2101INT – Principles of Intelligent Systems Lecture 9.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Probability: Review The state of the world is described using random variables Probabilities are defined over events –Sets of world states characterized.
Advertisements

PROBABILITY. Uncertainty  Let action A t = leave for airport t minutes before flight from Logan Airport  Will A t get me there on time ? Problems :
Where are we in CS 440? Now leaving: sequential, deterministic reasoning Entering: probabilistic reasoning and machine learning.
Artificial Intelligence Uncertainty
Reasoning under Uncertainty: Conditional Prob., Bayes and Independence Computer Science cpsc322, Lecture 25 (Textbook Chpt ) March, 17, 2010.
Marginal Independence and Conditional Independence Computer Science cpsc322, Lecture 26 (Textbook Chpt 6.1-2) March, 19, 2010.
CPSC 422 Review Of Probability Theory.
Probability.
Uncertainty Chapter 13. Uncertainty Let action A t = leave for airport t minutes before flight Will A t get me there on time? Problems: 1.partial observability.
KI2 - 2 Kunstmatige Intelligentie / RuG Probabilities Revisited AIMA, Chapter 13.
1 Bayesian Reasoning Chapter 13 CMSC 471 Adapted from slides by Tim Finin and Marie desJardins.
University College Cork (Ireland) Department of Civil and Environmental Engineering Course: Engineering Artificial Intelligence Dr. Radu Marinescu Lecture.
Uncertainty Management for Intelligent Systems : for SEP502 June 2006 김 진형 KAIST
Representing Uncertainty CSE 473. © Daniel S. Weld 2 Many Techniques Developed Fuzzy Logic Certainty Factors Non-monotonic logic Probability Only one.
Ai in game programming it university of copenhagen Welcome to... the Crash Course Probability Theory Marco Loog.
Probability and Information Copyright, 1996 © Dale Carnegie & Associates, Inc. A brief review (Chapter 13)
Uncertainty Logical approach problem: we do not always know complete truth about the environment Example: Leave(t) = leave for airport t minutes before.
Uncertainty Chapter 13.
Uncertainty Chapter 13.
Methods in Computational Linguistics II Queens College Lecture 2: Counting Things.
EE562 ARTIFICIAL INTELLIGENCE FOR ENGINEERS
CS 4100 Artificial Intelligence Prof. C. Hafner Class Notes Feb 28 and March 13-15, 2012.
Handling Uncertainty. Uncertain knowledge Typical example: Diagnosis. Consider:  x Symptom(x, Toothache)  Disease(x, Cavity). The problem is that this.
Uncertainty Chapter 13. Uncertainty Let action A t = leave for airport t minutes before flight Will A t get me there on time? Problems: 1.partial observability.
CHAPTER 13 Oliver Schulte Summer 2011 Uncertainty.
An Introduction to Artificial Intelligence Chapter 13 & : Uncertainty & Bayesian Networks Ramin Halavati
Uncertainty1 Uncertainty Russell and Norvig: Chapter 14 Russell and Norvig: Chapter 13 CS121 – Winter 2003.
CS 4100 Artificial Intelligence Prof. C. Hafner Class Notes March 15and20, 2012.
CS 4100 Artificial Intelligence Prof. C. Hafner Class Notes March 13, 2012.
Uncertainty Chapter 13. Outline Uncertainty Probability Syntax and Semantics Inference Independence and Bayes' Rule.
1 Chapter 13 Uncertainty. 2 Outline Uncertainty Probability Syntax and Semantics Inference Independence and Bayes' Rule.
Uncertainty Chapter 13. Outline Uncertainty Probability Syntax and Semantics Inference Independence and Bayes' Rule.
CS 4100 Artificial Intelligence Prof. C. Hafner Class Notes March 20, 2012.
