Download presentation
Presentation is loading. Please wait.
Published byLinda Manning Modified over 6 years ago
1
Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2013 Lecture 13
2
Logistics MT1 not yet graded, hope to return Wednesday
HW3 (contracts) online, due next Thurs (right before spring break) Second midterm April 8 Cumulative, through end of contract law More weight on more recent material, but will cover property law too
3
So far in contract law… Breach of contract Reliance
How liability for breach creates incentive for both, paradox of compensation Default rules, and penalty defaults
4
Discussion question Old urban legend: Serious question:
A man bought a box of extremely rare and expensive cigars, and insured them against loss or damage. After smoking them, he filed an insurance claim, saying they had been destroyed in 20 separate small fires. The insurance company refused to pay, the man sued and won. But as he was leaving the courtroom, he was arrested on 20 counts of arson. Serious question: If the intent of a contract is clear, but different from the literal meaning, which should be enforced?
5
Back to Default Rules Of course, Hadley and Baxendale could have made things much easier for the court – if they had just writing into the contract what should happen in case of delay they could have signed a contract saying, Hadley agrees to pay X for shipping, and Baxendale will refund Y for each day of delay beyond the first or they could have been even more specific Baxendale agrees to ship by train But then what happens if he learns the train schedule has changed, and shipping by boat becomes more practical?
6
From last week Default rules – rules that apply in circumstances not addressed in the contract Cooter and Ulen: impute rule most parties would have wanted, which is efficient rule, and apply that Ayres and Gertner: not necessarily Use “bad” default rule to create incentive to disclose information Hadley v Baxendale: Baxendale is efficient bearer of risk; but default rule limiting liability to foreseeable harm gives Hadley incentive to reveal how urgent the shipment is
7
Penalty defaults: other examples
Real estate brokers and “earnest money” Broker knows more about real estate law Default rule that seller keeps earnest money encourages broker to bring it up if it’s efficient to change this Consider a real estate broker who is handling the sale of a house by a private seller to a private buyer When a buyer’s offer is accepted, he puts down a deposit, called “earnest money,” to show that he is serious If he then backs out of the deal, he doesn’t get this earnest money back The question remains, though, how should the earnest money be divided between the seller and the broker? Both the broker and the seller are inconvenienced by the breach; it’s not really clear who is the efficient bearer of this risk However, what is clear is that the broker probably knows more about real estate law than the seller The broker is a professional, who does this type of transaction for a living The seller might be selling a house for the first time. If the default rule allowed the broker to keep the earnest money, the broker has no reason to bring this up when negotiating a contract with the seller But the seller might not know to bring this up; the seller might have no idea about earnest money, and not realize that this was another point that could be negotiated with the broker. On the other hand, if the default rule gave the earnest money to the seller, the broker would have a clear incentive to raise this with the seller And so they could negotiate whatever was the efficient allocation of the earnest money. Thus, whether or not it’s efficient, a default rule favoring the less-informed party once again gives an incentive to disclose information, which may be desireable.
8
Penalty defaults: other examples
Real estate brokers and “earnest money” Broker knows more about real estate law Default rule that seller keeps earnest money encourages broker to bring it up if it’s efficient to change this Courts will impute missing price of a good, but not quantity Forces parties to explicitly contract on quantity, rather than leave it for court to decide Ayres and Gertner give another nice example of penalty defaults used for a different purpose When a contract does not specify a price for a good, courts will tend to impute whatever the market price was at the time of the transaction That is, they will enforce the contract, and just impose the market price However, when a contract does not specify a quantity, courts will refuse to enforce the contract This means the default rule for price is the market price, but the default rule for quantity is 0 A quantity of 0 cannot possibly be what the parties would have wanted Nobody would go through the hassle of signing a contract in order to transact no goods So what is the reason for this default rule? Ayres and Gertner argue it is a penalty default, to force the parties to decide on a quantity Why should the parties be forced to decide on a quantity and not a price? Because it’s easier (cheaper) for the court to fill in the price than the quantity The rule for figuring out the price the parties would have agreed to is easy – the court can usually ascertain the market price of a given good on a given date However, if the court had to impute the quantity the parties would have wanted, this is much more difficult The court would have to figure out the marginal value of an incremental unit of the good to each side to figure out the efficient amount to transact Thus, shifting the burden of calculating the right quantity from the parties in the contract to the courts is inefficient So the default rule forces the parties to decide on the quantity themselves.
