Download presentation
Presentation is loading. Please wait.
Published byLorena Evans Modified over 8 years ago
1
The Political Economics Approach Advanced Political Economics Fall 2013 Riccardo Puglisi The Political Economy Approach
2
The Political Economy approach Economic AgentsPolitical Agents Political InstitutionsMarkets Economic Policy Economic Aggregates & Prices POLITICAL ECONOMY EQUILIBRA Individuals as ECONOMIC and POLITICAL Agents: ECONOMIC Agents take Labor, Savings, Consumption Decisions POLITICAL Agents (Voters) decide over Economic policies (Redistribution, Public Goods, etc.) Markets and Political Institutions as “aggregators”.
3
Possible Conflicts Citizens typically disagree: Policy instruments are set in the presence of different types of conflicts: (i)among individuals (e.g., redistributive policies), (ii)between individuals and politicians (e.g., rents and corruption); and (iii) among politicians (e.g., rents and elections).
4
Method of Analysis 1. Policy instruments related to conflicts among individuals. KEY ISSUES: redistribution ( how targeted? ), dynamic policies (public debt, growth), rents one-dimensional conflict Typical of broad redistributive programs (eg: welfare state programs) n-dimensional conflict Typical of narrowly target redistribution (eg: local public goods, agricultural subsidies, trade protection)
5
2.Which form of political participation? voting voting plus lobbying Post-electoral politics 3.Which electoral rule? We neglect the effects of electoral rule on party system (always two parties) Yet, majoritarian vs proportional elections directly influence some policies Method of Analysis
6
Tools of Political Economics INDIVIDUAL PREFERENCES AGGREGATION MECHANISM: POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS COLLECTIVE PREFERENCES
7
(Economic and Politically) Maximizing Agents Agents may differ according to an individual characteristic α i Economic Agent: Maximize Utility function w.r.t. economic variable C i subject to a budget constraint H Vector : Economic policies, taken as given Vector p: data determined by the market A General Policy Problem
8
Economic Agent Problem Examples: Savings, Labor Supply, Purchase of Goods, Investments (given taxes, fiscal incentives and prices)
9
Political Problem Policy Maker: Set q taking into account p and constraint G If the constraint is binding → p = P(q) Political Agent: Maximize Indirect Utility function W (by voting, lobbying….) Individual preferences over the policies W(q; α i ) q* c U1U1 U2U2 U3U3 q
10
Political Agent Problem
11
How do we Aggregate Preferences? Arrow’s (1951) IMPOSSIBILITY THEOREM: Shows that there is NO DEMOCRATIC mechanism which allows individual preferences to be aggregated in a consistent way: A1. RATIONALITY (complete & transitive) A2. UNRESTRICTED DOMAIN A3. WEAK PARETO OPTIMALITY A4. INDEPENDENCE (from irrelevant alternatives) Way out: Drop A2 and restrict individual preferences
12
Political Mechanisms 1.Motivation of politicians OPPORTUNISTIC PARTISAN 2.Timing of Policy Choice PRE-ELECTION politics (Commitment) POST-ELECTION politics (No Commitment) MAJORITY RULE VOTING: A1. DIRECT DEMOCRACY A2. SINCERE VOTING A3. OPEN AGENDA
13
One-Dimensional Policy DEF. 1: A CONDORCET WINNER is a policy q* that beats any other feasible policy in a pairwise voting. DEF. 2: Policy preferences of voter i are SINGLE PEAKED if the following statement is true:
14
Single Peakedness Preferences of agents 6 and 7 are not single-peaked.
15
Voting decision depends only on the single issue at stake Given the voter’s preferences, candidates position themselves on this issue so that they can win the election. Single Issue – Two Candidates Election
16
Voter’s Preferences on Two Issues with (Budget) Constrained Political Decision w1w1 w2w2 O*O*
17
Median Voter’s Theorem If all voters have single-peaked policy preferences over a given ordering of policy alternatives, a Condorcet winner always exists and coincide with the median ranked bliss point (q m ) Corollary: q m is the unique equilibrium policy (stable point) under pure majority rule (A1-A3) Idea: Nash equilibrium of the candidate game. A couple of strategies such that –given that the other candidate plays the Nash equilibrium strategy- the candidate chooses the optimal strategy. There is no profitable deviation for either candidate.
