Download presentation
Presentation is loading. Please wait.
Published byKristin Sullivan Modified over 6 years ago
1
Expected Value, Expected Utility & the Allais and Ellsberg Paradoxes
Psychology 466: Judgment & Decision Making Instructor: John Miyamoto 11/06/2017: Lecture 07-1 Note: This Powerpoint presentation may contain macros that I wrote to help me create the slides. The macros aren’t needed to view the slides. You can disable or delete the macros without any change to the presentation.
2
Lecture probably ends here
Outline Expected Value and Expected Utility: What's the Difference? Expected utility theory Subjective expected utility theory (Bayesian models) Allais Paradox Common consequence principle (a.k.a. Savage’s independence axiom or the sure-thing principle) Anticipated regret Nonlinear probability weighting Ellsberg Paradox Lecture probably ends here Psych 466, Miyamoto, Aut '17 What Is the Expected Value of a Gamble?
3
Expected Value of a Gamble
Same idea but with a different notation for the gamble. Psych 466, Miyamoto, Aut '17 Expected Value of a Gamble (Cont.): More General Version
4
Expected Value of a Gamble (cont.)
Psych 466, Miyamoto, Aut '17 Would It Be Rational to be an Expected Value Maximizer?
5
Would It Be Rational to be an Expected Value Maximizer?
Expected Value Maximizer: Someone who always prefers the gamble that has the higher expected value. Discussions pro and con during the 18th and 19th century. Rich gamblers wanting to know, which is the better bet? Psych 466, Miyamoto, Aut '17 Are You an Expected Value Maximizer? Concrete Example
6
Are You an Expected Value Maximizer
I offer you a choice: EV( Option 1 ) > EV( Option 2 ) An expected value maximizer would choose Option 1. Do you prefer Option 1 to Option 2? Higher Risk Lower Risk See ‘e:\p466\nts\stpetersburg.paradox.docm’ for the equations that are used as graphics on this slide. Continuation of this Example Psych 466, Miyamoto, Aut '17
7
Are You an Expected Value Maximizer? (Cont.)
Option 1: 50% chance you win $10, % chance you lose $10,000 Option 2: 50% chance you win $ % chance you lose $10 Intuitive argument in favor of Option 2: The pleasure of winning +$10,010 is smaller in absolute magnitude than the pain of losing -$10,000. The worst that can happen with Option 2 is the pain of losing -$10. What really matters is the subjective value of these outcomes, $10,010, +$2, -$10, -$10, and not the objective monetary amounts. St. Petersburg Paradox - Introduction Psych 466, Miyamoto, Aut '17
8
St. Petersburg Paradox Illustration of the St. Petersburg Game
Psych 466, Miyamoto, Aut '17
9
St. Petersburg Paradox (cont.)
Psych 466, Miyamoto, Aut '17 Same Slide Without any Rectangular Screens
10
St. Petersburg Paradox (cont.)
Psych 466, Miyamoto, Aut '17 Expected Value of the St. Petersburg Game
11
Expected Value of St. Petersburg Game is Infinite!
Psych 466, Miyamoto, Aut '17
12
Expected Value of St. Petersburg Game is Infinite!
Does It Feel Right that the St. Petersburg Game is Infinitely Valuable? Psych 466, Miyamoto, Aut '17
13
Expected Value of St. Petersburg Game is Infinite!