9
When to use penalty defaults?
Look at why the parties left a gap in contract Because of transaction costs use efficient rule For strategic reasons penalty default may be more efficient Similar logic in a Supreme Court dissent by Justice Scalia Congress passed a RICO law without statute of limitations Majority decided on 4 years – what they thought legislature would have chosen Scalia proposed no statute of limitations; “unmoved by the fear that this… might prove repugnant to the genius of our law…” “Indeed, it might even prompt Congress to enact a limitations period that it believes appropriate, a judgment far more within its competence than ours.” Ayres and Gertner do not argue penalty defaults should always be used, only that they are appropriate in certain circumstances They argue that we need to look at why the parties left a particular gap When gaps are left due to transaction costs of filling them, efficient defaults make sense But when gaps are left strategically – by a well-informed party who chooses not to contract around an inefficient default in order to get “a bigger share of a smaller pie” – penalty defaults may be more efficient. In the conclusion to their paper, Ayres and Gertner cite a similar point from a dissent by Supreme Court Justice Scalia The legislature had passed a RICO (racketeering/corruption) statute and had not specified a statute of limitations The Court was therefore being asked to decide on the statute of limitations The majority set the statute of limitations at 4 years, figuring that’s what the legislature most likely would have chosen had they remembered to specify it Scalia proposed no statute of limitations He was “unmoved by the fear that this… might prove repugnant to the genius of our law” Instead, he pointed out, “indeed, it might even prompt Congress to enact a limitations period that it believes appropriate, a judgment far more within its competence than ours.” So his view: rather than do what Congress would have wanted, do something they would not have wanted, to force them to do it themselves next time Exactly the same idea as a penalty default for a contract It’s a pretty cool article – take a look if you’re interested.
10
When should a contract not be enforced?
11
When should voluntary trade not be allowed?
Going back to property law… Coase Theorem: to get efficient outcomes, we should let people trade whenever they want to But also saw some exceptions – some trades that aren’t, and shouldn’t, be allowed Selling enriched uranium to a terrorist Similarly with contract law… First day: to get efficient outcomes, enforce any contract both parties wanted enforced But next, we’ll see exceptions – contracts which shouldn’t be enforced, due to externalities or market failures/transaction costs
12
Example of an unenforceable contract: a contract which breaks the law
Obvious: contract to buy a kilo of cocaine is unenforceable One example of an immutable rule: a contract to do something illegal is not enforceable In some cases, this seems really obvious. I give you $25,000 in exchange for a promise to give me a kilo of cocaine. You take my money, give me nothing; I have no recourse through contract law. But there are also less obvious situations, where a contract to do something perfectly legal on its face, is not enforceable, because the actual purpose of the contract was to circumvent the law The legal doctrine here is derogation of public policy
13
Example of an unenforceable contract: a contract which breaks the law
Obvious: contract to buy a kilo of cocaine is unenforceable Less obvious: otherwise-legal contract whose real purpose is to circumvent a law Legal doctrine: derogation of public policy Derogate, verb. detract from; curtail application of (a law) Applies to contracts which could only be performed by breaking law… …but also to “innocent” contracts whose purpose is to get around a law or regulation One example of an immutable rule: a contract to do something illegal is not enforceable In some cases, this seems really obvious. I give you $25,000 in exchange for a promise to give me a kilo of cocaine. You take my money, give me nothing; I have no recourse through contract law. But there are also less obvious situations, where a contract to do something perfectly legal on its face, is not enforceable, because the actual purpose of the contract was to circumvent the law The legal doctrine here is derogation of public policy
14
Derogation of public policy – example
Labor unions required by law to negotiate “in good faith” Recent NBA labor troubles Old CBA: 57% of “basketball-related income” went to player salaries Owners were offering less than 50%, players demanding 53%... Imagine the following contract: “For the next 50 years, if the NBAPA accepts a CBA paying less than 55% of BRI in player salaries, then we also agree that all non-retired players will work for you as coal miners every offseason at federal minimum wage.” Purpose is purely to “bind hands” in negotiations with ownership Contract would not be enforced Collective bargaining agreement between players and team owners expired; owners have locked out the players (like an owner-initiated strike) until new agreement is reached Negotiations are happening at the league offices in New York Imagine during one of the off-days from negotiations, Derek Fisher, the president of the players union, drives down to Philadelphia, visits the owner of a coal mining company, and signs the following contract There’s nothing illegal about a bunch of NBA players working as coal miners during the offseason However, the purpose of this contract isn’t to actually do that – it’s purely to change the union’s bargaining position in its negotiations with the league Once this contract is signed, Fisher can go back to the NBA offices in New York and say, “I don’t care what you say, there’s no way I can accept less than 55%” But this would violate the union’s obligation to bargain in good faith, and so this type of contract would not be enforced.
