Petrie maps and Petrie configurations Jurij Kovič, University of Primorska, Slovenia EuroGIGA Final Conference Berlin, February 20, 2014.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
22C:19 Discrete Math Graphs Fall 2010 Sukumar Ghosh.
Advertisements

22C:19 Discrete Math Graphs Fall 2014 Sukumar Ghosh.
Midwestern State University Department of Computer Science Dr. Ranette Halverson CMPS 2433 – CHAPTER 4 GRAPHS 1.
Graph-02.
Bangalore conference, December, Rank 3-4 Coxeter Groups, Quaternions and Quasicrystals Mehmet Koca Department of Physics College of Science.
Introduction to Graphs
Extended Gaussian Images
Embeddings with all triangles faces Dan Archdeacon The University of Vermont.
Graphing r = θ on the Polar Coordinate Plane
Chapter 12: Surface Area and Volume of Solids
Surfaces and Topology Raymond Flood Gresham Professor of Geometry.
CHAPTER 5: CONVEX POLYTOPES Anastasiya Yeremenko 1.
Symmetric Group Sym(n) As we know a permutation  is a bijective mapping of a set A onto itself:  : A  A. Permutations may be multiplied and form the.
By: Andrew Shatz & Michael Baker Chapter 15. Chapter 15 section 1 Key Terms: Skew Lines, Oblique Two lines are skew iff they are not parallel and do not.
Realizability of Graphs Maria Belk and Robert Connelly.
Computational Geometry Seminar Lecture 1
Definition Hamiltonian graph: A graph with a spanning cycle (also called a Hamiltonian cycle). Hamiltonian graph Hamiltonian cycle.
Graph Colouring Lecture 20: Nov 25.
Definition Dual Graph G* of a Plane Graph:
Volume and Angle Structures on closed 3-manifolds Feng Luo Rutgers University Oct. 28, 2006 Texas Geometry/Topology conference Rice University.
Drawing of G. Planar Embedding of G Proposition Proof. 1. Consider a drawing of K 5 or K 3,3 in the plane. Let C be a spanning cycle. 2. If the.
Graph Theory Ch.5. Coloring of Graphs 1 Chapter 5 Coloring of Graphs.
CONFIGURATIONS FROM GRAPH-THEORETICAL VIEWPOINT Notes for a book Tomaž Pisanski and Brigitte Servatius Copyright (C) 2005.
K-Coloring k-coloring: A k-coloring of a graph G is a labeling f: V(G)  S, where |S|=k. The labels are colors; the vertices of one color form a color.
Curve Curve: The image of a continous map from [0,1] to R 2. Polygonal curve: A curve composed of finitely many line segments. Polygonal u,v-curve: A polygonal.
K-Coloring k-coloring: A k-coloring of a graph G is a labeling f: V(G)  S, where |S|=k. The labels are colors; the vertices of one color form a color.
The Fish-Penguin-Giraffe Algebra A synthesis of zoology and algebra.
Matthew Bowling Euler’s Theorem Mathfest Spring ‘15.
Graph Theory Chapter 6 Planar Graphs Ch. 6. Planar Graphs.
Planar Graphs Graph G is planar, if it can be “properly” drawn in the plane. In order to explain this informal notion we have to define embeddings of graphs.
Maps. Graphs on Surfaces We are mainly interested in embeddings of graphs on surfaces:  : G ! S. An embedding should be differentiated from immersion.
Chapter 1 Fundamental Concepts II Pao-Lien Lai 1.
Edge-disjoint induced subgraphs with given minimum degree Raphael Yuster 2012.
Copyright © Zeph Grunschlag, More on Graphs.
12. Polyhedra
3-Dimentional Figures Section 11.1.
5.2 Trees  A tree is a connected graph without any cycles.
1 Rainbow Decompositions Raphael Yuster University of Haifa Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. (2008), to appear.
Lines in the plane, slopes, and Euler’s formula by Tal Harel
Planar Graphs. A graph is called planar if it can be drawn in the plane in such a way that no two edges cross. Example of a planar graph: The clique on.
Euler’s characteristic and the sphere
Section 5.1 Rubber Sheet Geometry Discovering the Topological Idea of Equivalence by Distortion. “The whole of mathematics is nothing more than a refinement.
Planar Graphs Graph Coloring
Graph Colouring Lecture 20: Nov 25. This Lecture Graph coloring is another important problem in graph theory. It also has many applications, including.
Graph Theory and Applications
Planar Graphs Lecture 10: Oct 21. This Lecture Today we will talk about planar graphs, and how to color a map using 6 colors. Planar graphs Euler’s formula.
Lecture 10: Graph-Path-Circuit
DRILL How many sides does dodecagon have?
Ch 12 and 13 Definitions. 1. polyhedron A solid with all flat surfaces that enclose a single region of space.
Basic properties Continuation
Trees Thm 2.1. (Cayley 1889) There are nn-2 different labeled trees
Combinatorics Ramsey theory.  a precocious British mathematician, philosopher and economist  a problem in mathematical logic: can one always find order.
Section 12-1 Exploring Solids. Polyhedron Three dimensional closed figure formed by joining three or more polygons at their side. Plural: polyhedra.
Great Theoretical Ideas in Computer Science for Some.
Space Figures and Nets Section 6-1 Notes and vocabulary available on my home page.
COMPSCI 102 Introduction to Discrete Mathematics.
Math 3121 Abstract Algebra I Lecture 6 Midterm back over+Section 7.
Graphs. Representations of graphs : undirected graph An undirected graph G have five vertices and seven edges An adjacency-list representation of G The.
Great Theoretical Ideas In Computer Science
37TH ANNUAL AMATYC CONFERENCE A Modern Existence Proof Through Graphs
Goal 1: Using Properties of Polyhedra Goal 2: Using Euler’s Theorem
Polyhedra Mikhilichenko Yelena-Maths teacher
Polyhedra Mikhаilichenko Yelena-Maths teacher
Graph theory Definitions Trees, cycles, directed graphs.
Motivation and definitions
Vertical Angles Vertical angles are across from each other and are created by intersecting lines.
14 Chapter Area, Pythagorean Theorem, and Volume
Agenda Review Lecture Content: Shortest Path Algorithm
A Portrait of a Group on a Surface with Boundary
Locality In Distributed Graph Algorithms
Presentation transcript:

Petrie maps and Petrie configurations Jurij Kovič, University of Primorska, Slovenia EuroGIGA Final Conference Berlin, February 20, 2014

The aim of the talk is to explain how some maps (we will name them Petrie maps ) can be used to obtain examples of configurations (we will name them Petrie configurations ): Petrie maps Petrie configurations.

Motivation Goal: To develop a method for constructing examples of large configurations – with many symmetries. Question: How to do it? Idea: Use as a „starting point“ some class of combinatorial object with many symmetries (e.g. Platonic solids) and somehow „transform“ them into configurations.

1. Basic definitions Our topic connects two branches of mathematics, one old, one new: the theory of configurations has its: “classical age” “renaissance” “dark age” “golden age” 1990-now (B. Grünbaum, Configurations of points and lines) the theory of flag graphs of maps i s developing from around Let us briefly review some of their basic concepts.

incidence structure: a triple (B, P, I) consisting of B … the set of blocks B (or lines) P … the set of points P and I … an incidence relation, a subset of B x P

geometrical representation of incidence structure (B, P, I) : P and B are represented by points and lines in the Euclidean plane

In a lineal incidence structure each two lines intersect in at most one point.

A configuration (n k ) is: - a lineal incidence structure - consisting of n lines and n points; - each line is incident with k points, - each point is incident with k lines However, if only the condition of lineality is not fulfilled, we will call such an incidence structure a “ non-lineal (n k ) configuration”.