Would you give your total wealth for the opportunity to play the St. Petersburg game? If you are an expected value maximizer, you should be eager to pay everything you own for the opportunity to play the St. Petersburg Game just once. Bernoulli's Utility Hypothesis Psych 466, Miyamoto, Aut '17
14
Expected Value & Expected Utility
Nobody is an expected value maximizer. Nobody always prefers the gamble with the higher expected value. Daniel Bernoulli (1738): People maximize the expected utility of their choices; not the expected value of their choices. Utility of X = subjective value of possessing or experiencing X (but Bernoulli did not know how to measure utility) Next 200 years: Economic theory attempts to get rid of the concept of subjective value. Psych 466, Miyamoto, Aut '17 Expected Utility Hypothesis: Simplified Mathematical Statement
15
Expected Utility Hypothesis (Simplified Version)
Let U(X) be the utility of X and let EU(G) be the expected utility of a gamble G. Expected Utility Hypothesis (simplified version): There exists a function U such that: (i) For every pair of gambles G1 and G2 , G1 preferred to G2 iff EU(G1) > EU(G2) (ii) If G = (X1, p; X2, 1-p) is any gamble, then EU(G) = pU(X1) + (1 - p)U(X2) The Expected Utility (EU) Hypothesis is the claim that a rational agent must satisfy (i) and (ii) with respect to every gamble G, G1 and G2 . Psych 466, Miyamoto, Aut '17 Example: Calculating the EU of Two Gambles
16
Example: Calculating the EU( Option 1 ) & EU( Option 2 )
I offer you a choice: Option 1: 50% chance you win $10, % chance you lose $10,000 Option 2: 50% chance you win $ % chance you lose $10 How to calculate the Expected Utility (EU) of each option? To calculate the EU of each option, we need to assign utilities to the outcomes. U($10,010) = +500 U(-$10,000) = -700 U(+$2) = +1.5 U(-$10) = -1.7 These are just hypothetical values that represent the relative subjective value of the dollar amounts. Psych 466, Miyamoto, Aut '17 Calculate the EU of Each Option
17
Example: Calculating the EU( Option 1 ) & EU( Option 2 )
I offer you a choice: Option 1: 50% chance you win $10, % chance you lose $10,000 Option 2: 50% chance you win $ % chance you lose $10 Calculate the Expected Utility of each option: EU( Option 1 ) = (½ ( ½ -700 ) = Utils EU( Option 2 ) = (½ 1.5) + ( ½ -1.7 ) = Utils Assume these are the utilities: U($10,010) = U(-$10,000) = -700 U($2) = +1.5 U(-$10) = -1.7 Psych 466, Miyamoto, Aut '17 Same Slide Without Red Boxes and Arrows
18
Example: Calculating the EU( Option 1 ) & EU( Option 2 )
I offer you a choice: Option 1: 50% chance you win $10, % chance you lose $10,000 Option 2: 50% chance you win $ % chance you lose $10 Calculate the Expected Utility of each option: EU( Option 1 ) = (½ 500) + ( ½ (-700) ) = Utils EU( Option 2 ) = (½ 1.5) + ( ½ -1.7 ) = Utils EU( Option 1 ) < EU( Option 2 ). If you are an EU maximizer, you will choose Option 2. Assume these are the utilities: U($10,010) = U(-$10,000) = -700 U($2) = +1.5 U(-$10) = -1.7 Psych 466, Miyamoto, Aut '17 Rationality Does NOT Demand that We Be Expected Value Maximizers
19
Rationality Does Not Demand that We Be Expected Value Maximizers
An insurance company is (approximately) an EV maximizer. An individual person is not an EV maximizer. Why? Suppose an insurance company sells 10,000 auto insurance policies for $500/year each. Insurance company knows that the expected value of each policy is -$420. An individual auto accident might cost $2,000 to $1,000,000, but they happen rarely. Is it rational to buy auto insurance? There are many examples where reasonable people are NOT EXPECTED VALUE MAXIMIZERS. Psych 466, Miyamoto, Aut '17 Birth of Expected Utility Theory
20
History of Expected Utility (EU) Theory (outline)
Daniel Bernoulli (1738) People maximize the expected utility of their choices; not the expected value of their choices. Expected utility provides an explanation for risk aversion, e.g., explains the St. Petersburg Paradox and the desire to buy insurance. Next 200 years: Economic theory attempts to get rid of the concept of subjective value. von Neumann & Morgenstern ( ) Publish mathematical foundations for EU theory. EU theory provides an explanation for risk aversion, e.g., explains the St. Petersburg Paradox and desire to buy insurance. Expected utility (EU) theory embraced as a foundations for economic theory. EU theory explains how a rational agent ought to decide among risky options. Some claim that it describes how people actually behave in economic decisions. Psych 466, Miyamoto, Aut '17 Reminder: What is the Expected Utility Hypothesis?
21
ReminderExpected Utility Hypothesis (Simplified Version)
The EU hypothesis asserts that a rational agent always satisfies (i) and (ii) with respect to every gamble G, G1 and G2 . (i) For every pair of gambles G1 and G2 , G1 preferred to G2 iff EU(G1) > EU(G2) (ii) If G = (X1, p; X2, 1-p) is any gamble, then EU(G) = pU(X1) + (1 - p)U(X2) If a person satisfies the EU hypothesis, (i) and (ii), then this person is said to be an expected utility maximizer, i.e., someone who always chooses the option with the maximum expected utility. Psych 466, Miyamoto, Aut '17 Preference Axioms - What Are They?
