Frank Cowell: Microeconomics Game Theory: Basics MICROECONOMICS Principles and Analysis Frank Cowell March 2004.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
The Basics of Game Theory
Advertisements

5. Combining simultaneous and sequential moves.
Introduction to Game Theory
BASICS OF GAME THEORY. Recap Decision Theory vs. Game Theory Rationality Completeness Transitivity What’s in a game? Players Actions Outcomes Preferences.
1 Game Theory. 2 Definitions Game theory -- formal way to analyze interactions among a group of rational agents behaving strategically Agents – players.
© 2009 Institute of Information Management National Chiao Tung University Game theory The study of multiperson decisions Four types of games Static games.
Overview... Consumption: Basics The setting
Chapter Twenty-Eight Game Theory. u Game theory models strategic behavior by agents who understand that their actions affect the actions of other agents.
Non-Cooperative Game Theory To define a game, you need to know three things: –The set of players –The strategy sets of the players (i.e., the actions they.
Chapter 6 Game Theory © 2006 Thomson Learning/South-Western.
Chapter 6 Game Theory © 2006 Thomson Learning/South-Western.
EKONOMSKA ANALIZA PRAVA. Game Theory Outline of the lecture: I. What is game theory? II. Elements of a game III. Normal (matrix) and Extensive (tree)
Frank Cowell: General Equilibrium Basics GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM: BASICS MICROECONOMICS Principles and Analysis Frank Cowell Almost essential A Simple Economy.
Multi-player, non-zero-sum games
1 Deter Entry. 2 Here we see a model of deterring entry by an existing monopoly firm. We will also introduce the notion of a sequential, or dynamic, game.
Lecture 2A Strategic form games
Game Theory: Strategy and Equilibrium
Game Theory: An Introduction Text: An Introduction to Game Theory by Martin J. Osborne.
Chapter 11 Game Theory and the Tools of Strategic Business Analysis.
Games What is ‘Game Theory’? There are several tools and techniques used by applied modelers to generate testable hypotheses Modeling techniques widely.
An Introduction to Game Theory Part I: Strategic Games
2008/02/06Lecture 21 ECO290E: Game Theory Lecture 2 Static Games and Nash Equilibrium.
Chapter 6 © 2006 Thomson Learning/South-Western Game Theory.
A camper awakens to the growl of a hungry bear and sees his friend putting on a pair of running shoes, “You can’t outrun a bear,” scoffs the camper. His.
Chapter 12 Choices Involving Strategy McGraw-Hill/Irwin Copyright © 2008 by The McGraw-Hill Companies, Inc. All Rights Reserved.
Frank Cowell: Microeconomics Games: Mixed Strategies MICROECONOMICS Principles and Analysis Frank Cowell Almost essential Game Theory: Strategy and Equilibrium.
Basics on Game Theory For Industrial Economics (According to Shy’s Plan)
Chapter Twenty-Eight Game Theory. u Game theory models strategic behavior by agents who understand that their actions affect the actions of other agents.
BEE3049 Behaviour, Decisions and Markets Miguel A. Fonseca.
1 Game Theory Here we study a method for thinking about oligopoly situations. As we consider some terminology, we will see the simultaneous move, one shot.
Game Theory Here we study a method for thinking about oligopoly situations. As we consider some terminology, we will see the simultaneous move, one shot.
An introduction to game theory Today: The fundamentals of game theory, including Nash equilibrium.
QR 38, 2/22/07 Strategic form: dominant strategies I.Strategic form II.Finding Nash equilibria III.Strategic form games in IR.
Game Applications Chapter 29. Nash Equilibrium In any Nash equilibrium (NE) each player chooses a “best” response to the choices made by all of the other.
EC941 - Game Theory Francesco Squintani Lecture 3 1.
Today: Some classic games in game theory
Social Choice Session 7 Carmen Pasca and John Hey.
Intermediate Microeconomics
Dynamic Games of complete information: Backward Induction and Subgame perfection - Repeated Games -
McGraw-Hill/Irwin Copyright  2008 by The McGraw-Hill Companies, Inc. All rights reserved. GAME THEORY, STRATEGIC DECISION MAKING, AND BEHAVIORAL ECONOMICS.
Dynamic Games & The Extensive Form
THE “CLASSIC” 2 x 2 SIMULTANEOUS CHOICE GAMES Topic #4.
3.1.4 Types of Games. Strategic Behavior in Business and Econ Outline 3.1. What is a Game ? The elements of a Game The Rules of the Game:
Lecture 5 Introduction to Game theory. What is game theory? Game theory studies situations where players have strategic interactions; the payoff that.
1 What is Game Theory About? r Analysis of situations where conflict of interests is present r Goal is to prescribe how conflicts can be resolved 2 2 r.
Frank Cowell: Microeconomics Consumer: Aggregation MICROECONOMICS Principles and Analysis Frank Cowell Almost essential Firm: Optimisation Consumption:
Frank Cowell: Mixed Strategy Games GAMES: MIXED STRATEGIES MICROECONOMICS Principles and Analysis Frank Cowell Almost essential Game Theory: Strategy and.
Strategic Behavior in Business and Econ Static Games of complete information: Dominant Strategies and Nash Equilibrium in pure and mixed strategies.
Frank Cowell: Games Uncertainty GAMES: UNCERTAINTY MICROECONOMICS Principles and Analysis Frank Cowell Almost essential Games: Mixed Strategies Almost.
Intermediate Microeconomics Game Theory and Oligopoly.
Frank Cowell: Game Theory Basics GAME THEORY: BASICS MICROECONOMICS Principles and Analysis Frank Cowell July Note: the detail in slides marked.
Intermediate Microeconomics Game Theory. So far we have only studied situations that were not “strategic”. The optimal behavior of any given individual.
M9302 Mathematical Models in Economics Instructor: Georgi Burlakov 0.Game Theory – Brief Introduction Lecture
Frank Cowell:Game Theory Strategy and Equilibrium GAME THEORY: STRATEGY AND EQUILIBRIUM MICROECONOMICS Principles and Analysis Frank Cowell Almost essential.
Lec 23 Chapter 28 Game Theory.
Oligopoly CHAPTER 13B. Oligopoly IRL In some markets there are only two firms. Computer chips are an example. The chips that drive most PCs are made by.
Frank Cowell: Design Basics DESIGN BASICS MICROECONOMICS Principles and Analysis Frank Cowell 1 Almost essential Welfare Basics Games: equilibrium Almost.
Games, Strategies, and Decision Making By Joseph Harrington, Jr. First Edition Chapter 4: Stable Play: Nash Equilibria in Discrete Games with Two or Three.
Advanced Subjects in GT Outline of the tutorials Static Games of Complete Information Introduction to games Normal-form (strategic-form) representation.
Dynamic Games of complete information: Backward Induction and Subgame perfection.
Chapter 12 Game Theory Presented by Nahakpam PhD Student 1Game Theory.
Game theory Chapter 28 and 29
Game theory basics A Game describes situations of strategic interaction, where the payoff for one agent depends on its own actions as well as on the actions.
Q 2.1 Nash Equilibrium Ben
Intermediate Microeconomics
Game theory Chapter 28 and 29
Choices Involving Strategy
Molly W. Dahl Georgetown University Econ 101 – Spring 2009
Game Theory Day 2: More Simple Games.
Lecture Game Theory.
Presentation transcript:

Frank Cowell: Microeconomics Game Theory: Basics MICROECONOMICS Principles and Analysis Frank Cowell March 2004

Frank Cowell: Microeconomics Introduction Focus on conflict and cooperation. Focus on conflict and cooperation. Provides fundamental tools for microeconomic analysis. Provides fundamental tools for microeconomic analysis. Games vs Neoclassical micro models Games vs Neoclassical micro models Offers new insights on concepts and techniques we have discussed earlier: Offers new insights on concepts and techniques we have discussed earlier:  Optimisation.  Equilibrium. Begin with basic ingredients of a game… Begin with basic ingredients of a game…

Frank Cowell: Microeconomics Ingredients of a game The players: The players:  Firms?  Consumers?  Household members? ………… Objectives of players: Objectives of players:  Profits?  Utility? ………… Rules of play: Rules of play:  Available actions  Information  Timing ………… The outcomes: The outcomes:  List of monetary payoffs?  List of utility levels? ………… Details follow

Frank Cowell: Microeconomics Actions Actions could be almost anything of economic interest. Actions could be almost anything of economic interest. Important to specify the action space as part of the rules of the game Important to specify the action space as part of the rules of the game Some examples: Some examples: Type of action Action space Nonnegative numbers [0,∞)  Quantity of a good Nonnegative numbers [0,∞)  Product price Set of places {London, Paris, New York…}  Location A simple pair { [+], [  ] } or { Left, Right } or { Bid, No Bid } …  Participation

Frank Cowell: Microeconomics How to represent a game Two main approaches: Two main approaches: 1. Extensive form Timing is important: who moves first? Timing is important: who moves first? Which moves are observed? Which moves are observed? 2. Normal form Simultaneous moves -- no timing issues Simultaneous moves -- no timing issues Encapsulate details of the game in a single table. Encapsulate details of the game in a single table. Each form has its uses in analysing the economic issues modelled by a game. Each form has its uses in analysing the economic issues modelled by a game. Consider a simple example… Consider a simple example…

Frank Cowell: Microeconomics Extensive form Take two players: Take two players:  Numbered for convenience.  Player 1 does not necessarily have precedence over 2. Each can take one of two actions: Each can take one of two actions:  Player 1 can choose Left or Right.  Player 2 can choose left or right. Outcomes just represented by numbers (utility levels). Outcomes just represented by numbers (utility levels). Consider the rules of play: Consider the rules of play:  Do the players take turns?  Or do they have to move at the same time?

