Horgan and Tienson The Principle of Phenomenal Intentionality (PI): “There is a kind of intentionality, pervasive in human mental life, that is constitutively.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
© Michael Lacewing Innate ideas Michael Lacewing.
Advertisements

Consciousness and Thought: Wrap-Up Talk
Varieties of Representationalism David J. Chalmers.
The Varieties of Self- Awareness David Chalmers. Self-Awareness Self-awareness = awareness of oneself One is self-aware if one stands in a relation of.
LECTURE 6 COGNITIVE THEORIES OF CONSCIOUSNESS
CONSTRAINTS ON IMAGERY I David Pearson Room T10, William Guild Building
The Extended Mind.
Meditation IV God is not a Deceiver, Truth Criterion & Problem of Error.
“What Is It Like To Be a Bat?”. Depth Perception The world (visually) appears to us as though it is three-dimensional. Some things appear closer to us.
Phenomenology and Reflexivity Getting clear(er) about “self- representational” theories of consciousness.
Descartes’ rationalism
Philosophy of Mind Matthew Soteriou. Functionalism and Qualia Critics of functionalist accounts of the mental often appeal to thought experiments in which.
Chapter 1 Critical Thinking.
Concept innatism II: the case of substance Michael Lacewing
“Be kind, because everyone you meet is fighting a hard battle.” – Plato.
Meditations on First Philosophy
Huiming Ren Shandong University of China. What we could learn from the case of veridical perceptions.
Hillary Putnam Whichever way you cut it, meanings ain’t in the head.
The Cognitive Reliability Argument An argument first proposed some twelve years ago by philosopher Alvin Plantinga of the University of Notre Dame, who.
Is There Reason for Skepticism? Joe Cruz Williams College Philosophy and Cognitive Science Thanks to Jonathan Vogel, Melissa Barry, Alan White, Will Dudley,
Direct realism Michael Lacewing
Hume on Taste Hume's account of judgments of taste parallels his discussion of judgments or moral right and wrong.  Both accounts use the internal/external.
Indirect realism Michael Lacewing
Faith & Reason: Kierkegaard, Clifford, & Aquinas ~ slide 1
Multiple Realizability, Qualia and Natural Kinds Dr. Andrew Bailey Philosophy Department University of Guelph Guelph, Ontario N1G 2W1, Canada
Descartes on Certainty (and Doubt)
Meditation One What is the objective of the Meditations? Hint: look at second sentence of Med. I.
 The cosmological argument is, as it’s name sugessts (from the greek cosmos, meaning ‘universe’ or ‘world’). An a posteriori argument for the existence.
Definitions – John Dewey
CS 357 – Intro to Artificial Intelligence  Learn about AI, search techniques, planning, optimization of choice, logic, Bayesian probability theory, learning,
McGinn’s Mysterianism. This Week’s Visits  Tuesday, April 6: Robinson, Theisen, Tierney, Weiland  And: Those who missed earlier visits. You know who.
Philosophy of Mind Matthew Soteriou. Physicalism The physicalist answer to the question of the relation between the mental and the physical: The mental.
2013/2014 RELATIONS OF CHAPTER “EMOTIONS” (In the Book of Robert Nozick “Examined Life”) Lezione 22 31/3/14 by Gabriele Buratti & Maria Teresa Carini.
Philosophy of Religion Michael Lacewing
Embodied Cognition and Consciousness: A Bestiary Dr. Andrew Bailey Philosophy Department University of Guelph Guelph, Ontario N1G 2W1, Canada
CHAPTER FIVE: THE SOURCES OF KNOWLEDGE P H I L O S O P H Y A Text with Readings ELEVENTH EDITION M A N U E L V E L A S Q U E Z.
Ross Arnold, Winter 2015 Lakeside institute of Theology The Existence of God II February 20, 2015.
Intentionalism and Representational Qualitative Character Intentionalism and Representational Qualitative Character 14 th Annual Meeting of the Association.
ToK - Truth Does truth matter?.
Theories of Perception: Empirical Theory of Perception Berkeley’s Theory of Reality Direct Realism Moderate Thomistic Realism.
Sensory Experience and Representational Properties David Papineau King’s College London The Aristotelian Society 7 October 2013.
Persons, Minds and Brains
Philosophy 224 Persons and Morality: Pt. 1. Ah Ha! Dennett starts by addressing an issue we’ve observed in the past: the tendency to identify personhood.
John Locke ( ) Influential both as a philosopher (Essay Concerning Human Understanding) and as a political thinker (Two Treatises on Government)
This week’s aims: To set clear expectations regarding homework, organisation, etc. To re-introduce the debate concerning the mind-body problem To analyse.
1 12 Evolution and Rationalism. 2 Evolution and religion Evolution and religion The growth of evolutionary theory had provided a fatal injury to the pretension.
The Language of Thought : Part I Joe Lau Philosophy HKU.
BRAIN IN VATS ѕєяριℓ тυтι ѕєяριℓ тυтι Bilkent University, April 2008 вяαιη ιη ναтѕ вяαιη ιη ναтѕ q ɹɐ ıu.
Critical Thinking. Critical thinkers use reasons to back up their claims. What is a claim? ◦ A claim is a statement that is either true or false. It must.