22
Preference Axioms – What Are They?
Preference Axioms for EU Theory: A set of assumptions about preference behavior which, if satisfied, imply that a decision maker is an EU maximizer. Transitivity is an example of a preference axiom. If you prefer A to B and you prefer B to C, then you must prefer A to C. E.g., I prefer coffee to tea. I prefer tea to a Coca Cola. Therefore I should prefer coffee to a Coca Cola. Sure-thing principle (common consequence assumption) is another example of a preference axiom. (To be explained later.) Preference Axioms Can Be Interpreted as a Normative Claim or a Descriptive Claim Psych 466, Miyamoto, Aut '17
23
Preference Axioms – What Are They?
Preference Axioms for EU Theory: A set of assumptions about preference behavior which, if satisfied, imply that a decision maker is an EU maximizer. Preference axioms can be construed as a NORMATIVE claim: This is how a rational agent OUGHT to behave. Preference axioms can be construed as a DESCRIPTIVE claim: This is how people ACTUALLY behave. Psych 466, Miyamoto, Aut '17 Allais Paradox
24
Allais Paradox Allais, M. (1953). Le comportement de l'homme rationnel devant le risque: Critique des postulats et axiomes de l'école Americaine. Econometrica, 21, Maurice Allais discovered that people systematically violate an assumption of EU theory. Allais Paradox = paradoxical pattern of typical choices in Allais-type choice problems. Allais discovered violations of the common consequence assumption of EU theory. Present the Choices for the Allais Paradox Psych 466, Miyamoto, Aut '17
25
Write Down Your Preferences for these Choices
Allais, M. (1953). Le comportement de l'homme rationnel devant le risque: Critique des postulats et axiomes de l'école Americaine. Econometrica, 21, Choice 1: Option A: Receive 1 million for sure. Option B: Receive 2.5 million, 10% chance Receive 1 million, 89% chance Receive 0, 1% chance Choice 2: Option A': Receive 1 million, 11% chance, otherwise $0. Option B': Receive 2.5 million, 10% chance, otherwise $0. Continuation of this Slide: Record Student Preferences Psych 466, Miyamoto, Aut '17
26
Class Results for the Allais Paradox Problem
Allais, M. (1953). Le comportement de l'homme rationnel devant le risque: Critique des postulats et axiomes de l'école Americaine. Econometrica, 21, Choice 1: Option A: Receive 1 million for sure. Option B: Receive 2.5 million, 10% chance Receive 1 million, 89% chance Receive 0, 1% chance Choice 2: Option A': Receive 1 million, 11% chance, otherwise $0. Option B': Receive 2.5 million, 10% chance, otherwise $0. (Write student responses on the board.) Typical choices: Choose A from Choice 1 and choose B' from Choice 2. typical preference typical preference Psych 466, Miyamoto, Aut '17 EU Analysis of Choice 1
27
Allais Paradox Violates EU Theory
Choice 1: Option A: Receive 1 million for sure. (); Option B: Receive 2.5 million, 10% chance, Receive 1 million, 89% chance, Receive 0 , % chance Choice 1: EU( Option A ) = (0.10)U( $1 mil ) + (0.89)U( $1 mil ) + (0.01)U( $1 mil ) EU( Option B ) = (0.10)U( $2.5 mil ) + (0.89)U( $1 mil ) + (0.01)U( $0 mil ) Psych 466, Miyamoto, Aut '17 EU Analysis of Choice 2
28
Allais Paradox Violates EU Theory