Frank Cowell: Microeconomics Extensive Form: Sequential LR   Player 1 chooses L or R     Player 2 chooses l or r…   …after player 1’s choice lr   lr   Payoffs, given as (u 1, u 2 ) (8,8)(0,10) (10,0) (3,3)  

Frank Cowell: Microeconomics Extensive Form: Simultaneous LR   Player 1 chooses L or R   Player 2 does not know player 1’s choice…   …when choosing l or r  llrr   Payoffs as before (8,8)(0,10) (10,0) (3,3)   Shaded area shows that 2 does not know which of the nodes in here is the relevant one

Frank Cowell: Microeconomics Normal form Also known as strategic form. Also known as strategic form. Represents the game as a consequences table Represents the game as a consequences table Need to specify Need to specify  The players  The strategies available to each  The payoff to each consequent upon each possible combination of strategies A difficulty: as yet we have not defined “strategy” A difficulty: as yet we have not defined “strategy” But we can get some insight a simplified version of the normal form But we can get some insight a simplified version of the normal form  For now we restrict attention to cases where the “action” can be used instead of “strategy”

Frank Cowell: Microeconomics Normal form example We use the game form we have represented earlier. We use the game form we have represented earlier. Two players Two players Each can take one of two actions Each can take one of two actions Same payoffs as before Same payoffs as before Focus on the case of simultaneous play Focus on the case of simultaneous play  A key assumption for the simplification we are using

Frank Cowell: Microeconomics 0,10 3,3 10,0R 8,8L Player 1 Player 2 lr Normal form   A table for two players   Player 1 chooses L or R   Player 2 chooses l or r   Payoffs, given as u 1, u 2   Outcome of choices L,r

Frank Cowell: Microeconomics How to solve the game? A simple approach A simple approach It is sometimes easy to see what actions could not be optimal It is sometimes easy to see what actions could not be optimal In which case, let’s eliminate them In which case, let’s eliminate them Could what is left be a solution? Could what is left be a solution?

Frank Cowell: Microeconomics The method in action Let’s illustrate the method with four examples. Let’s illustrate the method with four examples. Examples 2-4 are well-known cases: Examples 2-4 are well-known cases:  We will identify them by their usual names…  …although the names will not mean much for now.  But if you want a brief explanation click on the “story” button, top left of the screen. This is only a first glimpse of some important paradigms. This is only a first glimpse of some important paradigms. The examples will be taken up in further presentations. The examples will be taken up in further presentations. Click the button again to close the window

Frank Cowell: Microeconomics The examples Each game: … is symmetric … is symmetric  You can interchange the two players … has a simple action space … has a simple action space  Binary: i.e. every one consists of {Left, Right}, {[+],[  ]}, etc. …has a simple payoff structure …has a simple payoff structure  Purely ordinal (numbers in italics to remind us of this)  Four utility levels for each person {0, 1, 2, 3}  This will have to be changed in later developments … raises some interesting questions: … raises some interesting questions:  Can you spot what the solution must be?  Are there apparent solutions that the method misses?  Does it matter that the game is played simultaneously rather than sequentially? worst best

Frank Cowell: Microeconomics [–][–][–][–] 0,02,1 1,23,3[+] Player 1 Player 2 [+] [–][–][–][–] 0,02,1 A trivial game   A “contribution game”   Each player can choose [+] or [–].   Payoffs, given as (u 1, u 2 )   If 2 plays [+] then 1 gets more by playing [+]   So player 1 eliminates [ – ]   If 2 plays [–] then 1 also does better by playing [+] 1,2   For similar reasons 2 eliminates [ – ]   The solution Same result would emerge whether play is simultaneous or sequential A trivial game? Although this game is trivial in terms of game theory it can be seen as a caricature of an important economic phenomenon. We can consider it as a form of positive externality. If each player (firm or household) chooses [+] this reinforces the payoff to the other player of choosing [+] rather than [-]. In this case the model of the externality is so simple that a decision taken on an individual myopic basis automatically leads to the best possible outcome for each player. It is clear what the outcome would be. A trivial game? Although this game is trivial in terms of game theory it can be seen as a caricature of an important economic phenomenon. We can consider it as a form of positive externality. If each player (firm or household) chooses [+] this reinforces the payoff to the other player of choosing [+] rather than [-]. In this case the model of the externality is so simple that a decision taken on an individual myopic basis automatically leads to the best possible outcome for each player. It is clear what the outcome would be. Story

