Download presentation
Presentation is loading. Please wait.
Published byMelvin Stafford Modified over 8 years ago
1
Socrates on Evil And Ignorance
2
Introduction Sources Sources Socrates (470-399) wrote nothing Socrates (470-399) wrote nothing Aristophanes: Clouds Aristophanes: Clouds Xenophon: Memorabilia Xenophon: Memorabilia Plato wrote many dialogues starring Socrates Plato wrote many dialogues starring Socrates
3
Introduction Sources Sources Socrates (470-399) wrote nothing Socrates (470-399) wrote nothing Aristophanes: Clouds Aristophanes: Clouds Xenophon: Memorabilia Xenophon: Memorabilia Plato wrote many dialogues starring Socrates Plato wrote many dialogues starring Socrates Can we trust what Plato says? (‘Socratic Problem’) Can we trust what Plato says? (‘Socratic Problem’) Assume that early dialogues give Socrates’ views Assume that early dialogues give Socrates’ views
4
Introduction Sources Sources Socrates (470-399) wrote nothing Socrates (470-399) wrote nothing Aristophanes: Clouds Aristophanes: Clouds Xenophon: Memorabilia Xenophon: Memorabilia Plato wrote many dialogues starring Socrates Plato wrote many dialogues starring Socrates Can we trust what Plato says? (‘Socratic Problem’) Can we trust what Plato says? (‘Socratic Problem’) Assume that early dialogues give Socrates’ views Assume that early dialogues give Socrates’ views Euthyphro, Apology, Protagoras, Meno, and Crito Euthyphro, Apology, Protagoras, Meno, and Crito
5
Method Sophists in the background Sophists in the background Combine two trends Extensive foreign contacts leads to cultural relativism. (Custom is king of all.) Extensive foreign contacts leads to cultural relativism. (Custom is king of all.)
6
Method Herodotus When [Darius] was king of Persia, he summoned the Greeks who happened to be present at his court, and asked them what they would take to eat the dead bodies of their fathers. They replied that they would not do it for any money in the world. Later, in the presence of the Greeks, and through an interpreter, so they could understand what was said, he asked some Indians, of the tribe called Callatiae, who do in fact eat their parents’ dead bodies, what they would take to burn them. They uttered a cry of horror and forbade him to mention such a dreadful thing. One can see by this what custom can do, and Pindar, in my opinion, was right when he called it ‘king of all’.
7
Method Sophists in the background Sophists in the background Combine two trends Extensive foreign contacts leads to cultural relativism. (Custom is king of all.) Extensive foreign contacts leads to cultural relativism. (Custom is king of all.)
8
Method Sophists in the background Sophists in the background Combine two trends Extensive foreign contacts leads to cultural relativism. (Custom is king of all.) Extensive foreign contacts leads to cultural relativism. (Custom is king of all.) Importance of Law leads to demand for teachers of argument – Sophists Importance of Law leads to demand for teachers of argument – Sophists
9
Method Sophists in the background Sophists in the background Combine two trends Extensive foreign contacts leads to cultural relativism. (Custom is king of all.) Extensive foreign contacts leads to cultural relativism. (Custom is king of all.) Importance of Law leads to demand for teachers of argument – Sophists Importance of Law leads to demand for teachers of argument – Sophists Proud to declare that they could make the worse case appear to be the better case Proud to declare that they could make the worse case appear to be the better case
10
Method Sophists in the background Sophists in the backgroundResult Ethical relativism. Ethical relativism.
11
Method Sophists in the background Sophists in the backgroundResult Ethical relativism. Ethical relativism. Protagoras: ‘Man is the measure of all things.’ Protagoras: ‘Man is the measure of all things.’ Aristotle explains: [w]hat seems to any man to be the case really is the case. But if this is so, it follows that the same thing both is and is not, or is bad and good, and so with what I said in all other opposite statements; for things often appear to be beautiful to some and the contrary to others, and what appears to each man is the measure.
12
Method Sophists in the background Sophists in the backgroundResult Ethical relativism. Ethical relativism. Thrasymachus: ‘Justice is the interest of the strong.’ Thrasymachus: ‘Justice is the interest of the strong.’ The Athenians explain to the Melians: So far as right and wrong are concerned they think that there is no difference between the two, that those who still preserve their independence do so because they are strong, and that if we fail to attack them it is because we are afraid.
