Presentation is loading. Please wait.

Presentation is loading. Please wait.

Chapter 3 The Real Numbers.

Similar presentations


Presentation on theme: "Chapter 3 The Real Numbers."— Presentation transcript:

1 Chapter 3 The Real Numbers

2 The Completeness Axiom
Section 3.3 The Completeness Axiom

3 Before presenting this axiom, let’s look at why it’s needed.
There is one additional axiom that distinguishes from It is called the completeness axiom. Before presenting this axiom, let’s look at why it’s needed. When we graph the function f (x) = x2 – 2, it appears to cross the horizontal axis at a point between 1 and 2. But does it really? How can we be sure that there is a “number” x on the axis such that x2 – 2 = 0? – 2 2 x 1 f (x) 3 – 1 f (x) = x2 – 2 It turns out that if the x-axis consists only of rational numbers, then no such number exists. That is, there is no rational number whose square is 2. In fact, we can easily prove the more general result that is irrational (not rational) for any prime number p. Recall that an integer p > 1 is prime iff its only divisors are 1 and p.

4 Theorem 3.3.1 Let p be a prime number. Then is not a rational number.
Proof: We suppose that is rational and obtain a contradiction. If is rational, then we can write = m / n, where m and n are integers with no common factors other than 1. Then p n2 = m2, so p must be a factor of m2. Now the prime factored forms for m and m2 have exactly the same prime factors, so p is a factor of m. That is, m = k p for some integer k. But then p n2 = k 2 p 2, so that n 2 = k 2 p. Thus p is a factor of n2, and as above we conclude that p is also a factor of n. Hence p is a factor of both m and n, contradicting the fact that they have no common factors other than 1.  In Section 2.4 we learned that there are uncountably many irrational numbers. Thus, if we were to restrict our analysis to rational numbers, our “number line” would have uncountably many “holes” in it. It is these holes in the number line that the completeness axiom fills.

5 Upper Bounds and Suprema
In order to state the completeness axiom for , we need some preliminary definitions. Upper Bounds and Suprema Definition 3.3.2 Let S be a subset of If there exists a real number m such that m  s for all s  S, then m is called an upper bound of S, and we say that S is bounded above. If m  s for all s  S, then m is a lower bound of S and S is bounded below. The set S is said to be bounded if it is bounded above and bounded below. If an upper bound m of S is a member of S, then m is called the maximum (or largest element) of S, and we write m = max S. Similarly, if a lower bound of S is a member of S, then it is called the minimum (or least element) of S, denoted by min S. While a set may have many upper and lower bounds, if it has a maximum or a minimum, then those values are unique (Exercise 6).

6 Example 3.3.3 (a) Let S = {2, 4, 6, 8}. min max 2 4 6 8 10 lower bounds upper bounds Then S is bounded above by 8, 9, 8.5, 2, and any other real number greater than or equal to 8. Since 8  S, we have max S = 8. Similarly, S has many lower bounds, including 2, which is the largest of the lower bounds and the minimum of S. It is easy to see that any finite set is bounded and always has a maximum and a minimum.

7 [ ( ] Example 3.3.3 (b) The interval [0, ) is not bounded above.
min no maximum [ – 2 2 4 6 8 no upper bounds lower bounds It is bounded below by any nonpositive number, and of these lower bounds, 0 is the largest. Since 0  [0, ), 0 is the minimum of [0, ). (c) The interval (0, 4] has a maximum of 4, and this is the smallest of the upper bounds. max no min ( ] 2 4 lower bounds upper bounds It is bounded below by any nonpositive number, and of these lower bounds, 0 is the largest. Since 0  (0,1], the set has no minimum.