15
Derogation of public policy
In general: a contract is not enforceable if it cannot be performed without breaking the law Exception: if promisor knew (and promisee didn’t) I’m married, my girlfriend in California doesn’t know; I promise her I’ll marry her, she quits her job and moves to Madison My company agrees to supply a product that we can’t produce without violating a safety or environmental regulation Keeping either promise would require breaking the law… …but I’d still be liable for damages for breach Like in Ayres and Gertner: default rule penalizes better-informed party for withholding information
16
Default rules versus regulations
Talked earlier about default rules Default rules apply if no other rule is specified… …but can be contracted around Rules like “derogation of public policy” cannot be contracted around Parties to a contract can’t say, “even though this type of contract would normally not be valid, this one is” Rules which always apply: immutable rules, or mandatory rules, or regulations Fifth purpose of contract law is to minimize transaction costs of negotiating contracts by supplying efficient default rules and regulations.
17
Ways to get out of a contract
18
Formation Defenses and Performance Excuses
Claim that a valid contract does not exist (Example: no consideration) Performance excuse Yes, a valid contract was created But circumstances have changed and I should be allowed to not perform without penalty Most doctrines for invalidating a contract can be explained as either… Individuals agreeing to the contract were not rational, or Transaction cost or market failure Next, I want to discuss a number of ways to get out of a contract, that is, conditions under which a contract will not be enforced. These are typically divided into two categories: formation defenses and performance excuses A formation defense is a claim that a contract does not exist: that the requirements for a contract to be valid were not met (Under the bargain theory, for example, a formation defense might be that consideration was not given.) A performance excuse is a claim that, even though a valid contract was created, circumstances have changed and you should be excused from performing We said earlier that, under Coase, when individuals are rational and there are no transaction costs, voluntary negotiations should lead to efficiency So refusing to enforce voluntary contracts would not make sense Thus, most of the doctrines for invalidating a contract can be explained as a violation of one of these assumptions either the individuals agreeing to the contract were not rational or there was some sort of transaction cost or market failure
19
One formation defense: incompetence
Courts will not enforce contracts with people who can’t be presumed to be rational Children Legally insane Incompetence One party was “not competent to enter into the agreement” No “meeting of the minds” The first exception is that courts will generally not enforce contracts made by people who can’t be assumed to be rational. For example: children cannot sign binding contracts the legally insane cannot sign binding contracts For example: this article (about a month old) is about 7-year-old who was messing around on eBay and hit the “buy it now” button for a decommissioned Harrier fighter jet selling for 70,000 pounds, or a bit over $100,000. His father saw what he’d done and contacted the seller to apologize, and the seller, very reasonably, just re-listed the plane and sold it to another bidder But if the seller had tried to hold the son to the deal, he would have failed Contracts with children, and with the legally insane, can be invalidated under the doctrine of incompetence: one party to the contract was not competent to enter into a binding agreement In fact, the law does not automatically invalidate all contracts made with children or insane people It only invalidates contracts which were not in their best interests (Basically, the law creates an incentive not to cheat people who can’t take care of themselves.)
