Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2013 Lecture 20.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
ECON 1450 – Professor Berkowitz Lectures on Chapter 2 Tort Law Area of Common Law concerned with accidental injuries Potential defendant engages in activity.
Advertisements

What You’ll Learn How to define negligence (p. 88)
Q UINCY COLLEGE Paralegal Studies Program Paralegal Studies Program Litigation and Procedure Negligence and Strict Liability Litigation and Procedure Negligence.
Chapter 18: Torts A Civil Wrong
Law I Chapter 18.
Tort Law Part 2 Negligence and Liability. Negligence Most common tort Accidental or Unintentional Tort Failure to show a degree of care that a “reasonable”
Chapter 18 Torts.
Chapter 16 Lesson 1 Civil and Criminal Law.
Chapter 3 Tort Law.
Tort Law – Unintentional torts
Hazards Liability and Tort Lecture 8. Outline Another economic role for the government is regulating hazards and risks Factory producing explosives (location.
Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2011 Lecture 17.
Law and Economics-Charles W. Upton Extensions of the Model.
Chapter 16 Street Law Text pp
Strict Liability and Torts and Public Policy Mrs. Weigl.
 A body of rights, obligations, and remedies that is applied by courts in civil proceedings to provide relief for persons who have suffered harm from.
No Fault Auto Insurance Cassie Harmer, Melissa Fjelstrom, Brent Wuehler.
Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2013 Lecture 19.
Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 19.
Chapter 18.  Criminal Law: crime against the state  Civil Law: person commits a wrong, not always a violation of law  Plaintiff-the harmed individual,
4Chapter SECTION OPENER / CLOSER: INSERT BOOK COVER ART Intentional Torts Section 4.1.
Risk Management & Insurance
Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2009 Lecture 19.
Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2012 Lecture 17.
 1. Duty-The accused wrongdoer owed a duty of care to the injured person  2. Breach of Duty- the defendant’s conduct breached that duty  3. Causation-defendant’s.
Civil Law Resolutions to disputes between people..
Business Law. Your neighbor Shana is using a multipurpose woodcutting machine in her basement hobby shop. Suddenly, because of a defect in the two-year.
Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2012 Lecture 18.
Chapter 25 Employment - Related Injuries I. Requiring A Safe Workplace A.Occupational Safety & Health Administration Act of 1970 (OSHA)-prevent injuries.
Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2013 Lecture 21.
Chapter 5 Torts and Civil Law.
Unit 6 – Civil Law.
Exploring Business © 2009 FlatWorld Knowledge 16-1 The Legal and Regulatory Environment of Business.
Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 20.
Torts.
Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2009 Lecture 18.
Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2012 Lecture 19.
Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2010 Lecture 17.
Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2010 Lecture 19.
3.2 Negligence and Liability
Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2011 Lecture 18.
Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2009 Lecture 16.
Torts A.K.A. civil law. What’s a Tort? Torts more or less means “wrongs” Refers to civil laws Based on both common law (decisions made by judges) and.
TORTS: A Civil Wrong. Fairplay.org What is a Tort? A civil wrong A breach of some obligation Causing harm or injury to someone –Negligence –Libel Plaintiff.
Economics of Punitive Damages. Compensatory vs. Punitive Damages Compensatory damages are meant to return the victim to the pre-injury state Punitive.
Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2015 Lecture 18.
Defences for Negligence. The best defence is Negligence did not exist, or the defendant didn’t owe the plaintiff a duty of care. The best defence is Negligence.
Published by Flat World Knowledge, Inc. © 2014 by Flat World Knowledge, Inc. All rights reserved. Your use of this work is subject to the License Agreement.
"Fun is like life insurance; the older you get, the more it costs." -Frank McKinney (humorist and journalist)
Civil Law An overview of Tort Law – the largest branch of civil law Highlight the differences between tort law and criminal law How torts developed historically.
Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2010 Lecture 18.
Torts: A Civil Wrong Chapter 18. The Idea of Liability Under criminal law, wrongs committed are called crimes. Under civil law, wrongs committed are called.
TORTS: A CIVIL WRONG Chapter 18. TORTS: A CIVIL WRONG Under criminal law, wrongs committed are called crimes. Under civil law, wrongs committed are called.
CHAPTER 18 PART I Torts: A Civil Wrong. A Civil Wrong In criminal law, when someone commits a wrong, we call it a crime. In civil law, when someone commits.
Chapter 18. Understand the primary goals of tort law: (1) fair and efficient settlement of disputes; (2) compensation for those suffering damages; (3)
Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2015 Lecture 17.
 In some circumstances, responsibility lies not only with the person undertaking (or failing to undertake) an action, but also with an individual responsible.
Negligence Tort law establishes standards for the care that people must show to one another. Negligence is the conduct that falls below this standard.
Certain professionals, such as doctors, pilots, and plumbers, are held to the standards of reasonably skilled professionals in their field. Even minors.
Civil Law An overview of Tort Law – the largest branch of civil law
Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2017 Lecture 19.
Negligence.
Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2011 Lecture 18.
Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2010 Lecture 18.
Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2016 Lecture 19.
Torts “ Civil Wrongs” Chapter 17
Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2012 Lecture 18.
Negligence Ms. Weigl.
Lesson 6-1 Civil Law (Tort Law).
Differences and similarities
Presentation transcript:

Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2013 Lecture 20

1 So far in tort law…

2  Under strict liability:  random errors in setting damages have no effect  systematic errors in setting damages will skew the injurer’s incentives in the same direction  failure to consistently hold injurers liable lead to less precaution  Under negligence:  small errors, random or systematic, in setting damages have no effect  systematic errors in the legal standard of care have a one-to-one effect on precaution  random errors in the legal standard of care lead to more precaution  So…  when court can assess damages more accurately than standard of care, strict liability is better  when court can better assess standards, negligence is better  when standard of care is vague, court should err on side of leniency Wednesday, we considered the effect of mistakes in implementing tort law

3  Negligence rules lead to longer, more expensive trials  Simpler to just prove harm and causation  But negligence rules lead to fewer trials  Not every victim has a case, since not every injurer was negligent  Unclear which system will be cheaper overall What about relative administrative costs of the two systems?

4  Negligence with a defense of contributory negligence was dominant liability rule in common law countries  Negligent injurer is liable, unless victim was also negligent  Example: a car going 60 mph hits a car going 35 in a 30-mph zone  Since victim was also negligent, injurer is not liable  Last 40 years, most U.S. states have adopted a comparative negligence rule  Usually through legislation, sometimes through judicial decision  Appealing from fairness point of view  But any negligence rule leads to efficient precaution  So how do we explain the move? One other point having to do with errors

5  Evidentiary uncertainty  Given a legal standard for negligence, x n …  …and an actual level of precaution taken, x…  still uncertainty in whether the court will find negligence  Evidentiary uncertainty, like random errors in setting x n, leads to over-precaution…  …but comparative negligence partly mitigates this Comparative Negligence and Evidentiary Uncertainty

6 Comparative negligence and evidentiary uncertainty x $ p(x) A wx wx + p(x) A x*  Comparative negligence mitigates effect of evidentiary uncertainty Any negligence rule Simple negligence, evidentiary uncertainty Comparative negligence, evidentiary uncertainty

7 Does it all matter?

8  Reviews a wide range of empirical studies  Finds: tort law does affect peoples’ behavior, in the direction the theory predicts…  …but not as strongly as the model suggests Gary Schwartz, Reality in the Economic Analysis of Tort Law: Does Tort Law Really Deter?

9  Reviews a wide range of empirical studies  Finds: tort law does affect peoples’ behavior, in the direction the theory predicts…  …but not as strongly as the model suggests  Most academic work either…  took the model literally, or  pointed out reasons why model was wrong and liability rules might not affect behavior at all  Schwartz: the truth is somewhere in between Gary Schwartz, Reality in the Economic Analysis of Tort Law: Does Tort Law Really Deter?

10 “Yet between the economists’ strong claim that tort law systematically deters and the critics’ response that tort law rarely if ever deters lies an intermediate position: tort law, while not as effective as economic models suggest, may still be somewhat successful in achieving its stated deterrence goals. …The information [in various studies] suggests that the strong form of the deterrence argument is in error. Yet it provides support for that argument in its moderate form: sector-by-sector, tort law provides something significant by way of deterrence.” Gary Schwartz, Reality in the Economic Analysis of Tort Law: Does Tort Law Really Deter?

11 “Much of the modern economic analysis, then, is a worthwhile endeavor because it provides a stimulating intellectual exercise rather than because it reveals the impact of liability rules on the conduct of real-world actors. Consider, then, those public-policy analysts who, for whatever reason, do not secure enjoyment from a sophisticated economic proof – who care about the economic analysis only because it might show how tort liability rules can actually improve levels of safety in society. These analysts would be largely warranted in ignoring those portions of the law-and-economics literature that aim at fine- tuning.” Gary Schwartz, Reality in the Economic Analysis of Tort Law: Does Tort Law Really Deter?