8 Example 3.3.3 (d) The empty set  is bounded above by any m  . Note that the condition m  s for all s   is equivalent to the implication “if s  , then m  s.” This implication is true since the antecedent is false. Likewise,  is bounded below by any real m. Definition 3.3.5 Let S be a nonempty subset of If S is bounded above, then the least upper bound of S is called its supremum and is denoted by sup S. Thus m = sup S iff (a) m  s, for all s  S, That is, m is an upper bound of S. (b) if m < m, then there exists s  S such that s > m. Nothing smaller than m is an upper bound of S. If S is bounded below, then the greatest lower bound of S is called its infimum and is denoted by inf S.

9 Does T have a supremum? It depends on the context. If we think of T as a subset of the real numbers, then But is not a rational number. So T does not have a supremum in . When considering subsets of , it has been true that each set bounded above has had a least upper bound. This supremum may be a member of the set, as in the interval [0,1], but in both cases the supremum exists as a real number. or it may be outside the set, as in the interval [0,1), This fundamental difference between and is the basis for our final axiom of the real numbers, the completeness axiom: Every nonempty subset S of that is bounded above has a least upper bound. That is, sup S exists and is a real number. It follows readily from this that every nonempty subset S of that is bounded below has a greatest lower bound. So, inf S exists and is a real number.

10 Theorem 3.3.7 Given nonempty subsets A and B of , let C denote the set C = {x + y : x  A and y  B}. If A and B have suprema, then C has a supremum and sup C = sup A + sup B. Proof: Let sup A = a and sup B = b. If z  C, then z  x + y for some x  A and y  B. Thus z  x + y  a + b, so a + b is an upper bound of C. By the completeness axiom, C has a least upper bound, say sup C  c. Since c is the least upper bound of C, we have c  a + b. We must show that c  a + b. Since a  sup A, a –  is not an upper bound of A, and there must exist x  A such that x  a –  . To see that a + b  c, choose any  > 0. Similarly, since b = sup B, there exists y  B such that y  b –  . Combining these inequalities, we have x + y  a + b – 2 . That is, a + b < c + 2 for every   0. But, x + y  C and c  sup C, so c  a + b – 2 . Finally, since c  a + b and c  a + b, we conclude that c   a + b.  Thus by Theorem 3.2.8, a + b  c. A B A + B x y x + y a a –  b b –  c a + b – 2

11 Theorem 3.3.8 Suppose that D is a nonempty set and that f : D   and g : D   . If for every x, y  D, f (x)  g ( y), then f (D) is bounded above and g (D) is bounded below. Furthermore, sup f (D)  inf g (D). Thus f (D) is bounded above by g (z). Proof: Given any z  D, we have f (x)  g (z), for all x  D. It follows that the least upper bound of f (D) is no larger than g (z). That is, sup f (D)  g (z). Since this last inequality holds for all z  D, g (D) is bounded below by sup f (D). Thus the greatest lower bound of g (D) is no smaller than sup f (D). That is, inf g (D)  sup f (D).  D z f g f (D) sup f (D) inf g(D) g (D) g(z) least upper bound of f (D) greatest lower bound of g(D) upper bound of f (D) lower bound of g(D)

12 The Archimedean Property of
Theorem 3.3.9 The Archimedean Property of The set of natural numbers is unbounded above in . Proof: If were bounded above, then by the completeness axiom it would have a least upper bound, say sup = m. Since m is a least upper bound, m – 1 is not an upper bound of . Thus there exists an n in such that n > m – 1. and since n + 1  , this contradicts m being an upper bound of .  But then n + 1 > m, The Archimedean Property is widely used in analysis and there are several equivalent forms (which are also sometimes referred to as the Archimedean Property). We state them and establish their equivalence in the following theorem.

13 Theorem Each of the following is equivalent to the Archimedean property. (a) For each z  , there exists an n  such that n > z. (b) For each x > 0 and for each y  , there exists an n  such that nx > y. (c) For each x > 0, there exists an n  such that 0 < 1/n < x. Proof: We shall prove that Theorem  (a)  (b)  (c)  Theorem 3.3.9, thereby establishing their equivalence. Theorem  (a) If (a) were not true, then for some z0  we would have n  z0 for all n  . But then z0 would be an upper bound of , contradicting Theorem Thus the Archimedean property implies (a). (a)  (b) Given x  0 and y  , let z = y /x. Then there exists n  such that n > y/x, so that n x > y.