20
So… If courts won’t enforce a contract signed by someone who wasn’t competent… What if you signed a contract while drunk? You need to have been really, really, really drunk to get out of a contract (“Intoxicated to the extent of being unable to comprehend the nature and consequences of the instrument he executed”) Lucy v. Zehmer, Virginia Sup Ct 1954 The first time I taught this course, after I introduced the doctrine of incompetence, one of my students ed me an excellent question: what if you signed a contract while drunk? Can a drunk person sign a legally enforceable contract? or would the fact that he was drunk get him off the hook? We mentioned that the bargain theory required a “meeting of the minds” to agree to a contract It’s reasonable to question whether this could occur with someone who was drunk However, the general rule in the U.S. is this: You have to be really, really, really drunk for the contract not to count. OK, that’s not how it’s written in the case law The rule is, for a contract to be unenforceable, you need to have been “intoxicated to the extent of being unable to comprehend the nature and consequences of the instrument he executed.” Basically, not just drunk enough to have bad judgment, but drunk enough to have no idea of what you’re doing There’s a classic case that upheld this standard, Lucy v Zehmer, decided by the Supreme Court of Virginia in 1954 It’s a little embarrassing when your drunken antics end up in front of a state supreme court But the case makes for really fun reading
21
Lucy v. Zehmer Zehmer and his wife owned a farm (“the Ferguson farm”), Lucy had been trying to buy it for some time While out drinking, Lucy offers $50,000, Zehmer responds, “You don’t have $50,000” “We hereby agree to sell to W.O. Lucy the Ferguson Farm complete for $50,00000, title satisfactory to buyer.” The Zehmers owned a farm Lucy had been trying to buy it from them for a long time (They had made multiple offers, over several years, beginning at $20,000.) One night, Zehmer’s out drinking, and he runs into Lucy They continue to drink, and at some point, Lucy says something like, “I bet you’d sell that farm for $50,000.” Zehmer says, “You don’t have $50,000.” Lucy says, “I can get it!” Zehmer says, “No you can’t!” They argue for a while about whether Lucy would be able to raise $50,000 And eventually Lucy says, “Write it down!” So Zehmer grabs a discarded guest check (seriously), turns it over, and writes on the back, “We hereby agree to sell to W.O. Lucy the Ferguson Farm complete for $50,000, title satisfactory to buyer” (It appears from the trial proceedings that there were two drafts. In the first, the name of the farm and the word “satisfactory” were both misspelled. Also, the first draft originally said “I agree,” to which Lucy pointed out that Zehmer’s wife co-owned the farm; Zehmer crossed off the “I” and wrote “We”) So, Zehmer writes this contract and signs it; then he walks to the other end of the bar where his wife is sitting He tells her to sign it, she says, “What?” He whispers to her, don’t worry, it’s just a joke, we’re not selling the farm So she signs it He brings it back, Lucy takes the contract and puts it in his pocket
22
Lucy v. Zehmer Zehmer and his wife owned a farm (“the Ferguson farm”), Lucy had been trying to buy it for some time While out drinking, Lucy offers $50,000, Zehmer responds, “You don’t have $50,000” “We hereby agree to sell to W.O. Lucy the Ferguson Farm complete for $50,00000, title satisfactory to buyer.” That was Saturday. Sunday, Lucy calls his brother and gets him to put up half the money. Monday, Lucy goes to the registry of deeds to check the title, and then contacts Zehmer to carry out the contract Zehmer claims he was drunk, and joking, and refuses to honor the contract Lucy sues for specific performance, that is, asks the court to force Zehmer to sell him the farm at the agreed price There was some dispute during trial about exactly how drunk Zehmer was But it was ruled that while he was clearly drunk, he was not so drunk as to be “unable to comprehend the nature and consequences” of what he was doing (For one thing, a little while later, his wife asked him to drive her home.) Most of the opinion focuses on whether Lucy knew that Zehmer was joking when he wrote what looked like a proper, if unusual, legal contract Zehmer claimed the whole thing was “a bunch of two doggoned drunks bluffing to see who could talk the biggest and say the most” The court basically ruled that it wasn’t Lucy’s job to know Zehmer was joking That is, Zehmer may have thought he was joking, but it looked to Lucy like he was serious Zehmer behaved exactly as he would have behaved if he were drunk but actually wanted to sell the farm; which was good enough.
