MODERN VIRTUE ETHICS Three types. Theoretical (or cool) Virtue Ethics Aristotle saw virtue as based in Natural Law. Modern Virtue ethicists differ from.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Morality: constitutive of or overcoming self-interest?
Advertisements

Higher RMPS Lesson 4 Kantian ethics.
Non-Consequentialism
Moral, Legal and Aesthetic Reasoning
AS Religious Ethics Virtue Ethics Foundation Paper Revision Part 2.
From Aristotle to the 21st century
ETHICS BOWL VIRTUE ETHICS.
Themes in Ethics and Epistemology
Relativism Michael Lacewing
The Moral Argument for the Existence of God.
Categorical Imperative Universal Maxim Respect of Persons
Kant’s Ethical Theory.
Virtue Ethics in Action. TYPES OF ETHICAL THEORY: Utilitarian --based on considering the consequences of actions for people's well-being. Deontological.
ETHICS BOWL kantian ETHICS.
Ethical Theory.
Virtue Ethics (Aristotle)
Virtue Ethics. Virtue ethics focuses not so much on principles or the consequences of action, nor even the action itself so much as on the agent, the.
Practical wisdom Michael Lacewing
ETHICS BOWL CONSEQUENTIALism.
Kantian Ethics Exam Questions
Rosalind Hursthouse: Virtue Theory and Abortion
PHILOSOPHY 102 (STOLZE) Notes on Dale Jamieson, Ethics and the Environment, chapter 4.
Is there such a thing as conscious will?. What is “conscious will”?! Having “free will” or “conscious will” basically means being in control of one’s.
© Michael Lacewing Three theories of ethics Michael Lacewing
Modern Scholars, Virtuous People and Strengths and Weaknesses
Natural Law/Virtue Ethics. Morality and Human Nature  Natural Law Theory  Based upon assumption that the good is consistent with fundamental design.
1Chapter SECTION OPENER / CLOSER: INSERT BOOK COVER ART Defining Ethics Section 1.1.
UNIT 1 Ethics and the Law Section 1.1 Defining Ethics Section 1.2
Natural Law AS Revision
Deontological & Consequential Ethics
AS Philosophy & Ethics Mrs Sudds What are your expectations?
Ethical Theory: Absolute & Relativist theory L.O: Be able to understand the concepts of absolutist & relativist morality Explain the characteristics of.
Chapter 1 Understanding Ethics
THEORIES OF ETHICS PART 2 OF CHAPTER 12 (ETHICS).
Kantian ethics (& suicide): Kantian ethics (& suicide): Immanuel Kant ( ). A German philosopher. Ought implies Can Maxims Categorical Imperative.
Objectives: SWBAT  Identify Immanuel Kant  Analyze Kantian Rationality  Identify and discuss the Categorical Imperative.
L.O We are learning how Kant’s theory applies to abortion and homosexuality Wednesday 23 rd October 2013 Applying Kant’s theory Starter: What is your gut.
WHAT IS HIS DUTY? Duty - something that one is expected or required to do by moral or legal obligation. Your response:
HOMOSEXUALITY AND VIRTUE ETHICS.  There is no single view on homosexuality among Virtue ethicists.  Disagreements exist between those who follow the.
AREA 1 GUIDING PRINCIPLES SECTION 3 Consequences (Utilitarian Ethics) Duty and Reason (Kantian Ethics)
1Chapter SECTION OPENER / CLOSER: INSERT BOOK COVER ART Defining Ethics Chapter 1: Ethics & Sources of Law.
Deontology Criticisms Too absolutist, inflexible, severe - no exceptions to moral rules Assigns no moral value to attitudes, feelings, or actions motivated.
Revision.  1. Eudaimonia  2. The Golden Mean  3. Aristotle’s four cardinal virtues  4. Agent-centred  5. Aristotle’s three understandings of happiness?
After today’s lesson I will be able to: Explain Kant’s theory on moral ethics Explain the term ‘categorical imperative’ Understand the phrase 'Duty and.
1Chapter SECTION OPENER / CLOSER: INSERT BOOK COVER ART Defining Ethics Section 1.1.
ETHICALETHICALETHICALETHICAL PRINCIPLESPRINCIPLESPRINCIPLESPRINCIPLES.
Morality in the Modern World
Ethics Overview: Deontological and Teleological ( Consequentalist) Systems.
Introduction  Based on something other than the consequences of a person’s actions  Unlike Egoism  People should act in their own self-interest  Unlike.
Lesson Objective Key Words Lesson outcomes Hypothetical Categorical Imperatives Freedom To evaluate the differences between the Hypothetical and Categorical.
Theory of Consequences and Intentions There are two traditional ways of looking at the “rightness” or “wrongness” of an act. 1. Look at the consequences.
Evaluating the Analogy of the Cave – Plato’s view Plato essentially wants to convince you that the physical world around us is an illusion The analogy.
AS Ethics Utilitarianism Title: - Preference Utilitarianism To begin… What is meant by preference? L/O: To understand Preference Utilitarianism.
MNU Five Other Ethical Systems Dr. Judy Martin Session 7 – February 18, 2014.
Ethical theories tend to suggest a set of principles or rules than all human beings are bound by. Utilitarianism – the greatest good for the greatest.
Moral Theory Review.
Virtue Ethics revision summary
Normative Virtue Ethics
Chapter 1 Understanding Ethics
Michael Lacewing Relativism Michael Lacewing
What is ethics?. What is ethics? “Ethics is about my feelings” Agree or disagree?
ETHICS BOWL kantian ETHICS.
Theory of Health Care Ethics
Recap Key-Terms Cognitivism Non-Cognitivism Realism Anti-Realism
Kant’s Categorical Imperative - revision
Virtue Ethics.
By the end of this lesson you will have:
From Aristotle to the 21st century
VIRTUE ETHICS And Feminist Ethics.
Presentation transcript:

MODERN VIRTUE ETHICS Three types

Theoretical (or cool) Virtue Ethics Aristotle saw virtue as based in Natural Law. Modern Virtue ethicists differ from Aristotle’s view in the following ways: a. They reject the idea of a priori moral laws; b. They reject the idea of an ‘is’ becoming an ‘ought’; c. They base their morality on the moral agent.