13
Method Elenchus Elenchus Socrates professes ignorance Socrates professes ignorance
14
Method Elenchus Elenchus Socrates professes ignorance Socrates professes ignorance The Oracle at Delphi calls him the wisest The Oracle at Delphi calls him the wisest He enquires of those who claim to know He enquires of those who claim to know He finds that they don’t know He finds that they don’t know At least Socrates knows that he doesn’t know At least Socrates knows that he doesn’t know
15
Method Elenchus Elenchus Socrates professes ignorance Socrates professes ignorance The Oracle at Delphi calls him the wisest The Oracle at Delphi calls him the wisest He enquires of those who claim to know He enquires of those who claim to know He finds that they don’t know He finds that they don’t know At least Socrates knows that he doesn’t know At least Socrates knows that he doesn’t know The search for truth is a collaboration The search for truth is a collaboration Sophists treat argument as a competitive sport Sophists treat argument as a competitive sport
16
Method Elenchus Elenchus Question and answer session with the following rules and goals: Question and answer session with the following rules and goals: Socrates asks all the questions. Socrates asks all the questions. The interlocutor must answer every question. The interlocutor must answer every question. A definition or principle in moral philosophy is sought from the interlocutor. A definition or principle in moral philosophy is sought from the interlocutor. Socrates seeks clarification, gaining assent for various propositions. Socrates seeks clarification, gaining assent for various propositions. These propositions are used to show that the proposed definition or principle is unsatisfactory. These propositions are used to show that the proposed definition or principle is unsatisfactory.
17
Method Elenchus Elenchus Tends to look aimless Tends to look aimless Tends to end without a conclusion Tends to end without a conclusion Nevertheless we think there are some Socratic doctrines Nevertheless we think there are some Socratic doctrines
18
Doctrine Vengeance is always unjust Vengeance is always unjust In the Homeric Tradition wrongdoing ought to be repaid in kind. In the Homeric Tradition wrongdoing ought to be repaid in kind. Justice was conventionally defined as helping one’s friends and harming one’s enemies. Justice was conventionally defined as helping one’s friends and harming one’s enemies. In the Crito, Socrates argues against this view of justice. In the Crito, Socrates argues against this view of justice. He begins by comparing a healthy body with a healthy soul, and argues: He begins by comparing a healthy body with a healthy soul, and argues:
19
Doctrine Vengeance is always unjust Vengeance is always unjust Socrates: And will life be worth having, if that higher part of man be depraved, which is improved by justice and deteriorated by injustice? Do we suppose that principle, whatever it be in man, which has to do with justice and injustice, to be inferior to the body? (Crito 47e)
20
Doctrine Vengeance is always unjust Vengeance is always unjust Crito agrees that Crito agrees that Not life, but a good life, is to be chiefly valued. A good life is a just and honourable one. Doing wrong is always evil and dishonourable. Socrates concludes Socrates concludes We must do no wrong.
21
Doctrine Vengeance is always unjust Vengeance is always unjust Socrates argues Socrates argues S: And what of doing evil in return for evil, which is the morality of the many – is that just or not? C: Not just. S: For doing evil to another is the same as injuring him? C: Very true. S: Then we ought not retaliate or render evil for evil to anyone, whatever evil we may have suffered from him. (Crito 49c)
22
Doctrine Virtue is knowledge Virtue is knowledge And ignorance is evil And ignorance is evil A ‘Socratic Paradox’ A ‘Socratic Paradox’ ‘virtue’ = ‘aretê ’, a type of excellence in function ‘virtue’ = ‘aretê ’, a type of excellence in function
23
Doctrine Virtue is knowledge Virtue is knowledge Surely virtue makes us good. And if we are good, we are benefited, for all that is good benefits. Is that not so? So virtue is something beneficial? Let us then examine what kinds of thing benefit us, taking them up one by one: health, we say, and strength, and beauty, and also wealth. We say that these things, and others of the same kind, benefit us, do we not?
24
Doctrine Virtue is knowledge Virtue is knowledge Yet we say that these same things also sometimes harm one. Do you agree or not? Yet we say that these same things also sometimes harm one. Do you agree or not? Let us now look at the qualities of the soul. There is something you call moderation, and justice, courage, intelligence, memory, munificence, and all such things.
25
Doctrine Virtue is knowledge Virtue is knowledge Consider whichever of these you believe not to be knowledge but different from it; do they not at times harm us, at other times benefit us? Courage, for example, when it is not wisdom but like a kind of recklessness: when a man is reckless without understanding he is harmed, when with understanding he is benefited. Consider whichever of these you believe not to be knowledge but different from it; do they not at times harm us, at other times benefit us? Courage, for example, when it is not wisdom but like a kind of recklessness: when a man is reckless without understanding he is harmed, when with understanding he is benefited.