23
Lucy v. Zehmer So, you can be pretty drunk and still be bound by the contract you signed Might think “meeting of the minds” would be impossible But imagine what would happen if the rule went the other way You may think, being drunk, Zehmer lacked the necessary intent to enter into a contract Still, it probably makes sense not to make it too easy to invalidate a contract on the grounds that one of the parties was drunk, or joking If the ruling went the other way, it seems there would an awful lot of litigation over exactly how drunk someone was when a contract was signed Not to mention a lot more contracts being signed in bars, to give the parties an easy way out Or maybe a lot of lawyers carrying breathalyzers to make sure their contracts would be enforceable Basically, a more nuanced rule would be extremely difficult and costly to enforce So we seem to accept the cost of an occasional person making a bad decision while drunk, in order to keep the system working well the rest of the time. However, that’s not quite the final word on drunkenness If you were visibly drunk – that is, the other party clearly knew you were drunk – the court might be more willing to finding the contract unenforceable on other grounds (which we’ll get to shortly) such as fraud (you were tricked into signing) or unconscionability (the contract is too one-sided) If Zehmer had agreed to sell the farm for $10, the contract probably would not have been upheld But since the terms seemed reasonable, it was
24
Lucy v. Zehmer So, you can be pretty drunk and still be bound by the contract you signed Might think “meeting of the minds” would be impossible But imagine what would happen if the rule went the other way Borat lawsuits Julie Hilden, “Borat Sequel: Legal Proceedings Against Not Kazahk Journalist for Make Benefit Guileless Americans In Film” Moral of the story: don’t get drunk with people who might ask you to sign a contract There’s also a more recent example of the doctrine that being drunk does not get you out of a contract: the Borat lawsuits After the movie Borat came out a few years ago, two of the frat boys who ended up looking like racist a-holes sued They claimed they were tricked into signing the releases agreeing to be in the movie It seems the movie’s producers got them drunk and then asked them to sign the releases And also lied to them a lot – saying the movie was only going to be released in Europe, they wouldn’t use the frat boys’ names, or college, or frat Part of the problem for them is that the releases contained what are called “merger clauses” Merger clauses basically say, it doesn’t matter what else we already told you, all we’re agreeing to is what’s in this contract (Basically, any prior verbal agreement is “merged into” this contract, which is all we’re agreeing to.) It’s kind of sneaky, but it does seem to legally absolve the producers of anything they told the frat boys to get them to sign but that wasn’t in the contract Again, just being drunk doesn’t get you out of a contract One of the fratboys seemed to find it relevant that he was under the drinking age; but that, if anything, would make the producers liable in criminal court (for supplying alcohol to a minor), but not invalidate the releases (It’s also been established that the frat boys were all already heavy drinkers, unsurprisingly.) Last I heard, the lawsuits have all been dismissed, and the frat boys got nothing. (Since they’re not in the textbook; for the opinion in the Lucy v Zehmer case, which really does make great reading, see For an overview of the legal issues in the Borat lawsuits, see a piece by Julie Hilden, with the brilliant title “Borat Sequel: Legal Proceedings Against Not Kazakh Journalist for Make Benefit Guileless Americans in Film” at Moral of the story: don’t get drunk with people who might ask you to sign contracts.
25
Another formation defense: dire constraints
26
Dire constraints Necessity Duress
I’m about to starve, someone offers me a sandwich for $10,000 My boat’s about to sink, someone offers me a ride to shore for $1,000,000 Contract would not be upheld: I signed it out of necessity Duress Other party is responsible for situation I’m in “I made him an offer he couldn’t refuse” Contract signed at gunpoint would not be legally enforceable Back to contract law, and another situation in which we would not expect people to act rationally: courts will not enforce contracts signed under dire constraints, specifically, duress and necessity Necessity is when I’m at the point of starvation, and someone comes along and offers me a sandwich for $10,000 I don’t have it on me, so I sign a contract agreeing to pay him $10,000 and I eat the sandwich Or I’m on a boat that’s about to sink, and another boat offers me a ride back to shore for a million dollars In either case, the contract would not be upheld, since I signed it out of necessity. Duress is similar, but when the uncomfortable situation I’m in is being caused by the other party This is when someone kidnaps my child, and I agree to pay ransom to get her back The contract is not enforceable, because I agreed to it under duress This is exactly the idea of “making someone an offer he can’t refuse” from the Godfather; courts would not uphold a contract signed at gunpoint (Of course, whether you want to breach a contract with the Mafia, or sue the Mafia, is a separate question.) It’s not that hard to argue against holding people responsible for promises made under duress or necessity based on notions of fairness and morality The Friedman book (Law’s Order), however, tries to explain both of these in straight economic terms – I like his treatment a lot