Uncertainty Chapter 13. Outline Uncertainty Probability Syntax and Semantics Inference Independence and Bayes' Rule.
Probability and naïve Bayes Classifier Louis Oliphant cs540 section 2 Fall 2005.
An Introduction to Artificial Intelligence Chapter 13 & : Uncertainty & Bayesian Networks Ramin Halavati
Chapter 13 February 19, Acting Under Uncertainty Rational Decision – Depends on the relative importance of the goals and the likelihood of.
Uncertainty. Assumptions Inherent in Deductive Logic-based Systems All the assertions we wish to make and use are universally true. Observations of the.
Probability and Information Copyright, 1996 © Dale Carnegie & Associates, Inc. A brief review.
Reasoning under Uncertainty: Conditional Prob., Bayes and Independence Computer Science cpsc322, Lecture 25 (Textbook Chpt ) Nov, 5, 2012.
Uncertainty Chapter 13. Outline Uncertainty Probability Syntax and Semantics Inference Independence and Bayes' Rule.
Uncertainty Chapter 13. Outline Uncertainty Probability Syntax and Semantics Inference Independence and Bayes' Rule.
Introduction to Artificial Intelligence CS 438 Spring 2008 Today –AIMA, Ch. 13 –Reasoning with Uncertainty Tuesday –AIMA, Ch. 14.
Web-Mining Agents Data Mining Prof. Dr. Ralf Möller Universität zu Lübeck Institut für Informationssysteme Karsten Martiny (Übungen)
Uncertainty Let action A t = leave for airport t minutes before flight Will A t get me there on time? Problems: 1.partial observability (road state, other.
Uncertainty 1. 2 ♦ Uncertainty ♦ Probability ♦ Syntax and Semantics ♦ Inference ♦ Independence and Bayes’ Rule Outline.
CSE 473 Uncertainty. © UW CSE AI Faculty 2 Many Techniques Developed Fuzzy Logic Certainty Factors Non-monotonic logic Probability Only one has stood.
Uncertainty Fall 2013 Comp3710 Artificial Intelligence Computing Science Thompson Rivers University.
Web-Mining Agents Data Mining Prof. Dr. Ralf Möller Universität zu Lübeck Institut für Informationssysteme Karsten Martiny (Übungen)
Outline [AIMA Ch 13] 1 Uncertainty Probability Syntax and Semantics Inference Independence and Bayes' Rule.
Uncertainty & Probability CIS 391 – Introduction to Artificial Intelligence AIMA, Chapter 13 Many slides adapted from CMSC 421 (U. Maryland) by Bonnie.
Anifuddin Azis UNCERTAINTY. 2 Introduction The world is not a well-defined place. There is uncertainty in the facts we know: What’s the temperature? Imprecise.
Introduction to Artificial Intelligence – Unit 7 Probabilistic Reasoning Course The Hebrew University of Jerusalem School of Engineering and Computer.
Computer Science cpsc322, Lecture 25
Marginal Independence and Conditional Independence
Where are we in CS 440? Now leaving: sequential, deterministic reasoning Entering: probabilistic reasoning and machine learning.
Uncertainty Chapter 13.
Uncertainty Chapter 13.
Where are we in CS 440? Now leaving: sequential, deterministic reasoning Entering: probabilistic reasoning and machine learning.
EE562 ARTIFICIAL INTELLIGENCE FOR ENGINEERS
Uncertainty.
Uncertainty in Environments
Representing Uncertainty
CS 188: Artificial Intelligence Fall 2008
CS 188: Artificial Intelligence Fall 2007
Uncertainty Logical approach problem: we do not always know complete truth about the environment Example: Leave(t) = leave for airport t minutes before.
Uncertainty Chapter 13.
Uncertainty Chapter 13.
Uncertainty Chapter 13.
Uncertainty Chapter 13.
Presentation transcript:

2101INT – Principles of Intelligent Systems Lecture 9

Outline – Part 1 Uncertainty Probability Syntax and Semantics Inference Independence and Bayes' Rule Part 1 slides (2-21) are taken from those available from the AIMA website at Author recorded as Min-Yen Kan, NUS Ch13

Uncertainty Let action A t = leave for airport t minutes before flight Will A t get me there on time? Problems: 1. partial observability (road state, other drivers' plans, etc.) 2. noisy sensors (traffic reports) 3. uncertainty in action outcomes (flat tire, etc.) 4. immense complexity of modeling and predicting traffic Hence a purely logical approach either 1. risks falsehood: “A 25 will get me there on time”, or 2. leads to conclusions that are too weak for decision making: “A 25 will get me there on time if there's no accident on the bridge and it doesn't rain and my tires remain intact etc etc.” (A 1440 might reasonably be said to get me there on time but I'd have to stay overnight in the airport …) p462

Methods for handling uncertainty Default or nonmonotonic logic: – Assume my car does not have a flat tire – Assume A 25 works unless contradicted by evidence Issues: What assumptions are reasonable? How to handle contradiction? Rules with fudge factors: – A 25 |→ 0.3 get there on time – Sprinkler |→ 0.99 WetGrass – WetGrass |→ 0.7 Rain Issues: Problems with combination, e.g., Sprinkler causes Rain?? Probability – Model agent's degree of belief – Given the available evidence, – A 25 will get me there on time with probability 0.3

Probability Probabilistic assertions summarize effects of – laziness: failure to enumerate exceptions, qualifications, etc. – ignorance: lack of relevant facts, initial conditions, etc. Subjective probability: Probabilities relate propositions to agent's own state of knowledge e.g., P(A 25 | no reported accidents) = 0.06 These are not assertions about the world Probabilities of propositions change with new evidence: e.g., P(A 25 | no reported accidents, 5 a.m.) = 0.15 p463

Making decisions under uncertainty Suppose I believe the following: P(A 25 gets me there on time | …) = 0.04 P(A 90 gets me there on time | …) = 0.70 P(A 120 gets me there on time | …) = 0.95 P(A 1440 gets me there on time | …) = Which action to choose? Depends on my preferences for missing flight vs. time spent waiting, etc. – Utility theory is used to represent and infer preferences – Decision theory = probability theory + utility theory p465

Syntax Basic element: random variable Similar to propositional logic: possible worlds defined by assignment of values to random variables. Boolean random variables e.g., Cavity (do I have a cavity?) Discrete random variables e.g., Weather is one of Domain values must be exhaustive and mutually exclusive Elementary proposition constructed by assignment of a value to a random variable: e.g., Weather = sunny, Cavity = false (abbreviated as  cavity) Complex propositions formed from elementary propositions and standard logical connectives e.g., Weather = sunny  Cavity = false p467

Syntax Atomic event: A complete specification of the state of the world about which the agent is uncertain E.g., if the world consists of only two Boolean variables Cavity and Toothache, then there are 4 distinct atomic events: Cavity = false  Toothache = false Cavity = false  Toothache = true Cavity = true  Toothache = false Cavity = true  Toothache = true Atomic events are mutually exclusive and exhaustive p468

Axioms of probability For any propositions A, B – 0 ≤ P(A) ≤ 1 – P(true) = 1 and P(false) = 0 – P(A  B) = P(A) + P(B) - P(A  B) p471

Prior probability Prior or unconditional probabilities of propositions e.g., P(Cavity = true) = 0.2 and P(Weather = sunny) = 0.72 correspond to belief prior to arrival of any (new) evidence Probability distribution gives values for all possible assignments: P(Weather) = (normalized, i.e., sums to 1) Joint probability distribution for a set of random variables gives the probability of every atomic event on those random variables P(Weather,Cavity) = a 4 × 2 matrix of values: Weather =sunnyrainycloudysnow Cavity = true Cavity = false Every question about a domain can be answered by the joint distribution p468

Conditional probability Conditional or posterior probabilities e.g., P(cavity | toothache) = 0.8 i.e., given that toothache is all I know (Notation for conditional distributions: P(Cavity | Toothache) = 2-element vector of 2-element vectors) If we know more, e.g., cavity is also given, then we have P(cavity | toothache,cavity) = 1 New evidence may be irrelevant, allowing simplification, e.g., P(cavity | toothache, sunny) = P(cavity | toothache) = 0.8 This kind of inference, sanctioned by domain knowledge, is crucial p470

Conditional probability Definition of conditional probability: P(a | b) = P(a  b) / P(b) if P(b) > 0 Product rule gives an alternative formulation: P(a  b) = P(a | b) P(b) = P(b | a) P(a) A general version holds for whole distributions, e.g., P(Weather,Cavity) = P(Weather | Cavity) P(Cavity) (View as a set of 4 × 2 equations, not matrix mult.) Chain rule is derived by successive application of product rule: P(X 1, …,X n ) = P(X 1,...,X n-1 ) P(X n | X 1,...,X n-1 ) = P(X 1,...,X n-2 ) P(X n-1 | X 1,...,X n-2 ) P(X n | X 1,...,X n-1 ) = … = π i= 1 ^n P(X i | X 1, …,X i-1 )