LECTURE 19 THE COSMOLOGICAL ARGUMENT CONTINUED. THE QUANTUM MECHANICAL OBJECTION DEPENDS UPON A PARTICULAR INTERPRETATION WE MIGHT REASONABLY SUSPEND.
Unit 1 The Concept of Law. What is a Commonplace?  The set of everyday truths about a given subject matter providing us a shared subject matter for inquiry.
On Consciousness as Higher-Order Thought Charles Siewert Rice University.
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 8 Epistemology #1 By David Kelsey.
Blindsight, Zombies & Consciousness Jim Fahey Department of Cognitive Science Rensselaer Polytechnic Institute 10/4/2007.
Thomas Aquinas “On Being and Essence”. Saint Thomas Aquinas born ca. 1225; died 7 March 1274 Dominican.
Chapter 3: Knowledge The Rationalist’s Confidence: Descartes Introducing Philosophy, 10th edition Robert C. Solomon, Kathleen Higgins, and Clancy Martin.
The zombie argument: objections Michael Lacewing
Two central questions What does it mean to talk of, or believe in, God? –Is talk about God talk about something that exists independently of us? Or a way.
Philosophy of Religion
Intuition and deduction thesis (rationalism)
What do we mean by ‘mind’?
Consciousness and the Embodied Self Philosophy Department
Michael Lacewing Indirect realism Michael Lacewing © Michael Lacewing.
Problems for Identity Theory
Descartes’ proof of the external world
The zombie argument: responses
Do we directly perceive objects? (25 marks)
Is the concept of substance innate?
"CONSCIOUSNESS AND QUALITIES"
God is not a Deceiver, Truth Criterion & Problem of Error
Presentation transcript:

Horgan and Tienson The Principle of Phenomenal Intentionality (PI): “There is a kind of intentionality, pervasive in human mental life, that is constitutively determined by phenomenology alone” (2002, 520). HT call this sub-species of content phenomenal intentional content (PIC). They argue for PI by showing that “any two possible phenomenal duplicates have exactly similar intentional states vis-à-vis such content” (524). To do this they use a representative example: you and your phenomenal duplicate having the experience of seeing a picture hanging crooked. HT argue this phenomenology is sufficient to determine “conditions of accuracy,” which they equate with narrow truth conditions. They argue that not only perceptual experience but perceptual belief have this phenomenal intentional content. They argue that “a wide range of propositional-attitude states whose content goes well beyond the presentations of perceptual experience itself” (525) also have phenomenal intentional content. Thus, they say, any experiencing creature that undergoes “the distinctive phenomenal what-it’s-like of believing that a picture is hanging crooked” (526) thereby believes that there is a picture hanging crooked. Abstract Horgan and Tienson (2002) argue that some intentional content is constitutively determined by phenomenology alone. We argue this would require a certain kind of covariation of phenomenal states and intentional states which is not established by Horgan and Tienson’s arguments; that there is inadequate reason to think phenomenology determines perceptual belief; and that there is reason to doubt that phenomenology determines any species of non-perceptual intentionality. We also raise worries about the capacity of phenomenology to map onto intentionality in a way that would be appropriate for any determiner of content / fixer of truth conditions. Phenomenology and Intentionality Andrew Bailey T. Brad Richards Philosophy Department University of Guelph Guelph, Ontario N1G 2W1, Canada PIC is too strong for propositional attitudes “Mental states of the sort commonly cited as paradigmatically intentional (e.g. cognitive states such as beliefs, and conative states such as desires), when conscious, have phenomenal character that is inseparable from their intentional content” (HT 520). 1) Some kind of covariation relation is necessary to make PI plausible. 2) But any kind of covariation must be too strong for non-perceptual propositional attitudes. 3) Therefore, PI is too strong for non-perceptual propositional attitudes. It is implausible that everyone who entertains p has the same phenomenology. Consider, for example, HT’s example of wondering whether it is meatloaf for dinner tonight…. Compositionality Constraints “[S]ensory-phenomenal experience, by itself, determines conditions of accuracy” (HT 524). This requires a kind of isomorphism between phenomenology and intentionality such that the components of propositions which determine the proposition’s truth conditions are reflected by components of phenomenology which combine to determine truth conditions. At a minimum there must be some phenomenal difference to capture the different (narrow) truth conditions of all possible propositions. But since phenomenology doesn’t have the right kind of separable parts, and since its parts are not compositional like those of a proposition, it is not possible for it to be structurally isomorphic with a proposition. E.g.: consider HT’s Quinean example “Rabbits have tails.” PIC is too weak for perception The identification or conflation of phenomenal with phenomenal intentional perceptual states does not follow from HT’s argument. HT do not provide any reasons to think that a given phenomenal intentional content must always be associated with a given phenomenal state—that is, that fixing the narrow content of a perception determines its phenomenology. So their PIC is consistent with all the following having the same PIC as me (and each other) when looking at an orange: a spectrum-invert a blind person wearing Bach-y-Rita’s tactile stimulation machine a zombie So PIC does not support PI: phenomenology does not constitute content in the right way. What we require is some reason to think that orange experiences are ‘of’ orange because they are like this rather than like that (like other colour experiences, for example, or experiences from other sensory modalities): i.e. a kind of covariation.