26
Doctrine Virtue is knowledge Virtue is knowledge The same is true of moderation and mental quickness; when they are learned and disciplined with understanding they are beneficial, but without understanding they are harmful. Therefore, in a word, all that the soul undertakes and endures, if directed by wisdom, ends in happiness, but if directed by ignorance, it ends in the opposite.
27
Doctrine Virtue is knowledge Virtue is knowledge If then virtue is something in the soul and it must be beneficial, it must be knowledge, since all the qualities of the soul are in themselves neither beneficial nor harmful, but accompanied by wisdom or folly they become beneficial or harmful. This argument shows that virtue, being beneficial, must be a kind of wisdom. (Meno, 87c-88d)
28
Doctrine Virtue is knowledge Virtue is knowledge To have virtue, is to know how to live well. To have virtue, is to know how to live well. Virtue knowledge isn’t theoretical knowledge of what is right. Virtue knowledge isn’t theoretical knowledge of what is right. Virtue knowledge is knowledge of how it is to our benefit to do the right thing. Virtue knowledge is knowledge of how it is to our benefit to do the right thing.
29
Doctrine Virtue is knowledge Virtue is knowledge We always act for our own benefit. We always act for our own benefit. S:Do you not think, my good man, that all men desire good things? M:I do not. S:But some desire bad things? M:Yes.
30
Doctrine Virtue is knowledge Virtue is knowledge We always act for our own benefit. We always act for our own benefit. S:Do you mean that they believe the bad things to be good, or that they know they are bad and nevertheless desire them? M:I think there are both kinds. S:Do you think, Meno, that anyone, knowing that bad things are bad, nevertheless desire them? M:I certainly do…..
31
Doctrine Virtue is knowledge Virtue is knowledge We always act for our own benefit. We always act for our own benefit. S:Well then, those who you say desire bad things, believing that bad things harm their possessor, know that they will be harmed by them? M:Necessarily.
32
Doctrine Virtue is knowledge Virtue is knowledge We always act for our own benefit. We always act for our own benefit. S:And do they not think that those who are harmed are miserable to the extent that they are harmed? M:That too is inevitable. S:And that those who are miserable are unhappy? M:I think so.
33
Doctrine Virtue is knowledge Virtue is knowledge We always act for our own benefit. We always act for our own benefit. S:Does anyone wish to be miserable and unhappy? M:I do not think so, Socrates. S:No one then wants what is bad, Meno, unless he wants to be such. For what else is being miserable but to desire bad things and secure them? M:You are probably right, Socrates, and no one wants what is bad. (Meno 77b-78b)
34
Doctrine Virtue is knowledge and knowledge is virtue Virtue is knowledge and knowledge is virtue To have virtue, is to know how to live well. To have virtue, is to know how to live well. We always act for our own benefit. We always act for our own benefit.
35
Doctrine No-one knowingly does wrong No-one knowingly does wrong “Well gentlemen,” I said, “what about this? Aren’t all actions praiseworthy which lead to a painless and pleasant life? And isn’t praiseworthy activity good and beneficial?” They agreed.
36
Doctrine No-one knowingly does wrong No-one knowingly does wrong “So if what is pleasant is good,” I said, “no one who either knows or believes that something else is better than what he is doing, and is in his power to do, subsequently does the other, when he can do what is better. Nor is giving in to oneself anything other than error, nor controlling oneself anything other than wisdom.” They all agreed. “Well now. Is this what you mean by error, having false opinions and being mistaken about matters of importance?” They all agreed to that as well.
37
Doctrine No-one knowingly does wrong No-one knowingly does wrong Now surely,” I said, “no one freely goes for bad things or things he believes to be bad; it’s not, it seems to me, in human nature to be prepared to go for what you think to be bad in preference to what is good. And when you are forced to choose one of two evils, nobody will choose the greater when he can have the lesser. Isn’t that so?” (Protagoras, 358d4)
38
Doctrine A just person can suffer no harm A just person can suffer no harm A good person is a virtuous person A good person is a virtuous person Virtue is a kind of excellence Virtue is a kind of excellence A good life is an excellent life A good life is an excellent life Harm is a diminution of this excellence Harm is a diminution of this excellence A good person will not suffer this diminution A good person will not suffer this diminution A good person cannot be harmed A good person cannot be harmed
Similar presentations
© 2025 SlidePlayer.com. Inc.
All rights reserved.