Dilemma: Division Into Cases Dilemma: p  q p  r q  r  r Premises:x is positive or x is negative. If x is positive, then x 2 is positive. If x is negative,

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Chapter 3 Introduction to Logic © 2008 Pearson Addison-Wesley.
Advertisements

1 Section 1.5 Rules of Inference. 2 Definitions Theorem: a statement that can be shown to be true Proof: demonstration of truth of theorem –consists of.
John Rosson Thursday February 15, 2007 Survey of Mathematical Ideas Math 100 Chapter 3, Logic.
Chapter 1 The Logic of Compound Statements. Section 1.3 Valid & Invalid Arguments.
Chapter 1 The Logic of Compound Statements. Section 1.2 – 1.3 (Modus Tollens) Conditional and Valid & Invalid Arguments.
Discrete Mathematics Lecture 1 Logic of Compound Statements Harper Langston New York University.
Discrete Structures Chapter 1 Part A Fundamentals of Logic Nurul Amelina Nasharuddin Multimedia Department 1.
Discrete Mathematics Lecture 2 Alexander Bukharovich New York University.
Through the Looking Glass, 1865
Introduction to Logic Logical Form: general rules
Deductive reasoning.
Fall 2002CMSC Discrete Structures1 Let’s proceed to… Mathematical Reasoning.
Harper Langston New York University Summer 2015
2. Empty Set, Partitions, Power Set
Chapter 3 Section 4 – Slide 1 Copyright © 2009 Pearson Education, Inc. AND.
3.6 Analyzing Arguments with Truth Tables
Copyright © Curt Hill Rules of Inference What is a valid argument?
CSCI 115 Chapter 2 Logic. CSCI 115 §2.1 Propositions and Logical Operations.
2. The Logic of Compound Statements
 Predicate: A sentence that contains a finite number of variables and becomes a statement when values are substituted for the variables. ◦ Domain: the.
Week 3 - Monday.  What did we talk about last time?  Predicate logic  Multiple quantifiers  Negating multiple quantifiers  Arguments with quantified.
Week 2 - Friday.  What did we talk about last time?  Predicate logic  Negation  Multiple quantifiers.
(CSC 102) Lecture 7 Discrete Structures. Previous Lectures Summary Predicates Set Notation Universal and Existential Statement Translating between formal.
Chapter 2 The Logic of Quantified Statements. Section 2.4 Arguments with Quantified Statements.
Chapter 1 Logic Section 1-1 Statements Open your book to page 1 and read the section titled “To the Student” Now turn to page 3 where we will read the.
1 Sections 1.5 & 3.1 Methods of Proof / Proof Strategy.
2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.
Arguments with Quantified Statements M Universal Instantiation If some property is true for everything in a domain, then it is true of any particular.
Fundamentals of Logic 1. What is a valid argument or proof? 2. Study system of logic 3. In proving theorems or solving problems, creativity and insight.
Chapter 3: Introduction to Logic. Logic Main goal: use logic to analyze arguments (claims) to see if they are valid or invalid. This is useful for math.
(CSC 102) Lecture 8 Discrete Structures. Previous Lectures Summary Predicates Set Notation Universal and Existential Statement Translating between formal.
1 Introduction to Abstract Mathematics Chapter 2: The Logic of Quantified Statements. Predicate Calculus Instructor: Hayk Melikya 2.3.
Valid and Invalid Arguments
Chapter 2 Fundamentals of Logic 1. What is a valid argument or proof?
Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved.
Arguments with Quantified Statements Lecture 10 Section 2.4 Thu, Jan 27, 2005.
Week 4 - Friday.  What did we talk about last time?  Floor and ceiling  Proof by contradiction.
1 Chapter 2.1 Chapter 2.2 Chapter 2.3 Chapter 2.4 All images are copyrighted to their respective copyright holders and reproduced here for academic purposes.
Discrete Mathematical Structures: Theory and Applications 1 Logic: Learning Objectives  Learn about statements (propositions)  Learn how to use logical.
Week 2 - Friday.  What did we talk about last time?  Predicate logic  Negation  Multiple quantifiers.
Discrete Mathematics Lecture 2 Continuing Logic, Quantified Logic, Beginning Proofs Harper Langston New York University Summer 2016.
Harper Langston New York University Summer 2017
Arguments with Quantified Statements
2. The Logic of Compound Statements Summary
Valid and Invalid Arguments
3. The Logic of Quantified Statements Summary
Discrete Mathematics Lecture 1 Logic of Compound Statements
Discrete Mathematics Logic of Compound Statements
Methods of proof Section 1.6 & 1.7 Wednesday, June 20, 2018
Deductive Arguments.
Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved.
2 Chapter Introduction to Logic and Sets
Proposition logic and argument CISC2100, Spring 2017 X.Zhang
Logical Inferences: A set of premises accompanied by a suggested conclusion regardless of whether or not the conclusion is a logical consequence of the.
CS201: Data Structures and Discrete Mathematics I
Mathematical Reasoning
Chapter 3 Introduction to Logic 2012 Pearson Education, Inc.
Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved.
TRUTH TABLES continued.
1 Chapter An Introduction to Problem Solving
1 Chapter An Introduction to Problem Solving
Predicates and Quantifiers
Discrete Mathematics Lecture 4 Logic of Quantified Statements
Mathematical Reasoning
8C Truth Tables, 8D, 8E Implications 8F Valid Arguments
Logic and Reasoning.
Chapter 3 Introduction to Logic © 2008 Pearson Addison-Wesley.
CS201: Data Structures and Discrete Mathematics I
If there is any case in which true premises lead to a false conclusion, the argument is invalid. Therefore this argument is INVALID.
If there is any case in which true premises lead to a false conclusion, the argument is invalid. Therefore this argument is INVALID.
Presentation transcript:

Dilemma: Division Into Cases Dilemma: p  q p  r q  r  r Premises:x is positive or x is negative. If x is positive, then x 2 is positive. If x is negative, then x 2 is positive. Conclusion: x 2 is positive.