Choice 2: Option A': Receive 1 million, 11% chance, otherwise $ Option B': Receive 2.5 million, 10% chance, otherwise $0. () Choice 2: EU( Option A ) = (0.10)U( $1 mil ) + (0.89)U( $0 mil ) + (0.01)U( $1 mil ) EU( Option B ) = (0.10)U( $2.5 mil ) + (0.89)U( $0 mil ) + (0.01)U( $0 mil ) Psych 466, Miyamoto, Aut '17 Point Out that these Choices have a Common Consequence
29
Allais Paradox Violates EU Theory
Choice 1: Option A: Receive 1 million for sure. ; Option B: Receive 2.5 million, 10% chance, Receive 1 million, 89% chance, Receive 0 , % chance Choice 2: Option A': Receive 1 million, 11% chance, otherwise $ Option B': Receive 2.5 million, 10% chance, otherwise $0. To be consistent with EU Theory: Choose A in Choice 1 & A' in Choice 2 OR Choose B in Choice 1 & B' in Choice 2 Choice 1: EU( Option A ) = (0.10)U( $1 mil ) + (0.89)U( $1 mil ) + (0.01)U( $1 mil ) EU( Option B ) = (0.10)U( $2.5 mil ) + (0.89)U( $1 mil ) + (0.01)U( $0 mil ) Choice 2: EU( Option A’ ) = (0.10)U( $1 mil ) + (0.89)U( $0 mil ) + (0.01)U( $1 mil ) EU( Option B’ ) = (0.10)U( $2.5 mil ) + (0.89)U( $0 mil ) + (0.01)U( $0 mil ) Psych 466, Miyamoto, Aut '17 Same Slide with Both Rectangles Displayed
30
Allais Paradox Violates EU Theory
Choice 1: Option A: Receive 1 million for sure. (); Option B: Receive 2.5 million, 10% chance, Receive 1 million, 89% chance, Receive 0 , % chance Choice 2: Option A': Receive 1 million, 11% chance, otherwise $ Option B': Receive 2.5 million, 10% chance, otherwise $0. () Choice 1: EU( Option A ) = (0.10)U( $1 mil ) + (0.89)U( $1 mil ) + (0.01)U( $1 mil ) EU( Option B ) = (0.10)U( $2.5 mil ) + (0.89)U( $1 mil ) + (0.01)U( $0 mil ) Choice 2: EU( Option A’ ) = (0.10)U( $1 mil ) + (0.89)U( $0 mil ) + (0.01)U( $1 mil ) EU( Option B’ ) = (0.10)U( $2.5 mil ) + (0.89)U( $0 mil ) + (0.01)U( $0 mil ) Psych 466, Miyamoto, Aut '17 Tabular Representation of the Choices in the Allais Paradox
31
Tabular Representation of the Allais Choices
Choice 1: Option A: Receive 1 million for sure. (); Option B: Receive 2.5 million, 10% chance, Receive 1 million, 89% chance, Receive 0 , 1% chance Choice 2: Option A': Receive 1 million, 11% chance, otherwise $ Option B': Receive 2.5 million, 10% chance, otherwise $0. () Chance of Outcome 10% 89% 1% Choice 1 Option A $1 Option B $2.5 $0 Choice 2 Option A' Option B' Same Slide without the Opaque Grey Rectangles Psych 466, Miyamoto, Aut '17
32
Allais Paradox Is Based on Common Consequences
Choice 1: Option A: Receive 1 million for sure. (); Option B: Receive 2.5 million, 10% chance, Receive 1 million, 89% chance, Receive 0 , 1% chance Choice 2: Option A': Receive 1 million, 11% chance, otherwise $ Option B': Receive 2.5 million, 10% chance, otherwise $0. () Chance of Outcome 10% 89% 1% Choice 1 Option A $1 Option B $2.5 $0 Choice 2 Option A' Option B' Statement of the Common Consequence Principle Psych 466, Miyamoto, Aut '17
33
Common Consequences Principle (Other Names: Sure-Thing Principle, the Independence Axiom)
Common Consequence Principle: If two options have the same probability for a given consequence, then you should ignore this consequence when choosing between the options. Base your choice on the aspects of the options that differ. Chance of Outcome 10% 89% 1% Choice 1 Option A $1 Option B $2.5 $0 Choice 2 Option A' Option B' Typical Choice Typical Choice Psychological Explanations for the Allais Paradox Psych 466, Miyamoto, Aut '17
34
Why Do People's Preferences Display the Allais Paradox?