The Pappus configuration (one of the three (9 3 ) configurations) can be geometrically represented by points and lines in the Euclidean plane.

Some (n 3 ) configurations are not geometrically realizable by points and lines in the Euclidean plane, for example the Fano plane (7 3 ) :

map : a cellular embedding of a graph into a compact surface; it consists of the sets V of vertices, E of edges and F of faces polyhedral map : a map belonging to a polyhedron

flag Ф =(v,e,f) = a triple (vertex, edge, face) geometrically, flags can be represented as triangles (obtained by a barycentric subdivision of faces)

The three adjacent flags Ф 0, Ф 1, Ф 2 differ from Ф only in a vertex, an edge or a face.

flag graph F(M) of a map M; its vertices are flags, its edges (labeled 0,1,2 or colored blue, yellow and red) connect adjacent flags

Involutions s 0, s 1, s 2 carry each flag Ф of the flag graph F(M) into its three adjacent flags: Ф 0 = s 0 (Ф), Ф 1 = s 1 (Ф), Ф 2 = s 2 (Ф). They generate a group Mon(M) satisfying the relations: s 0 2 = s 1 2 = s 2 2 = (s 0 s 2 ) 2 = id.

The orbit of the flag Ф consists of all flags Ψ for which there is an edge-colors preserving automorphism of the flag graph F(M) sending Ф into Ψ. A k-orbit map has exactly k orbit of flags, e.g. a 1-orbit map has only 1 orbit of flags.

Example: the polyhedral net of a 10-orbit polyhedral map of the Archimedean solid ( ) called the snub cube.

2. Petrie walks and Petrie lines Definition 1. Choose any flag Ф in the flag graph F(M). Let (i, j, k) be any of the six permutations of the numbers (0,1,2). The corresponding Petrie walk is the sequence of flags (Φ, Φ i, (Φ i ) j, ((Φ i ) j ) k, (((Φ i ) j ) k ) i …).

An oriented Petry cycle is a Petrie walk in which the last flag is equal to the first one.

Definition 2. Choose any flag Ф in the flag graph F(M). Let (i, j, k) be any of the six permutations of the numbers (0,1,2). The cycle in F(M) whose vertices belong to the smallest oriented Petry cycle with length m ≡ 0 (mod 3) is the Petry cycle P i,j,k (Φ).

Proposition 1. Choose any flag Φ. There are at most three Petrie cycles incident with Φ. Proof. The following pairs of Petrie cycles are equal: P 0,1,2 (Φ) = P 2,1,0 (Φ), P 1,2,0 (Φ) = P 0,2,1 (Φ), P 2,0,1 (Φ) = P 1,0,2 (Φ).

Petrie walks and Petrie cycles may be represented as curves (meeting a flag Φ (v, e, f) in 1, 2 or 3 “arcs” near the points v, e, f)

Proposition 2. A flag Φ may be incident with 1, 2 or 3 Petrie cycles in 6 possible ways. There are 6 types of flags corresponding to the 6 ways how the Petrie cycles may meet a given flag.

Definition 3. A Petry cycle is called simple if it meets each flag of the flag graph F(M) at most once. Proposition 3. If all the Petry cycles are simple, each flag meets each Petrie cycle at most once (it is of the type I ).

Theorem 1. If M is a 1-orbit map then all the Petry cycles P in F(M) have the same length L(P). Proof. L(P 2,0,1 ( Φ )) = L(P 1,2,0 ( Φ)), since P 2,0,1 ( Φ ) and P 1,2,0 ( Φ) differ only in each third flag. L(P 1,2,0 ( Φ)) = L ( P 1,2,0 ( Φ 0 ) since Φ and Φ 0 are in the same orbit. L(P 0,1,2 ( Φ )) = L(P 1,2,0 ( Φ 0 )), since this is the same Petry cycle.