12  Worker’s compensation rules in the U.S.  Employer is liable – whether or not he was negligent – for economic costs of on-the-job accidents  Victim still bears non-economic costs (pain and suffering, etc.) “…Worker’s compensation disavows its ability to manipulate liability rules so as to achieve in each case the precisely efficient result in terms of primary behavior; It accepts as adequate the notion that if the law imposes a significant portion of the accident loss on each set of parties, these parties will have reasonably strong incentives to take many of the steps that might be successful in reducing accident risks.” Gary Schwartz, Reality in the Economic Analysis of Tort Law: Does Tort Law Really Deter?

13 Relaxing the assumptions of our model

14  So far, our model has assumed:  People are rational  Injurers pay damages in full  They don’t run out of money and go bankrupt  There are no regulations in place other than the liability rule  There is no insurance  Litigation is costless  We can think about what would happen when each of these assumptions is violated Our model thus far has assumed…

15  Behavioral economics: people systematically misjudge value of probabilistic events  Daniel Kahneman and Amos Tversky, “Prospect Theory: An Analysis of Decision under Risk”  45% chance of $6,000 versus 90% chance of $3,000  Most people (86%) chose the second  0.1% chance of $6,000 versus 0.2% chance of $3,000  Most people (73%) chose the first  But under expected utility, either u(6000) > 2 u(3000), or it’s not  So people don’t actually seem to be maximizing expected utility  And the “errors” have to do with how people evaluate probabilities Assumption 1: Rationality

16  People seem to overestimate chance of unlikely events with well-publicized, catastrophic events  Freakonomics: people fixate on exotic, unlikely risks, rather than more commonplace ones that are more dangerous Assumption 1: Rationality

17  People seem to overestimate chance of unlikely events with well-publicized, catastrophic events  Freakonomics: people fixate on exotic, unlikely risks, rather than more commonplace ones that are more dangerous  How to apply this: accidents with power tools  Could be designed safer, could be used more cautiously  Suppose consumers underestimate risk of an accident  Negligence with defense of contributory negligence: would lead to tools which are very safe when used correctly  But would lead to too many accidents when consumers are irrational  Strict liability would lead to products which were less likely to cause accidents even when used recklessly Assumption 1: Rationality

18  Another type of irrationality: unintended lapses  “Many accidents result from tangled feet, quavering hands, distracted eyes, slips of the tongue, wandering minds, weak wills, emotional outbursts, misjudged distances, or miscalculated consequences” Assumption 1: Rationality

19  Strict liability: injurer internalizes expected harm done, leading to efficient precaution  But what if…  Harm done is $1,000,000  Injurer only has $100,000  So injurer can only pay $100,000  But if he anticipates this, he knows D << A…  …so he doesn’t internalize full cost of harm…  …so he takes inefficiently little precaution  Injurer whose liability is limited by bankruptcy is called judgment-proof Assumption 2: Injurers pay damages in full

20  Owner of an oil tanker  Any accident would be an environmental catastrophe, doing $50,000,000 of harm  Upgraded navigation system would cost $225,000, and reduce likelihood of an accident from 1/100 to 1/500  Precaution reduces expected harm from $500,000 to $100,000, costs $225,000, so efficient to take precaution  If company would be forced to pay $50,000,000 after an accident, then under strict liability, would choose to buy new nav system  Suppose the business is only worth $5,000,000  If there’s an accident, pay the $5,000,000 and go out of business  Now nav system reduces expected damages from $50,000 to $10,000 – not worth the cost  So judgment-proof business would take too little precaution Example of judgment-proofness (from old final exam)

21  What stops me from speeding?  If I cause an accident, I’ll have to pay for it  Even if I don’t cause an accident, I might get a speeding ticket  Similarly, fire regulations might require a store to have a working fire extinguisher  Regulations supply additional incentive to take precaution Assumption 3: No regulation

22  We saw, if business is only worth $5,000,000, liability does not create enough incentive to upgrade nav system  Now suppose government passes regulation requiring modern navigation systems on all oil tankers  If business doesn’t upgrade, 1 in 5 chance of being caught by safety inspector and having to pay a $1,000,000 fine  Now, combining liability with regulation…  Upgrade: cost of new nav system is $225,000, expected damages are $10,000  private cost is $235,000  Don’t upgrade: expected damages are $50,000, expected government fine is $200,000  private cost is $250,000  Liability + regulation gives enough incentive to take precaution, even though either one alone would not be enough Continuing the example of judgment-proofness from before…