Choice 1: Option A: Receive 1 million for sure. Option B: Receive 2.5 million, 10% chance Receive 1 million, 89% chance Receive 0 , 1% chance Choice 2: Option A': Receive 1 million, 11% chance, otherwise $0. Option B': Receive 2.5 million, 10% chance, otherwise $ Class: Propose psychological explanations for the Allais Paradox. Anticipated Regret – Explanation for Allais Paradox Psych 466, Miyamoto, Aut '17
35
Explaining the Allais Paradox in terms of Anticipated Regret
Choice 1: Option A: Receive 1 million for sure. Option B: Receive 2.5 million, 10% chance Receive 1 million, 89% chance Receive 0 , 1% chance Choice 2: Option A': Receive 1 million, 11% chance, otherwise $0. Option B': Receive 2.5 million, 10% chance, otherwise $ In Choice 1, if you choose option B and get $0, you will feel intense regret. Choosing option A avoids the possibility of regret. In Choice 2, if you choose option B' and get $0, you will not feel regret regardless of how the gamble turns out because you could have gotten $0 with option A' as well. Emotions Triggered by Decision Outcomes Psych 466, Miyamoto, Aut '17
36
Emotions Triggered by Decision Outcomes
Psych 466,, Miyamoto, Aut '17 Same Slide with Upper Left Quadrant Displayed
37
Emotions Triggered by Decision Outcomes
Disappointment is experienced when you hope for a good outcome but you get a mediocre or bad outcome. Psych 466,, Miyamoto, Aut '17 Same Slide with Upper Right Quadrant Displayed
38
Emotions Triggered by Decision Outcomes
Relief is experienced when you fear a bad outcome but you get a neutral or good outcome. Psych 466,, Miyamoto, Aut '17 Same Slide with Lower Left Quadrant Displayed
39
Emotions Triggered by Decision Outcomes
Regret is experienced when you choose Action A instead of Action B, but once you experience the outcome, you realize that you would have been much better off if you had chosen B. Psych 466,, Miyamoto, Aut '17 Same Slide with Lower Right Quadrant Displayed
40
Emotions Triggered by Decision Outcomes
Self-congratulation is experienced when you choose Action A instead of Action B, and once you experience the outcome, you realize that you would have been much worse off if you had chosen B. Psych 466,, Miyamoto, Aut '17 Same Slide with All Quadrants Displayed
41
Emotions Triggered by Decision Outcomes
Allais Paradox & Nonlinear Perception of Probability Psych 466,, Miyamoto, Aut '17 #
42
Why Do People Have Allais-Type Preferences?
Chance of Outcome 10% 89% 1% Choice 1 Option A $1 Option B $2.5 $0 Choice 2 Option A' Option B' potential regret no potential regret Hypothesis: Choices 1 and 2 differ in terms of anticipated regret. Regret – comparison between what you have experienced and what you would have experienced if you made a different choice. Anticipated Regret – anticipating that a choice will create the possibility of regret. Clean Version of This Slide Psych 466, Miyamoto, Aut '17
43
Why Do People Have Allais-Type Preferences?
Chance of Outcome 10% 89% 1% Choice 1 Option A $1 Option B $2.5 $0 Choice 2 Option A' Option B' potential regret no potential regret Hypothesis: Choices 1 and 2 differ in terms of anticipated regret. Regret – comparison between what you have experienced and what you would have experienced if you made a different choice. Anticipated Regret – anticipating that a choice will create the possibility of regret. Explaining the Allais Paradox in terms of Nonlinear Probability Weighting Psych 466, Miyamoto, Aut '17
44
Explaining the Allais Paradox in terms of Nonlinear Perception of Probability
Choice 1: Option A: Receive 1 million for sure, 0% chance of receiving 0 dollars. Option B: Receive 2.5 million, % chance Receive 1 million, % chance Receive 0 , % chance Choice 2: Option A': Receive 1 million, 11% chance, Receive $ % chance Option B': Receive 2.5 million, 10% chance, Receive $0, % chance of $ In choice 1-A, the chance of $0 is 0%; in choice 1-B, it is 1%. In choice 2-A', the chance of $0 is 89%; in choice 2-B', it is 90%. Psychologically, the difference between a 0% and 1% chance of $0 is greater than the difference between an 89% and 90% chance of $0. Ellsberg Paradox Psych 466, Miyamoto, Aut '17
45
Time Permitting: Discuss the Ellsberg Paradox