14 Theorem Each of the following is equivalent to the Archimedean property. (a) For each z  , there exists an n  such that n > z. (b) For each x > 0 and for each y  , there exists an n  such that nx > y. (c) For each x > 0, there exists an n  such that 0 < 1/n < x. Proof: We shall prove that Theorem  (a)  (b)  (c)  Theorem 3.3.9, thereby establishing their equivalence. (b)  (c) Given x  0, take y = 1 in part (b). Then n x > 1, so that 1/n < x. Since n  , n > 0 and also 1/n > 0. (c)  Theorem 3.3.9 Suppose that were bounded above by some real number, say m. That is, n  m for all n  . Let k = m + 1. Then n  k – 1  k and 1/n > 1/k for all n. This contradicts (c) with x = 1/k . Thus (c) implies the Archimedean property. 

15 In Theorem 3.3.1 we showed that is not rational when p is prime.
We are now in a position to prove there is a positive real number whose square is p, thus illustrating that we actually have filled in the “holes” in . Theorem Let p be a prime number. Then there exists a positive real number x such that x2 = p. Proof: Let S = {r  : r > 0 and r2 < p}. Since p > 1, 1  S and S is nonempty. Thus S is bounded above by p, and by the completeness axiom, sup S exists as a real number. Furthermore, if r  S, then r2 < p < p2, so r < p. Let x = sup S. It is clear that x > 0, and we claim that x2 = p. To prove this, we shall show that neither x2 < p nor x2 > p is consistent with our choice of x.

16 Theorem Let p be a prime number. Then there exists a positive real number x such that x2 = p. Proof: Let S = {r  : r > 0 and r2 < p} and x = sup S. Suppose that x2  p. x2 p We want to find something positive, say 1/n, that we can add on to x and still have its square be less than p. This will contradict x as an upper bound of S. We have ( p – x2)/(2x + 1) > 0, so that Theorem (c) implies the existence of some n  such that The text shows where this estimate comes from. Then It follows that x + 1/n  S, which contradicts our choice of x as an upper bound of S.

17 Theorem Let p be a prime number. Then there exists a positive real number x such that x2 = p. Proof: Let S = {r  : r > 0 and r2 < p} and x = sup S. Now suppose that x2  p. x2 p We want to find something positive, say 1/m, that we can subtract from x and still have its square be greater than p. This will contradict x as the least upper bound of S. We have (x2 –  p)/(2x) > 0, so there exists an m  such that Then This implies that x – 1/m > r, for all r  S, so x – 1/m is an upper bound of S. Since x – 1/m < x, this contradicts our choice of x as the least upper bound of S. Finally, since neither x2 < p nor x2 > p is a possibility, we conclude by the trichotomy law that in fact x2 = p. 

18 Theorem 3.3.13 The density of in
If x and y are real numbers with x < y, then there exists a rational number r such that x < r < y. Proof: We begin by supposing that x > 0. Using the Archimedean property (a), there exists an n  such that n > 1/( y – x). Since n x > 0, it is not difficult to show (Exercise 9) that there exists m  such that m – 1  n x < m. That is, n x + 1 < n y. But then m  n x + 1 < n y, so that n x < m < n y. It follows that the rational number r = m/n satisfies x < r < y. Then apply the argument above to the positive numbers x + k and y + k. Finally, if x  0, choose an integer k such that k > | x |. If q is a rational satisfying x + k < q < y + k, then the rational r = q – k satisfies x < r < y.  It follows easily from this that the irrational numbers are also dense in the real numbers (Theorem ). That is, if x and y are real numbers with x < y, then there exists an irrational number w such that x < w < y.


Download ppt "Chapter 3 The Real Numbers."

Similar presentations


Ads by Google