Application: Find My Glasses 1. If my glasses are on the kitchen table, then I saw them at breakfast. 2. I was reading in the kitchen or I was reading in the living room. 3. If I was reading in the living room, then my glasses are on the coffee table. 4. I did not see my glasses at breakfast. 5. If I was reading in bed, then my glasses are on the bed table. 6. If I was reading in the kitchen, then my glasses are on the kitchen table.

Find My Glasses ( cont’d. ) Let:p = My glasses are on the kitchen table. q = I saw my glasses at breakfast. r = I was reading in the living room. s = I was reading in the kitchen. t = My glasses are on the coffee table. u = I was reading in bed. v = My glasses are on the bed table.

Find My Glasses ( cont’d. ) Then the original statements become: 1. p  q2. r  s3. r  t 4. ~q5. u  v6. s  p and we can deduce (why?): 1. p  q2. s  p 3. r  s 4. r  t ~q ~p ~s r  ~p  ~s  r  t Hence the glasses are on the coffee table!

Fallacies A fallacy is an error in reasoning that results in an invalid argument. Three common fallacies: –Using vague or ambiguous premises; –Begging the question; –Jumping to a conclusion. Two dangerous fallacies: –Converse error; –Inverse error.

Converse Error If Zeke cheats, then he sits in the back row. Zeke sits in the back row.  Zeke cheats. The fallacy here is caused by replacing the impication (Zeke cheats  sits in back) with its biconditional form (Zeke cheats  sits in back), implying the converse (sits in back  Zeke cheats).

Inverse Error If Zeke cheats, then he sits in the back row. Zeke does not cheat.  Zeke does not sit in the back row. The fallacy here is caused by replacing the impication (Zeke cheats  sits in back) with its inverse form (Zeke does not cheat  does not sit in back), instead of the contrapositive (does not sit in back  Zeke does not cheat).

Universal Instantiation Consider the following statement: All men are mortal Socrates is a man. Therefore, Socrates is mortal. This argument form is valid and is called universal instantiation. In summary, it states that if P(x) is true for all x Î D and if a Î D, then P(a) must be true.

Universal Modus Ponens Formal Version:  x Î D, if P(x), then Q(x). P(a) for some a Î D.  Q(a). Informal Version: If x makes P(x) true, then x makes Q(x) true. a makes P(x) true.  a makes Q(x) true. The first line is called the major premise and the second line is the minor premise.

Universal Modus Tollens Formal Version:  x Î D, if P(x), then Q(x). ~Q(a) for some a Î D.  ~P(a). Informal Version: If x makes P(x) true, then x makes Q(x) true. a makes Q(x) false.  a makes P(x) false.

Examples Universal Modus Ponens or Tollens??? If a number is even, then its square is even. 10 is even. Therefore, 100 is even. If a number is even, then its square is even. 25 is odd. Therefore, 5 is odd.

Using Diagrams to Show Validity Does this diagram portray the argument of the second slide? Mortals Men Socrates

Modus Ponens in Pictures For all x, P(x) implies Q(x). P(a). Therefore, Q(a). {x | Q(x)} {x | P(x)} a

A Modus Tollens Example All humans are mortal. Zeus is not mortal. Therefore, Zeus is not human. Mortals Humans Zeus

Modus Tollens in Pictures For all x, P(x) implies Q(x). ~Q(a). Therefore, ~P(a). {x | Q(x)} {x | P(x)} a

Converse Error in Pictures All humans are mortal. Felix the cat is mortal. Therefore, Felix the cat is human. Mortals Humans Felix?

Inverse Error in Pictures All humans are mortal. Felix the cat is not human. Therefore, Felix the cat is not mortal. Mortals Humans Felix?

Quantified Form of Converse and Inverse Errors Converse Error:  x, P(x) implies Q(x). Q(a), for a particular a.  P(a). Inverse Error:  x, P(x) implies Q(x). ~P(a), for a particular a.  ~Q(a).

An Argument with “No” Major Premise: No Naturals are negative. Minor Premise: k is a negative number. Conclusion: k is not a Natural number. Natural numbers Negative numbers k

Abduction Major Premise: All thieves go to Paul’s Bar. Minor Premise: Tom goes to Paul’s Bar. Converse Error: Therefore, Tom is a thief. Although we can’t conclude decisively if Tom is a thief or not, if we have further information that 99 of the 100 people in Paul’s Bar are thieves, then the odds are that Tom is a thief and the converse error is actually valid here. This is called abduction by Artificial Intelligence researchers.