23  When liability > injurer’s wealth, liability does not create enough incentive for efficient precaution  Regulations which require efficient precaution solve the problem  Regulations also work better than liability when accidents impose small harm on large group of people Assumption 3: No regulation

24  We assumed injurer or victim actually bears cost of accident  When injurer or victim has insurance, they no longer have incentive to take precaution  But, insurance tends not to be complete Assumption 4: No insurance

25  Insurance reduces incentive to take precaution  Moral hazard  Insurance companies have ways to reduce moral hazard  Deductibles, copayments  Increasing premiums after accidents  Insurers may impose safety standards that policyholders must meet Assumption 4: No insurance

26  If litigation is costly, this affects incentives in both directions  If lawsuits are costly for victims, they may bring fewer suits  Some accidents “unpunished”  less incentive for precaution  But if being sued is costly for injurers, they internalize more than the cost of the accident  So more incentive for precaution  A clever (unrealistic) way to reduce litigation costs  At the start of every lawsuit, flip a coin  Heads: lawsuit proceeds, damages are doubled  Tails: lawsuit immediately dismissed  Expected damages are the same  same incentives for precaution  But half as many lawsuits to deal with! Assumption 5: Litigation costs nothing

27 Perfect Compensation

28  Perfect compensatory damages (D = A)  Returns victim to original level of well-being  (Works like insurance)  And sets correct incentive for injurers  But in some cases, hard to determine level  Might be no price at which you’d be willing to give up a leg  Certainly no price at which a parent would be indifferent toward losing a child Perfect compensation

29  Recommended jury instructions, Massachusetts:  “Recovery for wrongful death represents damages to the survivors for the loss of value of decedent’s life. There is no special formula under the law to assess the plaintiff’s damages…  It is your obligation to assess what is fair, adequate, and just.  You must use your wisdom and judgment and your sense of basic justice to translate into dollars and cents the amount which will fully, fairly, and reasonably compensate the next of kin for the death of the decedent.  You must be guided by your common sense and your conscience on the evidence of the case…”  And from California:  “…You should award reasonable compensation for the loss of love, companionship, comfort, affection, society, solace or moral support.” Perfect compensation

30  Most people would rather be horribly injured than killed  Which means killing someone does more damage than injuring someone  But compensatory damages tend to be lower for a fatal accident than an accident which crippled someone  When someone is badly injured, may require huge amount of money to compensate them  In wrongful-death case, damages compensate victim’s loved ones, but no attempt to compensate victim  So these damages tend to be smaller One other odd feature of compensatory damages…

31 What’s a life worth?

32  Assessing damages in a wrongful death lawsuit requires some notion of what a life is worth  Safety regulators also need some notion of what a life is worth  Kip Viscusi, The Value of Risks to Life and Health  Regulators need to decide “where to draw the line” What’s a life worth? $72,000,000,000Proposed OSHA formaldehyde standard $ 104,200,000EPA asbestos regulations $ 89,300,000OSHA asbestos regulations $ 1,300,000Car side door protection standards $ 200,000Airplane cabin fire protection Estimated cost per life savedRegulation

33  Let w be starting wealth, p probability of death  There might be some amount of money M such that  Breaks down when p = 1 not because can’t equate death with compensation, but because second term vanishes  If we can find M, we can “solve for” u(death)!  Ask a bunch of people how much money they would need to take a 1/1000 chance of death?  Do a lab experiment where you expose people to a risk of death?  Better idea: impute how much compensation people require from the real-life choices they make Kip Viscusi, The Value of Risks to Life and Health p u(death) + (1 – p) u(w+M)= u(w)

34  Lots of day-to-day choices increase or decrease our risk of death  Choose between Volvo and sports car with fiberglass body  Take a job washing skyscraper windows, or office job that pays less  Buy smoke detectors and fire extinguishers, or don’t  “Hand Rule Damages”  Hand Rule: precaution is cost-justified if cost of precaution < reduction in accidents X cost of accident  Suppose side-curtain airbags reduce risk of fatal accident by 1/1000  If someone pays $1,000 extra for a car with side-curtain airbags, it must mean that $1,000 < 1/1000 * value of their life  or, implicitly, they value their life more than $1,000,000 Kip Viscusi, The Value of Risks to Life and Health