Definition 4. Given a Petrie cycle P i,j,k (Φ) = = (Φ, Φ i, (Φ i ) j, ((Φ i ) j ) k, (((Φ i ) j ) k ) i,… ) = = (Φ 1, Φ 2, Φ 3, Φ 4, Φ 5, … Φ 3m ) and a chosen flag Φ s of it the corresponding Petrie line is the set (with at most 3 elements): L i,j,k (Φ s ) = {Φ s, Φ s+ m(mod 3m), Φ s + 2m(mod 3m) }.

Some Petrie lines may be “degenerate” − incident with less than 3 points

Definition 4. A Petrie map is a map in which all the Petrie lines are non-degenerate. The corresponding incidence structure whose points correspond to flags of the flag graph F(M) and whose lines correspond to Petrie lines is called the Petrie configuration of M and is denoted P(M). Remark. It is possible to show that any such P(M) is really a non-lineal (n 3 )-configuration.

3. Existence of Petrie maps Proposition 5. If each Petry cycle in F(M) is simple, then M is a Petrie map. Proposition 6. If M is a 1-orbit map and at least one of its Petry cycles is simple, then all of its Petry cycles are simple, hence M is a Petrie map. Proof. If P 0,1,2 ( Φ ) is simple then P 1,2,0 ( Φ ) = P 1,2,0 ( Φ 0 ) = P 0,1,2 ( Φ ) is simple, and likewise P 2,0,1 ( Φ ) is simple, too. Proposition 7. All the polyhedral maps of the five Platonic solids are examples of Petrie maps. Proof. They are all 1-orbit maps; it suffices to show that they all have a simple Petrie cycle.

Octahedron and icosahedron have simple Petrie cycles:

The (n 3 ) configuration of dodecahedron is non-lineal:

Two Petrie lines of the same flag in a cube are the same

Petrie cycles of the tetrahedron

The incidence table of points and lines of the non-lineal configuration (24 3 ) of the tetrahedron

4. Structure of Petrie configurations From the above examples the structure of Petrie configurations could be guessed and then proven. Theorem 2. If all the Petrie cycles in F(M) has length 3m, then for any flag Φ : a) if m = 3(3n), then L 0,2,1 (3n) = L 2,0,1 (3n), b) if m = 3(3n +1), then Φ 1,0,2 (3n +1) = Φ 1,2,0 (3n + 1) c) if m = 3(3n + 2), then Φ 0,2,1 (3n+2) = Φ 2,0,1 (3n+2). Thus, every Petrie configuration is a non-lineal (n 3 ) configuration.

Proof. If m = 3(3n), then L 0,2,1 ( Φ ) = L 2,0,1 ( Φ ) = L 1,0,2 (Φ), since Φ 0,2,1 (3m) = Φ 2,0,1 (3m) for every m: if m = 3(3n +1), then Φ 1,0,2 (3n +1) = Φ 1,2,0 (3n + 1) if m = 3(3n + 2), then Φ 0,2,1 (3n+2) = Φ 2,0,1 (3n+2).

Also other (n 3 )-configurations, called s-Petrie configurations, can be obtained from maps: Their l ines L s ( Φ ) contain the s-th flags in the Petrie cycles P 0,1,2 ( Φ ), P 1,2,0 ( Φ ), P 2,0,1 ( Φ ).

At least for s = 2,3,4 the lines L s ( Φ ) are non- degenerate (contain 3 different elements). For other maps (e.g. on the torus) this is not always true.

3-Petrie lines in the cube satisfy the lineality condition, hence the corresponding 3-Petrie configuration is lineal.

5. Open questions, future work 1) Which maps of Archimedean solids have only simple Petrie circuits? 2) Which uniform solids are Petrie maps? 3) Study other examples of (n k )-configurations obtained by a similar method from k-regular graphs whose edges are labeled with 1,2,…,k, e.g. from Cayley graphs of some groups with k generators. Such configurations will very likely „inherit“ many symmetries from their „parents“.

Thank you!