27
Duress "I, the defendant, asked the Rowleys to hide me because I feared for my life. I offered the Rowleys an unspecified amount of money which they agreed upon, therefore forging a legally binding oral contract," Dimmick said in his hand-written court documents. He wants $235,000, in part to pay for the hospital bills that resulted from him being shot by police when they arrested him. source:
28
Friedman on duress Example
Mugger threatens to kill you unless you give him $100 You write him a check Do you have to honor the agreement? “Efficiency requires enforcing a contract if both parties wanted it to be enforceable” He did – he wants your $100 You did – you’d rather pay $100 than be killed So why not enforce it? Makes muggings more profitable leads to more muggings Tradeoff: refuse to enforce a Pareto-improving trade, in order to avoid incentive for bad behavior He begins with an example of duress A mugger approaches you in an alley and threatens to kill you unless you give him $100 You don’t have $100 on you, but he says he’ll accept a check When you get home, can you stop payment on the check? Or do you have to honor the agreement you made? Recall our principle from before: Efficiency requires enforcing a contract if both parties wanted it to be enforceable Clearly, the mugger wants the agreement to be enforceable; he’d rather have $100 than kill you And if you believe he’ll kill you if you don’t give him the money, then you clearly want it to be enforceable as well So making the contract enforceable seems to be a Pareto-improvement So what’s the problem? The problem, of course, is that even if such a contract is a Pareto-improvement once you’re in the situation, making such contracts enforceable encourages more muggings, since it increases the gains So refusing to enforce contracts signed under duress seems to trade off a short-term “loss” – the efficiency lost by ruling out some mutually beneficial trades – against creating less incentive for the bad behavior that put you in that situation in the first place.
29
Friedman on duress Example
Mugger threatens to kill you unless you give him $100 You write him a check Do you have to honor the agreement? “Efficiency requires enforcing a contract if both parties wanted it to be enforceable” He did – he wants your $100 You did – you’d rather pay $100 than be killed So why not enforce it? Makes muggings more profitable leads to more muggings Tradeoff: refuse to enforce a Pareto-improving trade, in order to avoid incentive for bad behavior (The fact that there is a tradeoff here suggests that it may not be optimal to rule out enforceability under every instance of duress For example, peace treaties can be thought of as contracts signed under duress – the losing side is facing the threat of continuing to battle a superior force Most people agree that peace treaties being enforceable is a good thing Peace treaties are clearly a good thing “ex post” – they make war less costly, by ending it more quickly It’s possible that by making war less costly, they encourage more wars – but it seems unlikely that this has much effect It’s probably efficient for peace treaties to be enforceable, but for promises made to a mugger to be unenforceable.)
30
What about necessity? Same logic doesn’t work for necessity
You get caught in a storm on your $10,000,000 sailboat Tugboat offers to tow you to shore for $9,000,000 (Otherwise he’ll save your life but let your boat sink) Duress: if we enforce contract, incentive for more crimes Here: if we enforce contract, incentive for more tugboats to be available for rescues – why is that bad? Social benefit of rescue: value of boat, minus cost of tow Say, $10,000,000 – $10,000 = $9,990,000 If tugboat gets entire value, his private gain = social gain So tugboat captain would invest the efficient amount in being available to rescue you So what’s the problem? However, the logic that tells us that contracts with muggers shouldn’t be enforced doesn’t work for contracts signed under necessity. You’re out sailing on your $10 million boat and get caught in a storm The boat starts taking on water and slowly begins to sink A tugboat comes by and offers to tow you back to shore, if you pay him $9 million If not, he won’t leave you to die – he’ll give you and your crew a ride back to shore, but your boat will be lost. With duress, we argued that making the contract enforceable would encourage muggers to commit more crimes, which is bad But here, making the contract enforceable would encourage tugboats to make themselves available to rescue more boats – so how is that a bad thing? In fact, Friedman points out that if we consider the tugboat captain’s decision beforehand – how much to invest in being in the right place at the right time – the higher the price, the better The total gain (to all parties) from the tugboat being there is the value of your boat, minus the cost of rescuing it – say, $10,000,000 - $10,000 = $9,990,000 Allowing the tugboat to recover the entire value of the boat would make his private gain from rescuing you exactly match the social gain This would cause the tugboat captain to invest the socially optimal amount in being available to rescue you!
