Ethics 160 Moral Arguments. Reasons and Arguments Different claims have different uses in our language. Sometimes, a claim or claims are used as a reason.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Phil 148 Chapter 3. What makes an argument good? It is often taken to be the case that an argument is good if it is persuasive, that is, if people are.
Advertisements

PHIL 148 Chapter 5 Stuff to include in and leave out of the standard form argument.
Reason and Argument Chapter 1. Claims A claim takes the form of a proposition. A proposition has a similar relation to a sentence as a number does to.
Formal Criteria for Evaluating Arguments
The Challenge of Cultural Relativism
What makes an argument good? It is often taken to be the case that an argument is good if it is persuasive, that is, if people are inclined to accept it.
Chapter 1 Critical Thinking.
“Be kind, because everyone you meet is fighting a hard battle.” – Plato.
Chapter Twelve: The Fact-Value Problem Chapter Twelve: The Fact-Value Problem Metaethics ► Philosophizing about the very terms of ethics ► Considering.
Meta-Ethics Slavery is evil Honesty is a virtue Abortion is wrong ‘Meta’ from Greek meaning ‘above’ or ‘after’
Application of Ethical Reasoning
Chapter 5 Premises: What to Accept and Why Important goal: to identify some general guidelines for what makes a premise or claim acceptable 7 ways for.
 Assertions: unsupported declaration of a belief  Prejudice: a view without evidence for or against  Premises: explicit evidence that lead to a conclusion.
Meta-Ethics Emotivism. What is Emotivism? Emotivism is a meta-ethical theory associated mostly with A. J. Ayer ( ) and C.L Stevenson ( )
From Last time Cognitivism vs. non-cognitivism Subjective descriptivism Cultural relativism Divine Command theory.
Introduction to Ethics Lecture 6 Ayer and Emotivism By David Kelsey.
Moral Realism & the Challenge of Skepticism
Philosophy 120 Symbolic Logic I H. Hamner Hill CSTL-CLA.SEMO.EDU/HHILL/PL120.
Introduction to Ethics Lecture 9 The Challenge of Cultural Relativism By David Kelsey.
Michael Lacewing Emotivism Michael Lacewing
Basic Critical Thinking Skills Essentials of Clear Thinking: Claims and Issues.
Phil 1: An Introduction to Philosophy
Basic Argumentation.
Logic and Philosophy Alan Hausman PART ONE Sentential Logic Sentential Logic.
0 Validity & Invalidity (Exercises) December 23, 2005.
Phil 148 Chapter 3. What makes an argument good? It is often taken to be the case that an argument is good if it is persuasive, that is, if people are.
FALSE PREMISE.
Basic Critical Thinking Skills Essentials of Clear Thinking: Claims and Issues.
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 3 Formalizing an argument By David Kelsey.
MIDTERM EXAMINATION THE MIDTERM EXAMINATION WILL BE ON FRIDAY, MAY 2, IN THIS CLASSROOM, STARTING AT 1:00 P.M. BRING A BLUE BOOK. THE EXAM WILL COVER:
Meta-Ethics Non-Cognitivism.
Introduction to Ethics Lecture 9 The Challenge of Cultural Relativism By David Kelsey.
The Nature of Morality General Overview “We are discussing no small matter, but how we ought to live” (Plato in the Republic ca. 390B.C.)
Reasoning and Critical Thinking Validity and Soundness 1.
+ Ethics II The nature of moral knowledge. + Moral knowledge Do you know the difference between right and wrong? Does anybody? Is moral knowledge even.
Mormons do not feel threatened by science. They are not enemies of the rational world. They are not creationist. On human conduct, they tend to stress.
Meta-Ethics Emotivism. Normative Ethics Meta-ethics Subject matter is moral issues such as abortion, war, euthanasia etc Provides theories or frameworks.
0 Validity & Invalidity (Exercises) All dogs have two heads. 2. All tigers are dogs. ___________________________________ 3. All tigers have two.
Critical Thinking. Critical thinkers use reasons to back up their claims. What is a claim? ◦ A claim is a statement that is either true or false. It must.
Debate 101 Brand. Class Rules We are respectful We are considerate We listen the first time We will be present We are responsible What are some of the.
EECS 690 May 4. LIDA Most of this chapter concerns specific ways in which a system like LIDA might be an accurate model of human psychology. This sounds.
Meta-ethics Meta-ethical Questions: What does it mean to be good/bad? What constitutes the nature of being good or bad?
History of Philosophy Lecture 5 Formalizing an argument
PHIL 2525 Contemporary Moral Issues Lec 2 Arguments are among us…
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 1-b What is Philosophy? (Part 2) By David Kelsey.
James Rachels 1941 – 2003 Philosopher by trade Argues against relativism.
Sentence (syntactically Independent grammatical unit) QuestionCommandStatement “This is a class in logic.” “I enjoy logic.” “Today is Friday.”
Philosophy 148 Inductive Reasoning. Inductive reasoning – common misconceptions: - “The process of deriving general principles from particular facts or.
And the search for truth. Knowledge. Knowing: Introduction to a classification scheme In ToK we may treat knowledge as falling into 3 categories. These.
Phil 148 Chapter 5 Stuff to include in and leave out of the standard form argument.
I think therefore I am - Rene Descartes. REASON (logic) It has been said that man is a rational animal. All my life I have been searching for evidence.
What is an argument? An argument is, to quote the Monty Python sketch, "a connected series of statements to establish a definite proposition." Huh? Three.
© 2009 McGraw-Hill Higher Education. All rights reserved.1 Chapters1 & 2.
Ethics Review Via the Euthyphro. What does Euthyphro think? What position would this be? Suppose Socrates asks only because he thinks piety is whatever.
1 Lesson 7: Arguments SOCI Thinking Critically about Social Issues Spring 2012.
Relativism, Divine Command Theory, and Particularism A closer look at some prominent views of ethical theory.
THE NATURE OF ARGUMENT. THE MAIN CONCERN OF LOGIC Basically in logic we deal with ARGUMENTS. Mainly we deal with learning of the principles with which.
Part One: Assessing the Inference, Deductive and Inductive Reasoning.
Deductive reasoning.
FALSE PREMISE.
Debate: Claims.
Making Sense of Arguments
Logic Problems and Questions
Introduction to Logic Lecture 1 What is Critical Reasoning?
Definitions: Evidence-Based Claims- 1.) the ability to take detailed
PROOF SURROGATE Jessica.
Analyzing and Evaluating Arguments
Evaluating Deductive Arguments
Presentation transcript:

Ethics 160 Moral Arguments

Reasons and Arguments Different claims have different uses in our language. Sometimes, a claim or claims are used as a reason to believe another claim. When claims are used in this way, an argument is present. (An argument is not merely a disagreement) A claim that is used a reason for believing another claim is called a premise. The claim that is being supported in this way in an argument is the conclusion.

Standard Form Arguments are often written in a special format. Premises are numbered, and written above their conclusions: 1.Premise 1 2.Premise 2 C. Conclusion

What makes an argument good? It is often taken to be the case that an argument is good if it is persuasive, that is, if people are inclined to accept it. People accept all kinds of foolish things. This is no standard of quality. In fact, Western philosophy was born when some people drew a distinction between philosophy and sophistry.

What makes a good argument: Validity – Means that IF the premises are true, then the conclusion has to be – In other words, there is a proper logical relationship between the premises and the conclusion – In other words, the premises, IF true, really are a reason to believe the conclusion Soundness – Means the argument is valid AND – Means that the premises ARE true

Examples: P1: Bill and Hillary Clinton have the same last name P2: People with the same last name are siblings C: Bill and Hillary Clinton are siblings This is a valid argument because IF the premises were true, the conclusion would have to be. The argument is not sound because P2 is false.

Example: P1: Whoever wrote the Bible is a great author P2: Charles Dickens wrote the Bible C: Charles Dickens is a great author This argument is also valid, because IF the premises were true, the conclusion would have to be, but again, it is unsound because P2 is false.

A common moral argument structure: 1.Moral principle (typically contains the word ‘should’, ‘ought’, ‘must’, ‘is right/wrong’, etc.) 2.Statement of a particular case that appleis to the principle. C. Connects the two statements in a logical way (ends up with the moral approach to the stated case) Example: 1.The new construction proposal would break the state budget 2.The state should not break its budget C. The state should reject the new construction proposal.

Ways of disputing a moral argument: Could claim it is invalid Could claim that the principle in P1 is false Could claim that the case in P2 doesn’t in fact fit the principle.

Truth Evaluable Language Note that in order to be used in an argument, language has to be of a sort that is truth-evaluable, that is, that can be true or false. Premises are judged on the basis of whether they are true or false, and arguments are put together so that true premises related in the proper way will generate a true conclusion. However, since some kinds of language are not truth evaluable, they are not (and cannot be) used in arguments. Things like questions, commands, exclamations, greetings, etc. are all excluded from use in arguments because they are not statements at all (and thus are not truth evaluable)

Moral Language In order to use moral language in arguments we must accept that moral language is truth- evaluable. In other words we have to accept that moral language is more like a statement than a command, an exclamation, etc. This position is referred to as realism, and commits itself to the existence of moral facts.

Moral Realism Anti-realists about morality contend that moral language corresponds with no recognizable category of facts. – Prescriptivists are a kind of antirealist who claim that all moral language is just a set of commands (thus not truth evaluable) in disguise. – Emotivists are a kind of antirealist who claim that all moral language is just a set of emotional expressions (thus not truth evaluable) in disguise. Realists claim that moral language is not in disguise at all and that what look like truth-evaluable statements really are truth evaluable statements. Realists correspondingly associate moral language with one (or more) of a number of factual categories, a few examples of which are: – sociological belief – human well-being – the outcomes of rational procedures – interpersonal conventions – human well-feeling – natural science – theology

Moral disagreement The fact that people disagree about morality does not indicate in any way whether there are or are not moral facts. On the contrary, if two people are to have a substantive moral disagreement, there has to be some fact of the matter with respect to morality, or else the moral dispute is just so much useless noise.

Moral Facts If someone claims that there are moral facts, they are merely claiming that when someone says “Action X is moral” they might be saying something true, and they might be saying something false. This is a rather unobjectionable claim. If someone not only says that there are moral facts, but also says that they know what all of them without a doubt are, then you should start to get skeptical.