35  Viscusi surveys lots of existing studies which impute value of life from peoples’ decisions  Many use wage differentials  How much higher are wages for risky jobs compared to safe jobs?  Others look at…  Decisions to speed, wear seatbelts, buy smoke detectors, smoke cigarettes  Decision to live in very polluted areas (comparing property values)  Prices of newer, safer cars versus older, more dangerous ones  Some used surveys to ask how people would make tradeoffs between money and safety  Each paper reaches some estimate for implicit value people attach to their lives Kip Viscusi, The Value of Risks to Life and Health

36 What does Viscusi find?

37 What does Viscusi find? 24 studies based on wage differentials Implicit value of life

38 What does Viscusi find? 7 studies using other risk-money tradeoffs 4.0 Prices of new automobilesAutomobile accident risks, Purchase price of smoke detector Fire fatality risks without smoke detectors, Estimated monetary equivalent of effect of risk info Cigarette smoking risks, Property values in Allegheny Co., PA Mortality effects of air pollution, Purchase price of smoke detectors Fire fatality risks without smoke detectors, Estimated disutility of seat belts Automobile death risks, Value of driver time based on wage rates Highway speed-related accident risk, 1973 Implicit Value of life ($ millions) Component of the Monetary Tradeoff Nature of Risk, Year

39 What does Viscusi find? 6 studies based on surveys 1.2 Series of contingent valuation questions, New Zealand survey, Traffic safety 2.7 (median) 9.7 (mean) Interactive computer program with pairwise auto risk-living cost tradeoffs until indifference achieved, 1987 Automobile accident risks 3.8 Willingness to pay for risk reduction, U.K. survey, 1982 Motor vehicle accidents 3.4 (pay), 8.8 (accept) Willingness to pay, willingness to accept change in job risk in mail survey, 1984 Job fatality risk 15.6 Mail survey willingness to accept increased risk, small (30) U.K. sample, 1975 Airline safety and locational life expectancy risks 0.1 Willingness to pay question, door-to-door small (36) Boston sample Improved ambulance service, post-heart attack lives Implicit Value of Life ($ millions) Survey Methodology Nature of Risk

40  Wide range of results  Most suggest value of life between $1,000,000 and $10,000,000  Many clustered between $3,000,000 and $7,000,000  Even with wide range, he argues this is very useful:  “In practice, value-of-life debates seldom focus on whether the appropriate value of life should be $3 or $4 million…  However, the estimates do provide guidance as to whether risk reduction efforts that cost $50,000 per life saved or $50 million per life saved are warranted.”  “The threshold for the Office of Management and Budget to be successful in rejecting proposed risk regulations has been in excess of $100 million.”  C&U: NHTSA uses $2.5 million for value of traffic fatality  Current: EPA $9.1 MM, FDA $7.9 MM, Transpo Dept $6 MM What does Viscusi find?

41 More twists on liability

42  Vicarious liability is when one person is held liable for harm caused by another  Parents may be liable for harm caused by their child  Employer may be liable for harm caused by employee  Respondeat superior – “let the master answer”  Employer is liable for torts of employee if employee was acting within the scope of his employment Vicarious Liability

43  Gives employers incentive to...  be more careful who they hire  be more careful what they assign employees to do  supervise employees more carefully  Employers may be better able to make these decisions than employees…  …and employees may be judgment-proof Vicarious Liability

44  Vicarious liability can be implemented through…  Strict liability rule: employer liable for any harm caused by employee (as long as employee was acting within scope of employment)  Negligence rule: employer is only liable if he was negligent in supervising employee  Which is better? It depends.  If proving negligent supervision is too hard, strict vicarious liability might work better  But an example favoring negligent vicarious liability… Vicarious Liability

45  Suppose you were harmed by accident caused by two injurers  Joint liability: you can sue them both together  Several liability: you can sue each one separately  Several liability with contribution: each is only liable for his share of damage  Joint and several liability: you can sue either one for the full amount of the harm  Joint and several liability with contribution: the one you sued could then sue his friend to get back half his money Joint and Several Liability

46  Joint and several liability holds under common law when…  Defendants acted together to cause the harm, or…  Harm was indivisible (impossible to tell who was at fault)  Good for the victim, because…  No need to prove exactly who caused harm  Greater chance of collecting full level of damages  Instead of suing person most responsible, could sue person most likely to be able to pay Joint and Several Liability