Frank Cowell: Microeconomics Trivial game: outcomes u1u1 u2u2   The payoffs   The solution…   …at this salient point seems reasonable

Frank Cowell: Microeconomics [–][–][–][–] 1,13,0 0,32,2[+] Player 1 Player 2 [+] [–][–][–][–] 0,32,2 “Prisoner’s dilemma”   A “contribution game”   Each player can choose [+] or [–].   Payoffs, given as (u 1, u 2 )   If 2 plays [+] then 1 gets more by playing [–]   So player 1 eliminates [+]   If 2 plays [–] then 1 also does better by playing [–] 3,0   For similar reasons 2 eliminates [+]   The solution?   Again, the same outcome from simultaneous or sequential play.   But there is something odd about this… Story

Frank Cowell: Microeconomics Prisoner’s Dilemma: outcomes u1u1 u2u2   The payoffs   The “solution”   But why isn’t this a solution…?   (To be continued…)   After all, it’s Pareto- superior to the “solution”

Frank Cowell: Microeconomics East 1,20,0 2,1West Player 1 Player 2 WestEast “Battle of the sexes”   A “coordination game”   Each player can choose West or East.   Payoffs, given as (u 1, u 2 )   If 2 plays W then 1 gets more by playing W   So, no elimination   But if 2 plays E then 1 does better by playing E   Outcome is clear if one player has “first move”: (2,1) or (1,2)   But what happens if they move simultaneously? Story

Frank Cowell: Microeconomics Battle of sexes: outcomes u1u1 u2u2   The payoffs   Outcome if 1 moves first   Outcome if 2 moves first

Frank Cowell: Microeconomics [–][–][–][–] 0,03,1 1,32,2[+] Player 1 Player 2 [+] [–][–][–][–] “Chicken”   Another “contribution game”   Each chooses [+] or [–].   Payoffs, given as (u 1, u 2 )   If 2 plays [+] then 1 gets more by playing [–]   Again no elimination   But if 2 plays [–] then 1 does better by playing [+]   If one player has “first move” outcome is (3,1) or (1,3)   But what happens in the case of a simultaneous move? Chicken Two tearaways drive their cars at each other: If neither driver swerves, both end up dead (utility level 0) If one driver swerves out of the way then he is regarded as "chicken" (utility level 1) and the other acquires extraordinary social esteem (utility level 3). If both drivers swerve, both look embarrassed (utility level 2). Clearly, if either driver knows what the other will do there is an incentive to do the opposite. Economic relevance: it is the basis of a class of problems where social and private interests are partially in opposition. An application is the provision of public goods. Suppose citizens have to decide on one of two actions: action [+]  contribute private resources to provision of an essential public good. action [  ]  not to contribute any resources. Each citizen wants to see that a public good is provided, even at his own (partial) expense. Each knows that if no resources are provided there is no public good  outcome (0,0). He would prefer it if someone else pays for the public good and he can "free ride"  outcome (3,1). But if he knows that no-one else will pay for the good he is willing to do it himself. Chicken Two tearaways drive their cars at each other: If neither driver swerves, both end up dead (utility level 0) If one driver swerves out of the way then he is regarded as "chicken" (utility level 1) and the other acquires extraordinary social esteem (utility level 3). If both drivers swerve, both look embarrassed (utility level 2). Clearly, if either driver knows what the other will do there is an incentive to do the opposite. Economic relevance: it is the basis of a class of problems where social and private interests are partially in opposition. An application is the provision of public goods. Suppose citizens have to decide on one of two actions: action [+]  contribute private resources to provision of an essential public good. action [  ]  not to contribute any resources. Each citizen wants to see that a public good is provided, even at his own (partial) expense. Each knows that if no resources are provided there is no public good  outcome (0,0). He would prefer it if someone else pays for the public good and he can "free ride"  outcome (3,1). But if he knows that no-one else will pay for the good he is willing to do it himself. Story

Frank Cowell: Microeconomics u2u2 Chicken: outcomes u1u1   The payoffs   But why isn’t this a solution…?   (To be continued…)   Outcome if 1 moves first   Outcome if 2 moves first

Frank Cowell: Microeconomics Review: basic concepts Actions Actions  Must specify carefully the action space Order of play Order of play  Simultaneous or sequential? Representation of the game Representation of the game  Extensive form  Normal form Elimination Elimination  First steps toward a solution Review

Frank Cowell: Microeconomics What next? Introduce strategy Introduce strategy The role of information – a first look The role of information – a first look Examine the meaning of rationality Examine the meaning of rationality Formalise equilibrium Formalise equilibrium This is handled in Game Theory: Strategy and Equilibrium This is handled in Game Theory: Strategy and Equilibrium Game Theory: Strategy and Equilibrium Game Theory: Strategy and Equilibrium