Inference by enumeration Start with the joint probability distribution: For any proposition φ, sum the atomic events where it is true: P(φ) = Σ ω:ω╞φ P(ω) p475

Inference by enumeration Start with the joint probability distribution: For any proposition φ, sum the atomic events where it is true: P(φ) = Σ ω:ω╞φ P(ω) P(toothache) = = 0.2

Start with the joint probability distribution: Can also compute conditional probabilities: P(  cavity | toothache) = P(  cavity  toothache) P(toothache) = = 0.4 Inference by enumeration

Normalization Denominator can be viewed as a normalization constant α P(Cavity | toothache) = α, P(Cavity,toothache) = α, [P(Cavity,toothache,catch) + P(Cavity,toothache,  catch)] = α, [ + ] = α, = General idea: compute distribution on query variable by fixing evidence variables and summing over hidden variables

Independence A and B are independent iff P(A|B) = P(A) or P(B|A) = P(B) or P(A, B) = P(A) P(B) P(Toothache, Catch, Cavity, Weather) = P(Toothache, Catch, Cavity) P(Weather) 32 entries reduced to 12=(8+4); for n independent biased coins, O(2 n ) →O(n) Absolute independence powerful but rare Dentistry is a large field with hundreds of variables, none of which are independent. What to do? p477

Conditional independence If I have a cavity, the probability that the probe catches in it doesn't depend on whether I have a toothache: (1) P(catch | toothache, cavity) = P(catch | cavity) The same independence holds if I haven't got a cavity: (2) P(catch | toothache,  cavity) = P(catch |  cavity) Catch is conditionally independent of Toothache given Cavity: P(Catch | Toothache,Cavity) = P(Catch | Cavity) Equivalent statements: P(Toothache | Catch, Cavity) = P(Toothache | Cavity) P(Toothache, Catch | Cavity) = P(Toothache | Cavity) P(Catch | Cavity)

Bayes' Rule Product rule P(a  b) = P(a | b) P(b) = P(b | a) P(a)  Bayes' rule: P(a | b) = P(b | a) P(a) / P(b) or in distribution form P(Y|X) = P(X|Y) P(Y) / P(X) = αP(X|Y) P(Y) Useful for assessing diagnostic probability from causal probability: – P(Cause|Effect) = P(Effect|Cause) P(Cause) / P(Effect) – E.g., let M be meningitis, S be stiff neck: P(m|s) = P(s|m) P(m) / P(s) = 0.8 × / 0.1 = – Note: posterior probability of meningitis still very small! p480

Bayes' Rule and conditional independence P(Cavity | toothache  catch) = αP(toothache  catch | Cavity) P(Cavity) = αP(toothache | Cavity) P(catch | Cavity) P(Cavity) This is an example of a naïve Bayes model: P(Cause,Effect 1, …,Effect n ) = P(Cause) π i P(Effect i |Cause) Total number of parameters is linear in n

Summary Probability is a rigorous formalism for uncertain knowledge Joint probability distribution specifies probability of every atomic event Queries can be answered by summing over atomic events For nontrivial domains, we must find a way to reduce the joint size Independence and conditional independence provide the tools

Outline – Part 2 Non-monotonic logics Uncertainty and temporal knowledge

Non-monotonicity Humans are not first-order theorem provers – everyday we are faced with making decisions based on uncertain and incomplete information Classical logics do not handle such scenarios well Any new information, or facts, added to the knowledge base are expected to be consistent with the existing facts When new information can contradict previously drawn conclusions, this is said to be non-monotonicity p358

The non-monotonicity problem Humans are not first-order theorem provers – everyday we are faced with making decisions based on uncertain and incomplete information bird(X)  flies(X) bird(tweety)  flies(tweety) By modus tollens:  flies(tweety)   bird(tweety) Which is incorrect, the rule, premise 1, or premise 2? p358

Circumscription Circumscription can be viewed as a more powerful version of the closed-world assumption Predicates are introduced to denote the “abnormality” of objects in obeying particular rules Eg. Birds fly can be written as bird(X)   abnormal 1 (X)  flies(X) The predicate  abnormal 1 (X) is said to be circumscribed.  abnormal 1 (X) may be assumed unless abnormal 1 (X) is explicitly known. p358

Model Preference Introduces the concept of preferred models, where a sentence is entailed from a KB if it is true in all preferred models (rather than in all models) One model is preferred to another if it has fewer abnormal objects p358