18
A slight detour: Game Theory A game is the mathematical representation of a «situation» where agents interact, i.e. the utility each of them obtains depends on her action and the actions chosen by the other players. Elements of a game: 1)Players 2)Strategies (the set of feasible actions) 3)Payoffs (for each player, for each possible combination of strategies) Typical assumptions: rationality and common knowledge of rationality (CKR) Timing of the game: simultaneous-move vs. sequential-move game
19
A slight detour: Game Theory (cont.)
20
Intuition: in a Nash eqbm each player plays an optimal strategy, conditional on the other player(s) playing the strategy dictated by the Nash equilibrium itself. It’s easy to check whether a «candidate» Nash Equilibrium is really so: you have to check that for each player there is no profitable deviation, i.e. a different strategy that would deliver to that player a utility that it is higher than the one she obtains when players play the strategies dictated by that candidate Nash equilibrium. Message: Easy to kill a candidate Nash equilibrium, typically easier than to find a true one. A slight detour: Game Theory (cont.)
21
Sketch of Proof (two candidates committing on platforms) U q A B C qAqA q* qCqC q’q’’ Median voter: B Condorcet winner: q* Hp.: each candidate receives a payoff of one if she wins the election, zero otherwise. Both candidates offering q* as policy proposal is the Nash Equilibrium of the voting game. Check that there is a profitable deviation for any other couple of proposals. But not for this one!
22
DEF. 3: The preferences of the set of voters V satisfy the SINGLE-CROSSING PROPERTY when the following statement is true: If the preferences of voters in V satisfy the single-crossing property, a Condorcet winner always exists and coincides with the bliss point of the voter with the median value of α i Theorem
23
Multidimensional Policy – Unidimensional Conflict DEF. 4: Voters in the set V have INTERMEDIATE PREFERENCES if their indirect utility function W(q,α i ) can be written as: Theorem If voters in V have intermediate preferences, a Condorcet winner exists and is given by q(α i )
24
Multidimensional Policy SPATIAL VOTING MODELS: Representation of preferences as some measure of the distance from the bliss point When does an equilibrium exists? MEDIAN in all directions, i.e. a composite-policy such that the voters are splitted in two even parts according to any policy dimension
25
Condorcet Cycles: Spatial Representation of Preferences y x 1 2 3 A C B 123 A to BBAB B to CBCC C to AAAB B wins against A C wins against B A wins against C
26
Voting Models 1. LEGISLATIVE MODELS: (Post Electoral Politics: decision making rules, agenda setting, allocation of policy jurisdiction, etc.) STRUCTURE INDUCED EQUILIBRIUM (Shepsle 1979) AGENDA SETTER (Baron-Ferejhon 1989)
27
2.INTEREST GROUP MODELS / LOBBYING: (Contributions, informational asymmetries, etc.) Becker (1983, 1985) Grossman-Helpman (1994) 3.ELECTORAL MODELS: (Electoral competition between two candidates, distribution of voters preferences, etc.) PROBABILISTIC VOTING (Dixit-Londregan 1996) CITIZEN CANDIDATE (Besley-Coate 1997; Osborne-Slivinki 1996)
28
Issue by Issue Voting (SIE) y x 1 2 3 x* y* E x 1 (y) 1.Vote reaction function for each voter i: x i (y) and y i (x) 2.Find the median voter on each dimension 3.Equilibrium is the cross point among the median voters’ reaction function x 2 (y)x 3 (y) y 2 (x) y 1 (x) y 3 (x)
Similar presentations
© 2025 SlidePlayer.com. Inc.
All rights reserved.