Mathematical Structures for Computer Science Chapter 1.2 Copyright © 2006 W.H. Freeman & Co.MSCS SlidesFormal Logic
Propositions or statements are sentences that are either true or false. In logic, propositions are represented by the letters A, B, C, … Propositions can be combined into more complicated expressions known as well- formed formulas, or wffs. ◦ The connectives: and ( ), or ( ), implies ( ), and negation () Wffs are represented by the letters P, Q, R, … Section 1.2 Propositional Logic1
o A system for determining whether or not a particular logical argument is valid, using rules of inference (also known as propositional calculus.) o Definition of Argument: o A sequence of statements in which the conjunction of the initial statements (called the premises, or hypotheses) is said to imply the final statement (called the conclusion). o Presented symbolically as (P 1 Λ P 2 Λ... Λ P n ) Q where P 1, P 2,..., P n represent the hypotheses and Q represents the conclusion. Section 1.2 Propositional Logic2
What is a valid argument? When does Q logically follow from P 1, P 2,..., P n ? Informal answer: When the truth of the hypotheses guarantees the truth of the conclusion. Note: We need to be sure the hypotheses are related to the conclusion; not just any knowledge we might have about the conclusion Q. Example: ◦ P 1 : Neil Armstrong was the first human to step on the moon. ◦ P 2 : Mars is a red planet And the conclusion ◦ Q: No human has ever been to Mars. ◦ P 1, P 2, and Q are all true, but Q isn’t a logical consequence Section 1.2 Propositional Logic3
Definition of valid argument: In a formal logical system an argument is valid if, whenever the hypotheses are all true, the conclusion must also be true. i.e. (P 1 Λ P 2 Λ... Λ P n ) Q is a tautology. ◦ You must be able to logically deduce Q from the hypotheses How to arrive at a valid argument? ◦ Using a proof sequence Section 1.2 Propositional Logic4
Definition of Proof Sequence: A proof sequence is a sequence of wffs in which each wff is either a hypothesis or the result of applying one of the formal system’s derivation rules to earlier wffs in the sequence. Derivation rules allow you to rewrite a hypothesis in a more useful form, based on the equivalence relations from section one, or to derive new wffs from the old ones. Section 1.2 Propositional Logic5
Derivation rules for propositional logic Section 1.2 Propositional Logic6 Equivalence RulesInference Rules Allows individual wffs to be rewritten Allows new wffs to be derived Truth preserving rulesWork only in one direction
Certain pairs of wffs are equivalent, hence one can be substituted for the other with no change to truth values. The set of equivalence rules are summarized here: Let R and S be statement variables Section 1.2 Propositional Logic7 ExpressionEquivalent toAbbreviation for rule P V Q P Λ Q Q V P Q Λ P Commutative (comm) (P V Q) V R (P Λ Q) Λ R P V (Q V R) P Λ (Q Λ R) Associative (assoc) (P V Q) (P Λ Q) P Λ Q P V Q De Morgan’s Laws P QP V Q Implication (imp) P (P) Double Negation (dn) PQPQ(P Q) Λ (Q P) Equivalence (equ)
Inference rules allow us to add a new wffs to aproof sequence. If one or more wffs match an existing part of the proof sequence (this is the “from” part) you can deduce the second part and add to the proof. Note: Inference rules do not work in both directions, unlike equivalence rules. ◦ E.g., if you know R V S you can’t deduce R (or S). Section 1.2 Propositional Logic8 FromCan DeriveAbbreviation for rule R, R S SModus Ponens- mp R S, SR Modus Tollens- mt R, SR Λ SConjunction-con R Λ SR, SSimplification- sim RR V SAddition- add
Example for using Equivalence rule in a proof sequence: ◦ Simplify (A V B) V C 1. (A V B) V C 2. (A Λ B) V C1, De Morgan 3. (A Λ B) C2, imp Example of using Inference Rule ◦ If it is bright and sunny today, then I will wear my sunglasses. Modus Ponens ( given P, P S, conclude S) It is bright and sunny today. Therefore, I will wear my sunglasses. Modus Tollens(given P S, S, conclude P) I will not wear my sunglasses. Therefore, it is not bright and sunny today. Section 1.2 Propositional Logic9
Prove the argument A Λ (B C) Λ [(A Λ B) (D V C)] Λ B D ◦ First, write down all the hypotheses. 1. A 2. B C 3. (A Λ B) (D V C) 4. B Use the inference and equivalence rules to get at the conclusion D. 5. C2,4, mp 6. A Λ B1,4, con 7. D V C 3,6, mp 8. C V D7, comm 9. C D8, imp and finally 10. D5,9 imp The idea is to keep focused on the result and sometimes it is very easy to go down a longer path than necessary. Section 1.2 Propositional Logic10
Used to prove an argument of the form P 1 Λ P 2 Λ... Λ P n R Q Deduction method allows for the use of R as an additional hypothesis and thus prove P 1 Λ P 2 Λ... Λ P n Λ R Q Suppose you want to prove [(A B) Λ (B C)] (A C) Section 1.2 Propositional Logic11
