "cause" to "effect" is based on past experiences of "constant conjunction," and these past experiences....

accustom or habituate us to believe that one event is the cause of another, which we believe to be the effect of the prior event. This is what leads us to believe that....

the future will resemble the past. It is all a matter of CUSTOM or HABIT. This is the foundation of....

The Idea that there is a Necessary Connection between Cause & Effect What, then, is the sense impression from which this idea is derived? If this is a meaningful (& true?) idea, then (according to Hume) it must be derived from sense impressions.

There is no sense impression of causal power or necessary connection of cause & effect, but we do experience....  (1) the spatial contiguity,  (2) the temporal succession, and  (3) the constant conjunction of "cause" & "effect."

It is from this experience,  especially the experience of constant conjunction,  that the idea of a necessary connection between "cause" & "effect" arises (or is inferred);  but the "inference" is simply a matter of "custom or habit."  This seems to mean that the "inference" here is psycho-logical rather than logical. Actually, there is no experience of the necessary connection between cause and effect. Thus, all factual judgments (which are based on the assumption that there is a necessary connection between cause and effect) are subject to doubt.  No necessity, no certainty.

Immanuel Kant Lutheran (Pietist) background “Second Copernican Revolution” in philosophy Spent all his life in Königsberg, a small German town on the Baltic Sea in East Prussia. (After World War II, Germany's border was pushed west, so Königsberg is now called Kaliningrad and is part of Russia.) Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

Immanuel Kant At the age of fifty-five, Kant had published much work on the natural sciences, taught at Königsberg University for over twenty years, and achieved a good reputation in German literary circles. During the last twenty-five years of his life, however, Kant's philosophical work placed him firmly in the company of such towering giants as Plato and Aristotle. Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

Immanuel Kant Kant's three major works are often considered to be the starting points for different branches of modern philosophy: the Critique of Pure Reason (1781) for the philosophy of mind; the Critique of Practical Reason (1788) for moral philosophy; and the Critique of Judgment (1790) for aesthetics. Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

Immanuel Kant The Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals was published in 1785, just before the Critique of Practical Reason. It is essentially a short introduction to the argument presented in the second Critique. Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

Kant’s Intellectual Climate Kant lived and wrote during the Enlightenment. This period produced the ideas about human rights and democracy that inspired the French and American revolutions. (Some other major figures of the Enlightenment were Locke, Hume, Rousseau and Leibniz.) The characteristic quality of the Enlightenment was an immense confidence in reason, i.e. humanity's ability to solve problems through logical analysis. The central metaphor of the Enlightenment was a notion of the light of reason dispelling the darkness of mythology and misunderstanding. Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

Kant’s Intellectual Climate Enlightenment thinkers like Kant felt that history had placed them in the unique position of being able to provide clear reasons and arguments for their beliefs. The ideas of earlier generations, they thought, had been determined by myths and traditions; their own ideas were based on reason. Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals (According to this way of thinking, the French monarchy's claims to power were based on tradition; reason prescribed a republican government like that created by the revolution.)

Kant Kant's philosophical goal was to use logical analysis to understand reason itself. Before we go about analyzing our world, Kant argued, we must understand the mental tools we will be using. In the Critique of Pure Reason, Kant set about developing a comprehensive picture of how our mind – our reason – receives and processes information. Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

Kant Kant later said that the great Scottish philosopher David Hume ( ) had inspired him to undertake this project. Hume, Kant said, awoke him from an intellectual "slumber." The idea that so inspired Kant was Hume's analysis of cause-and- effect relationships. Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

Hume According to Hume, when we talk about events in the world we say that one thing ‘causes’ another. But nothing in our perceptions tells us that anything causes anything else. All we know from our perceptions is that certain events regularly occur immediately after certain other events. ‘Causation’ is just a concept that we employ to make sense of why certain events regularly follow certain other events. Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

Kant Kant took Hume's idea and went one step further. Causation, Kant argues, is not just an idea that we employ to make sense of our perceptions. It is a concept that we cannot help but employ. We don't sit around watching events and then develop an idea of causation on the basis of what we see. We automatically bring the concept to bear on the situation. Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

Kant Kant argued that causation and a number of other basic ideas (e.g., time and space) are hardwired, as it were, into our minds. Anytime we try to understand what we see, we cannot help but think in terms of causes and effects. Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

Kant Kant's argument has huge implications. If our picture of the world is structured by concepts that are hardwired into our minds, then we can't know anything about how the world ‘really’ is. The world we know about is developed by combining sensory data (‘appearances’ or ‘phenomena,’ as Kant called them) with fundamental concepts of reason (‘causation,’ etc.). We don't know anything about the ‘things-in- themselves’ from which sensory data emanates. Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

Kant This recognition that our understanding of the world may have as much to do with our minds as with the world has been called a “Copernican Revolution” in philosophy – a change in perspective as significant to philosophy as Copernicus’s recognition that the earth is not the center of the universe. Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

Kant Kant's insights posed a severe challenge to many earlier ideas. Ex.: Before Kant many philosophers offered ‘proofs’ of the existence of God. One argument made was that there must be a "first cause" for the universe. Kant pointed out that the question of whether there "must" be a first cause for the universe is irrelevant, because it is really a question about how we understand the world, not a question about the world itself. Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

Kant Kant’s analysis similarly shifted the debate over free will and determinism. (Kant presents a version of this argument in Chapter 3 of the Groundwork.) When we use reason to understand why we have made the choices we have, we can come up with a causal explanation. But this picture is not necessarily accurate. We don't know anything about how things "really" are; we are free to think that we can make free choices, because for all we know this might "really" be the case. Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

Kant In the Critique of Practical Reason and the Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals, Kant applies this same technique –using reason to analyze itself – to determine what moral choices we should make. Just as we cannot rely on our picture of the world for knowledge about how the world "really" is, so also we cannot rely on expectations about events in the world in developing moral principles. Kant tries to develop a moral philosophy that depends only on the fundamental concepts of reason. Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

Kant’s Intellectual Climate: Criticisms Some later thinkers have criticized Enlightenment philosophers like Kant for placing too much confidence in reason. Some have argued that rational analysis is not the best way to deal with moral questions. Further, some have argued that Enlightenment thinkers were pompous to think that they could discover the timeless truths of reason; in fact, their ideas were determined by their culture just as all other people’s are. Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals