Quantum Mechanics: Interpretation and Philosophy Significant content from: “Quantum Mechanics and Experience” by David Z. Albert, Harvard University Press.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Quantum Computation and Quantum Information – Lecture 2
Advertisements

Lecture Outline Chapter 30 Physics, 4th Edition James S. Walker
The photon, the quantum of light
Actually, we need not speak of particles at all. For many experiments it is more convenient to speak of matter waves... The two pictures are of course.
Chapter 15: Duality of Matter Did you read chapter 15 before coming to class? A.Yes B.No.
QUANTUM MECHANICS Probability & Uncertainty 1.Probability 2.Uncertainty 3.Double-slit photons.
Quantum Mechanics: The Stern-Gerlach Experiment (1921)
Philosophy 024: Big Ideas Prof. Robert DiSalle Talbot College 408, x85763 Office Hours: Monday and Wednesday.
Gaitskell PH0008 Quantum Mechanics and Special Relativity Lecture ?? (Quantum Mechanics) TEST FILE Prof Rick Gaitskell Department of Physics Brown.
Lecture 4 - Feynmans thought experiments Things on a very small scale behave like nothing we have direct experience about. Even the experts do not uderstand.
Quantum Mechanics 102 Tunneling and its Applications.
Quantum Cryptography Prafulla Basavaraja CS 265 – Spring 2005.
Quantum Computation and Quantum Information – Lecture 2 Part 1 of CS406 – Research Directions in Computing Dr. Rajagopal Nagarajan Assistant: Nick Papanikolaou.
Experimental Quantum Teleportation Quantum systems for Information Technology Kambiz Behfar Phani Kumar.
Quantum theory and Consciousness This is an interactive discussion. Please feel free to interrupt at any time with your questions and comments.
CS4600/5600 Biometrics and Cryptography UTC/CSE
Modern Physics lecture 3. Louis de Broglie
6. Atomic and Nuclear Physics Chapter 6.5 Quantum theory and the uncertainty principle.
Introductory Video Quantum Mechanics Quantum Mechanics.
Quantum Mechanics. What is Quantum Physics? Quantum physics takes into account every possible outcome of measurement of physical properties  Quantum.
Alice and Bob’s Excellent Adventure
Quantum Information, Communication and Computing Jan Kříž Department of physics, University of Hradec Králové Doppler Institute for mathematical physics.
Institute of Technical Physics Entanglement – Beamen – Quantum cryptography The weird quantum world Bernd Hüttner CPhys FInstP DLR Stuttgart.
In 1887,when Photoelectric Effect was first introduced by Heinrich Hertz, the experiment was not able to be explained using classical principles.
School of something FACULTY OF OTHER School of Physics and Astronomy FACULTY OF MATHEMATICAL AND PHYSICAL SCIENCES Nonlocality of a single particle Jacob.
From the previous discussion on the double slit experiment on electron we found that unlike a particle in classical mechanics we cannot describe the trajectory.
Quantum Mechanics: Interpretation and Philosophy Significant content from: “Quantum Mechanics and Experience” by David Z. Albert, Harvard University Press.
QUANTUM TELEPORTATION
By Ryan Deetscreek and Greg Goettner
Extending the Definition of Exponents © Math As A Second Language All Rights Reserved next #10 Taking the Fear out of Math 2 -8.
1 3/10 Day 16: Questions? Hidden Variables Local Realism & EPR “ The problems of language here are really serious. We wish to speak in some way about the.
Quantum Theory Chapter 5. Lecture Objectives Indicate what is meant by the duality of matter. Indicate what is meant by the duality of matter. Discuss.
It’s all done with Mirrors Many of the predictions of quantum mechanics are verified with ordinary matter particles (like electrons), but these experiments.
PRESENTED BY MIDHUN.T - EC 3 - S 61 TOPIC – QUANTUM TELEPORTATION Presented by - MIDHUN T EC 3, S 6 ROLL NO. 20 Reg no
Weird Atoms and Strange Photons The Quantum Nature of the Universe Hiro Miyake Spark! March 10, 2012.
Wave-Particle Duality - the Principle of Complementarity The principle of complementarity states that both the wave and particle aspects of light are fundamental.
Early quantum optics Blackbody radiation Planck 1900: EM wave amplitudes/energies work as though they were quantized Photoelectric effect: Einstein.
Bohr Model of Atom Bohr proposed a model of the atom in which the electrons orbited the nucleus like planets around the sun Classical physics did not agree.
Quantum mechanical phenomena. The study between quanta and elementary particles. Quanta – an indivisible entity of a quantity that has the same value.
Quantum Cryptography Slides based in part on “A talk on quantum cryptography or how Alice outwits Eve,” by Samuel Lomonaco Jr. and “Quantum Computing”
Wednesday, October 31 Ford Final Chapter (10). Agenda Announce: –Test Wednesday –Office Hours probably busy…better book appt. –Read Chs. 1-3 of Vilekin.
ATOMIC orbitals!. When the a planet moves around the sun, you can plot a definite path for it which is called an orbit. A simple view of the atom looks.
Quantum Mechanics1 Schrodinger’s Cat. Quantum Mechanics2 A particular quantum state, completely described by enough quantum numbers, is called a state.
Light and the Problem of Measurement 20 th Century physics changed science by realizing that you can only know something if you can measure it. In some.
Werner Heisenberg.
Quantum Theory By: Brian Williams. Blackbody Radiation Around the turn of the 20 th century, physicists were studying the total energy carried by all.
 In this packet we will look at:  The meaning of acceleration  How acceleration is related to velocity and time  2 distinct types acceleration  A.
R.Kass/F02 P416 Lecture 1 1 Lecture 1 Probability and Statistics Introduction: l The understanding of many physical phenomena depend on statistical and.
Physics Lecture 10 2/22/ Andrew Brandt Monday February 22, 2010 Dr. Andrew Brandt 1.HW4 on ch 5 is due Monday 3/1 2.HW5 on ch 6 will be.
Page 1 COMPSCI 290.2: Computer Security “Quantum Cryptography” including Quantum Communication Quantum Computing.
Modern Physics lecture X. Louis de Broglie
The Transactional Interpretation: an introduction ©2012 R. E. Kastner.
Basic Concepts Absolute Size The Superposition Principle Copyright – Michael D. Fayer, 2007 Size Classical MechanicsQuantum Mechanics RelativeAbsolute.
Quantum Mechanics 102 Tunneling and its Applications.
Cohesion : A SENSE OF FLOW Coherence : A SENSE OF THE WHOLE 王詳勛 & 張鴻翌.
Quantum Measurements: some technical background “Measurement postulate” “Projection postulate” The two aspects of measurement Density matrices, environments,
Phy107 Fall From Last Time… Today Superposition of wave functions Indistinguishability Electron spin: a new quantum effect The Hydrogen atom and.
1 HEINSENBERG’S UNCERTAINTY PRINCIPLE “It is impossible to determine both position and momentum of a particle simultaneously and accurately. The product.
14.2 Electrons in the atom  Each different element has its own characteristic pattern of colors called a spectrum.  The colors of clothes, paint, and.
COMPSCI 290.2: Computer Security
Quantum Theory Chapter 27.
Quantum Information Promises new insights Anthony J
Postulates of Bohr model
Quantum Teleportation
Double Slit Experiment
Heisenberg Uncertainty
Schrödinger Equation Outline Wave Equations from ω-k Relations
Total Energy is Conserved.
Quantum Mechanics: Interpretation and Philosophy
Presentation transcript:

Quantum Mechanics: Interpretation and Philosophy Significant content from: “Quantum Mechanics and Experience” by David Z. Albert, Harvard University Press (1992). Main Concepts: -- complementarity -- the uncertainty principle -- superposition -- collapse of the wavefunction -- the measurement problem

Color Hardness s h w b Assume electrons have a “color” and a “hardness” property (which we can accurately measure). Assume the “color” of an electron can be either black (b) or white (w). Assume the “hardness” of an electron can be either hard (h) or soft (s). (discrete values -- quantization) Color: Hardness: measurement

Lets do something easy: say we measure that an electron is white e - e - then if we measure its color again, we will find it is white (same for black, same for “hardness” properties) (our measuring device is reliable)

Are the color and hardness properties of an electron correlated? Hardness s h No: 50% of white electrons are hard w 50% knowing the color of an electron tells us nothing about its hardness (and no additional information helps)

Now assume a white electron emerges from the soft aperture of a hardness box (50% will do so). e - Let us measure the color e - 50% somehow the hardness box has tampered with the color value !

Color and Hardness b+h w+h b+s w+s Can we build a “color and hardness” box? This box would need to consist of a hardness box and a color box. But the hardness measurement scrambles the color, and vice versa. To say “the color of this electron is now such-and- such and the hardness of this electron is now such- and-such” seems to be fundamentally beyond our means (uncertainly principle: color and hardness are incompatible physical properties)

the “black box” is just a fancy mirror that makes the two paths coincide If we feed an s (or an h) electron in, it emerges along the h and s path, unchanged.

Use a w electron and measure hardness. w Find 50% h and 50% s

Use a h electron and measure color. h Find 50% w and 50% b

Use a w electron and measure color. w This device is just a fancy hardness box (it is a hardness box with a few harmless mirrors), and we know a hardness measurement scrambles the color.

Use a w electron and measure color. w Find 100% w !!!

Let us add a movable wall that absorbs electrons Slide the wall into place: 1.) 50% reduction in the number of electrons emerging along the h and s path 2.) Of the electrons that emerge, their color is now scrambled: 50% w and 50% b. w What can possibly be going on ?

Consider an electron which passes through the apparatus when the sliding wall is out. Does it take route h ? No, because h electrons have 50/50 b/w color statistics. w w Does it take route s ? No, same reason. Can it somehow have taken both routes ? No: if we look to see where the electron is inside the apparatus, we find that 50% of the time it is on route h, and 50% of the time it is on route s. We never find two electrons inside, or two halves of a single, split electron, or anything like that. There isn’t any sense in which the electron seems to be taking both routes. Can it have taken neither route? No: if we put sliding walls in place to block both routes, nothing gets through at all. But these are all the logical possibilities that we have any notion whatever of how to entertain !

What can these electrons be doing? Electrons would seem to have modes of being available to them which are quite unlike what we know how to think about. The name of this new mode (which is just a name for something we don’t understand) is superposition. What we say about an initially white electron which is now passing through our apparatus (with the wall out) is that it’s not on h and not on s and not on both and not on neither, but, rather, that it’s in a superposition of being on h and being on s. And what this means (other than “none of the above”) we don’t know.

We know, by experiment, that electrons emerge from the hard aperture of a hardness box if and only if they’re hard electrons when they enter that box. When a white electron is fed into a hardness box, it emerges neither through the hard aperture nor through the soft one nor through both nor through neither. So, it follows that a white electron can’t be a hard one, or a soft one, or (somehow) both, or neither. To say that an electron is white must be just the same as to say that it’s in a superposition of being hard and soft. Why can’t we say “the color of this electron is now such-and-such and the hardness of this electron is now such-and-such”? It isn’t at all a matter of our being unable to simultaneously know what the color and the hardness of a certain electron is (that is: it isn’t a matter of ignorance). It’s deeper than that.

Why is quantum mechanics a probabilistic theory? If it could ever be said of a white electron that a measurement of its hardness will with certainty produce the outcome (say) “soft”, that would be inconsistent with what we know (that it’s in a superposition of hard and soft) On the other hand, our experience is that every hardness measurement whatsoever either comes out “hard” or it comes out “soft”. So apparently the outcome of a hardness measurement on a white electron has got to be a matter of probability !

Elitzer-Vaidman bomb testing problem ww We can tell whether or not the wall is in path s

Elitzer-Vaidman bomb testing problem ww Assume the wall is actually a very sensitive bomb, so sensitive that if an electron hits it, it will explode. How can we detect the presence of the bomb without setting it off ??

Elitzer-Vaidman bomb testing problem w 50% of the time (compared to the bomb not being there) no particle emerges along h and s. The bomb explodes. 25% of the time, we get a w electron out at h and s. We learn nothing (same result as bomb being absent) 25% of the time, we get a b electron out at h and s. We have detected the presence of the bomb without touching it !!!! (interaction-free measurement)

Use a w electron and measure color. w Find 100% w Actually, this device does nothing, so of course the color doesn’t change. This device doesn’t measure hardness, because when the electron exits the device, we don’t know which path it followed! We erased the hardness information by recombining the paths. In this context the bomb acts as a measures device – it tells us which path (hence which hardness value) the electron took.

e - e - incoming electron outgoing electron hardness measurement readyhardsoft

Niels Bohr (Nobel Prize 1922): Quantum mechanics does not describe how nature is but rather articulates what we can say about nature. “We must only discuss the outcomes of measurements.” Expressed in modern language, this means that quantum mechanics is a science of knowledge, of information.

Suppose we accept that collapse happens (since this is consistent with our experience that measurements yield definitive outcomes). We could then ask, when does collapse occur? Eugene Wigner (Nobel Prize 1963) proposed an answer in 1961: Collapse occurs precisely at the level of consciousness, and perhaps, moreover, consciousness is always the agent that brings it about. (this doesn’t really help)

When does collapse occur? Suppose that Alice has a theory about collapse: collapse happens immediately after the electron exits the measurement box. And suppose that Bob has another theory about collapse: collapse happens later, for example when a human retina or optic nerve or brain gets involved. Can we decide who is right empirically, that is, by performing some experiment?

Here’s how to start: Feed a black electron into a hardness device and give it enough time to pass through. If Alice is right, the state of the system is now either Can we decide who is right empirically, that is, by performing some experiment? or (with 50% prob.) whereas if Bob is right, the state of the system is currently so all we need to do is to figure out a way to distinguish, by means of a measurement, these two cases: In one case the pointer points in a particular (but as yet unknown) direction, and in the other case the pointer isn’t pointing in any particular direction at all.

What if we measure the position of the tip of the pointer? That is, lets measure where the pointer is pointing. This won’t work. If Alice is right, of course we will find a 50/50 chance of finding the pointer “pointing-at-hard” vs. “pointing-at-soft”. This is because, according to Alice, the pointer is already in one of those two states. But if Bob is right, then a measurement of the position of the tip of the pointer will have a 50% change of collapsing the wavefunction of the pointer onto the “pointing-at-hard” state, and 50% change of collapsing it to “pointing-at- soft”. Therefore the probability of any given outcome of a measurement of the position of the pointer will be the same for both these theories; and so this isn’t the sort of measurement we are looking for.

What if we measure the hardness of the electron? This won’t work. What if we measure the color of the electron? This won’t work. These arguments establish that different conjectures about precisely where and precisely when collapse occurs cannot be empirically distinguished from one another. And so the best we can do at present is to try to think of precisely where and precisely when collapses might possibly occur (that is, without contradicting what we do know to be true by experiment). But it turns out to be hard to do even that.

Schroedinger’s Cat Wigner’s Friend

Quantum Cryptography: how to communicate without eavesdropping (from S.J. Lomonaco, Jr., Key idea: How to determine if Eve is listening to Alice and Bob’s conversation?

Quantum Cryptography: how to communicate without eavesdropping (from S.J. Lomonaco, Jr., Key idea: How to determine if Eve is listening to Alice and Bob’s conversation? Alice Bob Eve

This is our hardness value (hard/soft) This is our color value (black/white)

Quantum Teleportation Classical information can be copied any number of times, but perfect copying of quantum information is impossible, a result known as the no-cloning theorem, which was proved in 1982 by Wootters and Zurek of Los Alamos National Laboratory. (If we could clone a quantum state, we could use the clones to violate Heisenberg’s Uncertainty Principle.)

Quantum Teleportation Quantum mechanics seems to make such a teleportation scheme impossible in principle. Heisenberg’s uncertainty principle rules that one cannot know both the precise position of an object and its momentum at the same time. Thus, one cannot perform a perfect scan of the object to be teleported; the location or velocity of every atom and electron would be subject to errors. (In Star Trek the “Heisenberg Compensator” somehow miraculously overcomes this difficulty.) However, in 1993 physicists discovered a theoretical way to use quantum mechanics itself for teleportation. They used entanglement to circumvent the limitations imposed by Heisenberg’s uncertainty principle without violating it.

Entangled Pair laser beam (photon) crystal Occasionally a single UV photon is converted into two photons of lower energy, one vertically polarized and one horizontally polarized. If these two photons emerge along the cone intersection (green areas), neither of them has a definite polarization. Why? Indistinguishability (7 th postulate, photons are bosons).

Feynman(1965 Nobel Prize)’s Rules for interference If two or more indistinguishable processes can lead to the same final event (particle could take either path), then add their complex amplitudes and square, to find the probability: P = | A 1 +A 2 | 2 ≈ | e ikL 1 + e ikL 2 | 2 ≈ 1 + cos k(L 1 -L 2 ) If multiple distinguishable processes occur, find the real probability of each, and then add: P = | A 1 | 2 + |A 2 | 2 ≈ | e ikL 1 | 2 + | e ikL 2 | 2 ≈ 1 If there is any way – even in principle – to tell which process occurred, then there can be no interference (if you knew which path the particle came from, you’d see a randomized color) !

Entangled Pair Photon 1 does not have a definite polarization, but its polarization is complementary to that of photon 2. Measurement of the polarization of photon 1 will collapse photon 2 into the opposite polarization (action at a distance).

Quantum Teleportation No cloning allowed, so how can we teleport a photon? Answer: we will use an entangled pair of photons (A and B) to teleport a photon X from Alice to Bob. Quick summary: Alice begins with photon X but does not know what its properties are (because if she measured it, its properties might change!). She teleports it to Bob, which destroys her “copy”. Bob ends up with photon X.

Quantum Teleportation

Hardness s h h black box h and s sliding wall track s

general outline: -David Z. Albert book chapter 1 -collapse postulate -Schroedinger’s cat -bomb detection