Who is Daniel Ellsberg? * Time magazine cover: July 5, Article: "The [Vietnam] War Exposés: Battle Over The Right to Know." * Book cover: "Most Dangerous: Daniel Ellsberg and the Secret History of the Vietnam War," by Steve Sheinkin, 2015. * Daniel Ellsberg, outside a federal courthouse in 1971, faced 12 felony counts as a result of his leak of the Pentagon Papers; the charges were dismissed in Credit Donal F. Holway/The New York Times. From June 7, 2011 article in the New York Times. * Ellsberg being arrested at 3/20/2011 protest over treatment of U.S. military prisoner, Bradley (now, Chelsea) Manning. Presentation of the Choices for the Ellsberg Paradox Psych 466, Miyamoto, Aut '17
46
Tuesday, 7 November, 2017: The Lecture Ended Here
Psych 466, Miyamoto, Aut '17
47
Ellsberg Paradox Ellsberg, D. (1961). Risk, ambiguity, and the Savage axioms. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 75, We are going to draw a ball from an urn. The urn contains 30 red balls, and 60 balls that are either blue or yellow, but you do not know the relative proportion of blue and yellow balls. Payoffs are based on the following payoff matrix. Number of balls 30 balls 60 balls Color Red Blue Yellow Choice 1 Option A: Bet on red $1000 $0 $0 Option B: Bet on blue $0 $1000 $0 Choice 2 Option A': Bet on red or yellow $1000 $0 $1000 Option B': Bet on blue or yellow $0 $1000 $1000 Repeat this Slide w-o Rectangles Psych 466, Miyamoto, Aut '17
48
Ellsberg Paradox Get Class Responses
Ellsberg, D. (1961). Risk, ambiguity, and the Savage axioms. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 75, We are going to draw a ball from an urn. The urn contains 30 red balls, and 60 balls that are either blue or yellow, but you do not know the relative proportion of blue and yellow balls. Payoffs are based on the following payoff matrix. Number of balls 30 balls 60 balls Color Red Blue Yellow Choice 1 Option A: Bet on red $1000 $0 $0 Option B: Bet on blue $0 $1000 $0 Choice 2 Option A': Bet on red or yellow $1000 $0 $1000 Option B': Bet on blue or yellow $0 $1000 $1000 Typical choices: Choose A from Choice 1 and choose B' from Choice 2. Get Class Responses Ellsberg Paradox and the Common Consequence Principle Psych 466, Miyamoto, Aut '17
49
Ellsberg Paradox & the Common Consequence Principle (Other Names: Sure-Thing Principle, Savage’s Independence Axiom) Common Consequence Principle: If two options have the same consequence given some outcome, you should ignore this common consequence. You should base your choice on the aspects of the options that differ. Number of Balls (60 X 0) 30 Red X Blue 60 - X Yellow Choice 1 Option A $1000 $0 Option B Choice 2 Option A' Option B' Psych 466, Miyamoto, Aut '17 Allais Paradox Violates the Common Consequence Principle
50
Ellsberg Paradox (cont.)
Common consequence principle says: you should prefer A to B and A’ to B’ OR you should prefer B to A and B’ to A’. Does this feel right? If not, why not? Number of Balls (60 X 0) 30 Red X Blue 60 - X Yellow Choice 1 Option A $1000 $0 Option B Choice 2 Option A' Option B' Psych 466, Miyamoto, Aut '17 Why Do the Allais & Ellsberg Paradoxes Occur?
51
Ellsberg Paradox & Ambiguous Probabilities
Common consequence principle says: you should prefer A to B and A’ to B’ OR you should prefer B to A and B’ to A’. Number of balls 30 balls 60 balls Color Red Blue Yellow Choice 1 Option A: Bet on red $1000 $0 $0 Option B: Bet on blue $0 $1000 $0 Choice 2 Option A': Bet on red or yellow $1000 $0 $1000 Option B': Bet on blue or yellow $0 $1000 $1000 Define concept of an ambiguous probability. unambiguous ambiguous ambiguous unambiguous Psych 466, Miyamoto, Aut '17 Summary re Allais and Ellsberg Paradoxes
52
Summary Allais Paradox & Ellsberg Paradox: Strong evidence that expected utility (EU) theory is not descriptively adequate. Hypotheses that explain the Allais Paradox: People’s decisions are influenced by anticipated regret. People’s perception of probability is nonlinear. Hypothesis that explain the Ellsberg Paradox: People tend to avoid ambiguous probabilities in the domain of gains. People tend to seek ambiguous probabilities in the domain of losses. Psych 466, Miyamoto, Aut '17 Where We Are Headed in the Next Set of Lectures - END
53
Where We Are Headed in the Next Set of Lectures
Prospect Theory Reflection effect Framing effects that result from reflection effects Mental accounting Psych 466, Miyamoto, Aut '17 END
Similar presentations
© 2025 SlidePlayer.com. Inc.
All rights reserved.