Model Preference - Example Nixon’s diamond: republican(nixon)  quaker(nixon) republican(X)   abnormal 2 (X)   pacifist(X) quaker(X)   abnormal 3 (X)  pacifist(X) Was Nixon a pacifist? With both abnormals circumscribed there are two preferred models, each with one abnormal, hence no definitive conclusion. Only if we were to assert that religious beliefs take precedence over political ones could a conclusion be drawn: prioritised circumscription p359

Default logic Default logic is a formalism using default rules to generate non-monotonic conclusions A default rule looks like this: P: J 1,…,J n / C Given a prerequisite P, some justifications J i and a conclusion C If any of the justifications are proven false, then the conclusion may not be drawn, eg: bird(X) : flies(X) / flies(X) p359

Extending default rules The extension of a default theory is the maximal set of consequences of the theory That is, an extension S consists of the original known facts and a set of drawn conclusions, such that 1) no additional conclusions can be drawn 2) the justification of every default conclusion is consistent with S Returning to Nixon’s diamond, the both pacifist and  pacifist are extensions. As before, prioritised schemes allow some rules to be preferred to others p359

Semantic networks Semantic networks are a graphical representation for representing knowledge Long used in philosophy before computer science This network by Porphyry C. 300BC p350

Semantic networks cont. There are many different kinds of semantic network Common to all is that they are a declarative graphic representation of knowledge, or to support reasoning about knowledge Some networks are defined to be necessarily true, given their true definitions Others are used to model human reasoning and can handle uncertainty p350

Semantic networks – Planet Barklon “Imagine it is the year 3000 and that a group of space scientists have discovered a planet in a far off galaxy. This planet is called Barklon. Scientists have been observing for 5 years and have built up quite a database – about the peoples, animals and plants on Barklon. Back at Galactic HQ, your job is to compile a report on the planet Barklon for your superiors. Your superiors are specifically interested in the supplied 14 features. All of the relevant database information is provided with each question.” Extract from Ford & Billington (2000) “Strategies in Human Non-Monotonic Reasoning”

Planet Barklon Instructions Twilbers are usually jadds All jadds are muffers Kragded is a twilber Is Kragded a muffer? The most reasonable answer is B, likely yes.

Barklon Answers For some questions, difficult to assign “correct” answers – depends on reasoning technique. There are accepted answers though: 1) B2) B3) B4) D5) E6) strong E, weak D 7) E8) E9) E10) B11) D12) B13) B14) E

Graphical representation All members of the plant species zillo are small Small plant species are usually found in deserts Garffi is a zillo Nagdals are usually spotted plants. All spotted plants are found in deep caves. Croldor is a nagdal. Trendors are usually green animals. Green animals are usually found on cliffs. Stordy is a trendor.

Strong vs Weak Specificity Consider problem 6 Zugs are usually not vlogs. Zugs are usually striped creatures. Striped creatures are usually vlogs. Duss is a zug. Depending on the reasoning method, two possible answers, “likely no” or “can’t tell” Should two “usually” links be treated equivalently as a single link?

Strong specificity allows transitivity of “usually” Saying “Zugs are usually striped are usually vlogs” is equivalent to saying “Zugs are usually vlogs” Under this interpretation, the network cannot be decided and the correct answer is E Strong Specificity

Weak specificity allows transitivity of “usually” but weaken successive uses Saying “Zugs are usually striped are usually vlogs” is weaker than saying “Zugs are usually vlogs” When we then explicitly say that “Zugs are not usually vlogs”, this is the stronger statement Hence the answer is D Weak Specificity

Very important to be able to reason about time Representing explicit points is often problematic – requires either real-valued variables, or quantise time into approriate discrete steps Using intervals then provides a way to qualitatively reason about time, abstracting away the specific quantified points Very useful in planning and scheduling domains Temporal Reasoning p338

In computer science, attributed to Allen (1983), but can be dated at least back to Broad (1945) Between any two intervals there are 13 possible relations I = The first 6 have inverses to make up to 13. Interval Algebra p338

Interval Algebra

Determining consistency within temporal constraint networks is difficult because possible relations between intervals are disjunctions – so this or this or this or … can hold. Can and has been translated into SAT There are a number of tractable subclasses of TR, just as there are for SAT Interval Algebra