Prove [(A B) Λ (B C)] (A C) Using deduction method, prove (A B) Λ (B C) Λ A C 1. A Bhyp 2. B Chyp 3. Ahyp 4. B1,3 mp 5. C2,4 mp The above is called the rule of Hypothetical Syllogism or hs for short. Many such other rules can be derived from existing rules which thus provide easier and faster proofs. Section 1.2 Propositional Logic12
These rules can be derived using the previous rules. They provide a faster way of proving arguments. Section 1.2 Propositional Logic13 FromCan DeriveName / Abbreviation P Q, Q RP R Hypothetical syllogism- hs P V Q, PQDisjunctive syllogism- ds P QQ P Contraposition- cont Q PP Q Contraposition- cont
Additional inference rules yield shorter proofs, but more rules to remember. Section 1.2 Propositional Logic14 FromCan DeriveName / Abbreviation PP Λ PSelf-reference – self P V PPSelf-reference – self (P Λ Q) RP (Q R) Exportation – exp P, PQInconsistency – inc P Λ (Q V R)(P Λ Q) V (P Λ R)Distributive - dist P V (Q Λ R)(P V Q) Λ (P V R)Distributive - dist
Prove that (P Q) (Q P) is a valid argument (called Contraposition – con). ◦ Hence prove, (P Q) Λ Q P (using deduction method). ◦ The above is true using the modus tollens inference rule. Prove P Λ P Q (called Inconsistency) 1. P hyp 2. P hyp 3. P V Q1, add 4. Q V P3, comm 5. (Q) V P4, dn 6. Q P5, imp: (A V B) (A B) 7. (Q)2, 6, mt: from ( P S, S ) get P 8. Q7, dn Section 1.2 Propositional Logic15
(A Λ B) Λ (C Λ A) Λ (C Λ B) A is an argument 1. (A Λ B)hyp 2. (C Λ A)hyp 3. (C Λ B)hyp 4. A V B1, De Morgan 5. B V A4, comm 6. B A5, imp 7. (C) V A2, De Morgan 8. C A7, imp 9. C V (B)3, De Morgan 10. (B) V C 9, comm 11. B C10, imp 12. B A8, 11, hs 13. (B A) Λ (B A)6, 12, con Section 1.2 Propositional Logic16
At this point, we have now to prove that (B A) Λ (B A) A Proof sequence 1. B Ahyp 2. B Ahyp 3. A B1, cont 4. A A3, 2, hs 5. A V A4, imp 6. A6, self Section 1.2 Propositional Logic17
To convert a verbal argument to a symbolic form so it can be tested for validity: “Symbolize” the argument using propositional wff’s Use the derivation rules for propositional logic to prove the argument is valid Example: “If interest rates drop, the housing market will improve. Either the federal discount rate will drop or the housing market will not improve. Interest rates will drop. Therefore the federal discount rate will drop.” Let I representInterest rates drop HrepresentThe housing market will improve F representThe federal discount rate will drop Then (I H) (F H) I F Section 1.2 Propositional Logic18
A proof sequence for (I H) (F H) I F 1. I Hhyp 2. F Hhyp 3. Ihyp 4. H F2, comm 5. H F4, imp 6. I F1, 5, hs 7. F5, 3, mp Section 1.2 Propositional Logic19
Russia was a superior power, and either France was not strong or Napoleon made an error. Napoleon did not make an error, but if the army did not fail, then France was strong. Hence the army failed and Russia was a superior power. Converting it to a propositional form using letters A, B, C and D A: Russia was a superior power B: France was strong B: France was not strong C: Napoleon made an errorC: Napoleon did not make an error D: The army failedD: The army did not fail Combining, the statements using logic (A Λ (B V C)) hypothesis C hypothesis (D B) hypothesis (D Λ A)conclusion Combining them, the propositional form is (A Λ (B V C)) Λ C Λ (D B) (D Λ A) Section 1.2 Propositional Logic20
Prove (A Λ (B V C)) Λ C Λ (D B) (D Λ A) Proof sequence 1. A Λ (B V C)hyp 2. Chyp 3. D Bhyp 4. A1, sim 5. B V C1, sim 6. C V B 5, comm 7. B2, 6, ds 8. B (D) 3, cont 9. (D) 7, 8, mp 10. D9, dn 11. D Λ A4, 10, con Section 1.2 Propositional Logic21
Prove the following arguments ◦ (A´ B´) Λ (A C) (B C) ◦ (Y Z´) Λ (X´ Y) Λ [Y (X W)] Λ (Y Z) (Y W) If the program is efficient, it executes quickly. Either the program is efficient, or it has a bug. However, the program does not execute quickly. Therefore it has a bug. (use letters E, Q, B) The crop is good, but there is not enough water. If there is a lot of rain or not a lot of sun, then there is enough water. Therefore the crop is good and there is a lot of sun. (use letters C, W, R, S) Section 1.2 Propositional Logic22
Write down the propositional form of the following argument: If my client is guilty, then the knife was in the drawer. Either the knife was not in the drawer or Jason Pritchard saw the knife. If the knife was not there on October 10, it follows that Jason Pritchard didn’t see the knife. Furthermore, if the knife was there on October 10, then the knife was in the drawer and also the hammer was in the barn. But we all know that the hammer was not in the barn. Therefore, ladies and gentlemen of the jury, my client is innocent. Section 1.2 Propositional Logic23