Some modern Virtue ethicists see the moral action as important because it makes you virtuous. Others regard the action as of no specific importance. What counts is the moral agent’s nature, how virtuous they are. ROSALIND HURSTHOUSE is a leading figure in this second group.

Hursthouse looks at the virtues that go with Aristotle’s Golden Mean, e.g. courage rather than foolhardiness or cowardice. It is these moral virtues (that she calls the X-factor) that she is interested in. If you, by nature, are virtuous then what you do will be virtuous. If you are bad, your actions can never be virtuous. She argues that people should get into a state of virtuous living and then what they do will always be virtuous.

Criticisms of Hursthouse 1.Your action might seem virtuous but what about your motivation? Hursthouse doesn’t consider this. E.g. I may invade Iraq because I am a virtuous person and wish to get rid of a tyrant, but deep down inside I might be counting the oil revenue!

2. What happens when my state of virtue conflicts with another person’s? Every moral decision impacts on more than one person, and if his/her moral state is as virtuous as mine, how can we both be acting virtuously?

3. How can a virtuous state be judged objectively? I might appear virtuous; I might convince myself that I am virtuous but how can my virtue be truly determined?

Hursthouse’s idea of Virtue Ethics is purely theoretical. It does not have any rules to follow. Hursthouse does not show how a particular character trait could be applied to a specific moral issue. This seems impractical and unhelpful to many.

Practical Virtue Ethics This was a way of answering the problem of Hursthouse’s theoretical Virtue Ethics. It was put forward by MARTHA NUSSBAUM, an academic at the University of Chicago. She uses the principle of phronesis to examine particular issues.

The concept of phronesis is taken from Aristotle, who believed that morality is inbuilt into rational humans. It means “practical wisdom”. It involves rational reflection, and deciding how to put reflection into practice. He argued that humans use phronesis to discover the best way of applying moral concepts to the real world.

Nussbaum’s first major book looked at the issue of justice, which Virtue Ethicists find difficult. This is because the virtue of an individual may clash with the virtue of the whole in cases of justice. People who campaign for justice are often destroyed and end up being sacrificed for their pursuit of it, e.g. Socrates, Jesus, Thomas More.

In 2009 Nussbaum published ‘From Disgust to Humanity’, which looks at issues of sexual orientation. She defends the rights of homosexuals. She claimed that a vitruous life is one which tolerates those who are different as long they do not abuse others. She supports a multicultural society. Yet, unlike relativists, she cannot condone such cultural practices as female circumcision.

Motive (or warm) Virtue Ethics A theory put forward by Roman Catholic philosopher ELIZABETH ANSCOMBE ( ) and her friend PHILIPPA FOOT. Anscombe rejects the is/ought dichotomy. She explains this by referring to a house plant.

Imagine that one day you return home and find that one of your houseplants is limp through lack of water. What do you do? You give it the water that it lacks and hopefully the plant recovers. This is a common sense understanding of is/ought. Just because the plant is limp does not mean that it ought to be so. The plant is limp because it lacks water. You know what to do; you provide it with what it lacks.

Anscombe develops this idea using the analogy of a man shopping in a supermarket. He has a shopping list of ingredients for a meal. He walks around the supermarket placing ingredients into his basket. Suppose he acts impulsively, ignores his list and buys what he wants. He leaves the supermarket and returns home. He has bought the wrong ingredients. He cannot blame his list, whether he or his partner wrote it. It is his fault.

This analogy can be applied to ethics. The shopping list = a list of virtues. In life, the moral agent walks around the ethical supermarket. What counts is not who created the list of virtues (although Anscombe says it is God), but the intention of the moral agent. The moral agent knows what ingredients (virtues) are required for an ethical life but will he/she take them or not?

Virtue Ethics is therefore concerned with ensuring that the moral agent makes the right choices. It is concerned with intentions, with convincing individuals that they should choose the right ingredients needed for a good life and not to live impulsively. This view leads Anscombe to assert the importance of the law of double effect, since it is based on the intentions of the moral agent.

Anscombe’s shopping list of moral virtues and moral evils are real. Humans should be led to buy the right things in the supermarket of life. Buying the right goods will develop the natural goodness of humans. This is achieved by using phronesis.

Anscombe and Foot assume that all humans want a moral life and to live a good life for its own sake. Alasdair MacIntyre disagrees with this assumption. He argues that virtues may be desirable but humans need a reason to be moral. You can’t rely on a concept of natural goodness. E.g. people give presents in order to receive something in return. If they did not, they would stop giving.

So, MacIntyre argues, consequences matter. A degree of consequentialism should be added to Virtue Ethics. People need to know why they should be virtuous. They should work this out by using reason.

The contemporary American philosopher, MICHAEL SLOTE, develops this idea of motives as the basis of Virtue Ethics. Slote calls this warm Virtue Ethics since it is based on human sentiments and feelings rather than obedience to certain theoretical virtues. The moral agent must base moral judgements on virtues such as care and empathy.

Therefore a moral agent may sacrifice his/her life for a sick or elderly relative. This would be the moral thing to do. Slote regard being sentimental as morally good rather than, as Kant and Mill, a sign of ethical weakness. He regards traditional approaches to Virtue Ethics as too cold and clinical. He agrees that the motivation of the moral agent is supremely important.