Chapter 18: Conversion, Obversion, and Squares of Opposition

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Artificial Intelligence
Advertisements

Conditional Statements
Deductive Arguments: Categorical Logic
Logic Use mathematical deduction to derive new knowledge.
Operations (Transformations) On Categorical Sentences
1 Philosophy 1100 Title:Critical Reasoning Instructor:Paul Dickey Website:
Conditional Statements Geometry Chapter 2, Section 1.
Today’s Topics Introduction to Predicate Logic Venn Diagrams Categorical Syllogisms Venn Diagram tests for validity Rule tests for validity.
Critical Thinking Lecture 9 The Square of Opposition By David Kelsey.
Philosophy 103 Linguistics 103 Yet, still, Even further More and yet more, etc., ad infinitum, Introductory Logic: Critical Thinking Dr. Robert Barnard.
EDUCTION.
Categorical Propositions
Categorical Syllogisms Always have two premises Consist entirely of categorical claims May be presented with unstated premise or conclusion May be stated.
Syllogistic Logic 1. C Categorical Propositions 2. V Venn Diagram 3. The Square of Opposition: Tradition / Modern 4. C Conversion, Obversion, Contraposition.
Immediate Inference Three Categorical Operations
Chapter 9 Categorical Logic w07
CSCI 115 Chapter 2 Logic. CSCI 115 §2.1 Propositions and Logical Operations.
Discrete Mathematics and Its Applications
Categorical Propositions To help us make sense of our experience, we humans constantly group things into classes or categories. These classifications are.
A Brief Summary for Exam 1 Subject Topics Propositional Logic (sections 1.1, 1.2) –Propositions Statement, Truth value, Proposition, Propositional symbol,
CATEGORICAL PROPOSITIONS, CHP. 8 DEDUCTIVE LOGIC VS INDUCTIVE LOGIC ONE CENTRAL PURPOSE: UNDERSTANDING CATEGORICAL SYLLOGISMS AS THE BUILDING BLOCKS OF.
Philosophy 148 Chapter 7. AffirmativeNegative UniversalA: All S are PE: No S is P ParticularI: Some S is PO: Some S is not P.
Barnett/Ziegler/Byleen Finite Mathematics 11e1 Chapter 7 Review Important Terms, Symbols, Concepts 7.1. Logic A proposition is a statement (not a question.
Conditional Statements Conditional Statement: “If, then” format. Converse: “Flipping the Logic” –Still “if, then” format, but we switch the hypothesis.
Philosophy 103 Linguistics 103 Yet, still, Even further More and yet more, ad infinitum, Introductory Logic: Critical Thinking Dr. Robert Barnard.
Lecture Propositional Equivalences. Compound Propositions Compound propositions are made by combining existing propositions using logical operators.
AIM: WHAT IS AN INDIRECT PROOF?
Strict Logical Entailments of Categorical Propositions
4 Categorical Propositions
© 2010 Pearson Prentice Hall. All rights reserved. CHAPTER 3 Logic.
2.2.1 Analyze Conditional Statements and Proof Chapter 2: Reasoning and Proof.
CATEGORICAL SYLLOGISMS
Critical Thinking Lecture 9 The Square of Opposition
2.1 Conditional Statements Goal 1: Recognizing Conditional Statements Goal 2: Using Point, Line, and Plane Postulates CAS 1,3.
Midterm Practice Famous Fallacies, TFTD, Hurley
Chapter 13: Categorical Propositions. Categorical Syllogisms (p. 141) Review of deductive arguments –Form –Valid/Invalid –Soundness Categorical syllogisms.
Practice Quiz 3 Hurley 4.3 – 4.6.
Logic The Lost Art of Argument. Logic - Review Proposition – A statement that is either true or false (but not both) Conjunction – And Disjunction – Or.
Chapter 19: Living in the Real World. Introductory Remarks (p. 190) The joy and misery of ordinary English is that you can say the same thing in many.
Inverse, Contrapositive & indirect proofs Sections 6.2/6.3.
The Traditional Square of Opposition
Midterm Practice Famous Fallacies, TFTD, Hurley
Lesson 2-1 Conditional Statements 1 Lesson 2-3 Conditional Statements.
1 Propositional Proofs 1. Problem 2 Deduction In deduction, the conclusion is true whenever the premises are true.  Premise: p Conclusion: (p ∨ q) 
Categorical Propositions Chapter 5. Deductive Argument A deductive argument is one whose premises are claimed to provide conclusive grounds for the truth.
Simple Logic.
Chapter 1 Logic and Proof.
Further Immediate Inferences: Categorical Equivalences
Today’s Topics Introduction to Predicate Logic Venn Diagrams
Famous Fallacies, TFTD, Hurley
Practice Quiz 3 Hurley
2-2 Conditional Statements
Famous Fallacies, TFTD, Hurley
4.1 The Components of Categorical Propositions
Categorical Propositions
Philosophy 1100 Class #8 Title: Critical Reasoning
Critical Thinking Lecture 9 The Square of Opposition
Philosophy 1100 Title: Critical Reasoning Instructor: Paul Dickey
4 Categorical Propositions
A Brief Summary for Exam 1
Categorical propositions
(1.4) An Introduction to Logic
4 Categorical Propositions
“Only,” Categorical Relationships, logical operators
5 Categorical Syllogisms
X X X X Logical relations among categorical propositions S P S P S P
1.3 Propositional Equivalences
CHAPTER 3 Logic.
4 Categorical Propositions
Practice Quiz 3 Hurley 4.3 – 4.6.
Presentation transcript:

Chapter 18: Conversion, Obversion, and Squares of Opposition

Conversion, Obversion, and Contraposition (pp. 181-183) Two statement forms are logically equivalent if and only if they are true under exactly the same circumstances You will need to recognize logically equivalent forms of categorical propositions to deal with syllogisms in ordinary English (Chapter 19).

Conversion, Obversion, and Contraposition (pp. 181-183) To convert, switch the positions of the subject and predicate terms. The converse is logically equivalent only for universal negative and particular affirmative propositions. “No S are P” is logically equivalent to “No P are S.” “Some S are P” is logically equivalent to “Some P are S.”

Conversion, Obversion, and Contraposition (pp. 181-183) Complementary classes and complementary terms The complement of a class contains all objects not contained in the original class. Sometimes the complementary class is limited by an assumed context. The complement of the class of senators contains everything that is not a senator. If the assumed context is members of Congress, the complement of senators is representatives. For a term T, it’s complement is non-T. In ordinary English, the complement of a term often, although not always, has a preface such as in- or un-. ‘Flammable’ and ‘inflammable’ are synonyms, for example.

Conversion, Obversion, and Contraposition (pp. 181-183) To obvert, change the quality of a proposition from affirmative to negative or negative to affirmative, and replace the predicate with its complement. Every categorical proposition is equivalent to its obverse. “All S are P” is logically equivalent to “No S are non-P. “No S are P” is logically equivalent to “All S are non-P.” “Some S are P” is logically equivalent to “Some S are not non-P.” “Some S are not P” is logically equivalent to “Some S are non-P.”

Conversion, Obversion, and Contraposition (pp. 181-183) To form the contrapositive, replace the subject and predicate terms with their complements and convert. The contrapositive is logically equivalent only for universal affirmative and particular negative propositions. In those cases in which the contrapositive is logically equivalent to the given, it can be derived by successive uses of conversion and obversion. See p. 183.

The Boolean Square of Opposition (pp. 183-185) Squares of opposition are graphic representations of immediate inferences that can be drawn given the truth or falsehood of a categorical proposition. An immediate inference is made without appealing to another proposition. On the Boolean Square, A and O propositions and I and E propositions are contradictories. Two statements are contradictories if and only if the truth of one entails the falsehood of the other.

The Boolean Square of Opposition (pp. 183-185) The Boolean square looks like this:

The Aristotelian Square of Opposition (pp. 183-185) The Aristotelian interpretation of categorical propositions holds that universal propositions have existential import. A statement has existential import if and only if its truth requires that the subject class has at least one member. A universal proposition in effect also assets its corresponding particular proposition. A: All S are P and some S are P. E: No S are P and some S are not P.

The Aristotelian Square of Opposition (pp. 183-185) A and O propositions and I and E propositions are contradictories. A and E propositions are contraries. Two statements are contraries if it is possible for both to be false, but it is not possible for both to be true. An I proposition is the subaltern of an A proposition, and an O proposition is the subaltern of an E proposition Subalternation is a relation between a universal proposition and its corresponding particular proposition such that if the universal is true, the particular is also true. I and O propositions are subcontraries. Two statements are subcontraries if it is possible for both to be true, but it is not possible for both to be false.

The Aristotelian Square of Opposition (pp. 183-185) The Aristotelian Square looks like this:

The Aristotelian Square of Opposition (pp. 183-185) On the Aristotelian Interpretation, given the truth of a universal proposition, you can determine the truth value of every other statement on the square. Given the falsehood of a universal, you can only determine that its contradictory is true. Given the falsehood of a particular proposition, you can determine the truth value of every other statement on the square. Given the truth of a particular, you can only determine that its contradictory is false.

The Aristotelian Square of Opposition (pp. 183-185) Assume true: False False True

The Aristotelian Square of Opposition (pp. 183-185) False True True Assume false:

The Aristotelian Square of Opposition (pp. 183-185) Assume false True

The Aristotelian Square of Opposition (pp. 183-185) True Assume false

Squares and Equivalences Together You can combine considerations of equivalent forms with the squares “Some S are not non-P” is logically equivalent to “Some S are P. So, if that statement is true, on either square you can infer that “No S are P” is false. “All non-P are non-S” is logically equivalent to “All S are P.” If that statement is true: On the Boolean square you can infer only that “Some S are not P” is false. On the Aristotelian square you can infer that “Some S are not P” is false, that “Some S are P” is true, and that “No S are P” is false.