31
What about necessity? What about your decision: whether to sail that day 1 in 1000 chance of being caught in a storm If so, 1 in 2 that a tugboat will rescue you Private cost of sailing: 1 in 2000 you lose boat, 1 in 2000 you pay tugboat captain value of boat $10,000,000/ $10,000,000/2000 = $10,000 So you’ll choose to sail if your value is above $10,000 Social cost: 1 in 2000 boat is lost, 1 in 2000 boat is rescued $10,000,000/ $10,000/2000 = $5,005 Efficient to sail when your value is above $5,005 When your value from sailing is between $5,005 and $10,000, you “undersail” If the price of being towed was just the marginal cost, your private cost = social cost and you would sail the efficient amount But on the other hand, consider your decision about whether to take your boat out on a day when a storm is a possibility Suppose there’s a 1-in-1000 chance of being caught in a storm And if you are caught in a storm, there’s a one-in-two chance a tugboat will be there to rescue you. If the tugboat captain can charge you the full value of your boat, then when weighing the costs and benefits of going sailing that day, you consider a 1-in-1000 chance of losing the full value of the boat That is, in your analysis of whether it’s worth sailing, you’ll include the 1/2000 possibility the boat sinks, and the 1/2000 possibility you pay its full value to an opportunistic tugboat captain – a total expected cost of $10,000 So you’ll only go sailing on days where your benefit is greater than $10,000 But when you go sailing and start to sink, half the time, your loss is the tugboat captain’s gain The social cost of you sailing includes a 1-in-2000 chance the boat is lost, plus a 1-in-2000 chance it has to be towed to shore So the total expected cost is $10,000,000 / $10,000 / = $5,005 So efficiency says you should go out sailing whenever the benefit to you is greater than $5,005. So if the tugboat captain is able to charge you the full value of the boat, you will “undersail” That is, in cases where your private gain from sailing is between $5,005 and $10,000, efficiency would suggest you should sail But since the private cost outweighs the benefit, you choose not to. On the other hand, suppose the tugboat could only charge you the cost of the tow Then the social cost of sailing would match the private cost to you - $5,005 This would lead you to go sailing exactly the efficient amount.
32
Friedman’s point Same transaction sets incentives on both parties
Price that would be efficient for one decision, is inefficient for other “Put the incentive where it would do the most good” Least inefficient price is somewhere in the middle And probably not the price that would be negotiated in the middle of a storm! Friedman, then, makes the following point The same transaction sets ex-ante incentives on both parties And the price that would lead to an efficient decision by one of them, would lead to an inefficient decision by the other. So, what should we do? As Friedman puts it, “put the incentive where it will do the most good.” Somewhere in between the cost of the tow and $10 million is the “least bad” price That is, the price that minimizes the losses due to inefficient choices by both sides If the tugboat captain is more sensitive to incentives than you are, the best price is likely closer to the value of the boat If you respond more to incentives than he does, the best price may be closer to the cost of the tow But regardless of the details, two things will generally be true: the least inefficient price is somewhere in the middle and there’s no reason for it to be the price that would be negotiated during the storm
33
Friedman’s point Same transaction sets incentives on both parties
Price that would be efficient for one decision, is inefficient for other “Put the incentive where it would do the most good” Least inefficient price is somewhere in the middle And probably not the price that would be negotiated in the middle of a storm! So makes sense for courts to overturn contracts signed under necessity, replace them with ex-ante optimal terms More general point Single price creates multiple incentives May be impossible to get efficient behavior in all dimensions That is, once you’re caught in a storm, all the relevant decisions have already been made you’ve decided whether to sail the tugboat captain has decided whether to be out there looking for sinking sailboats Those are like sunk costs – they don’t affect your bargaining position now So there’s no reason that, if you bargained over saving your boat during the storm, you’d end up anywhere near that efficient price On the other hand, there’s always the risk that bargaining breaks down and you refuse the tugboat captain’s offer, incurring a large social cost (the value of the boat minus the tow is lost) So from an efficiency point of view, it makes sense for courts to step in, overturn contracts that were signed under necessity, and replace them with what would have been ex-ante optimal terms This takes away the need to bargain hard during the storm, ensuring that the boat is saved; and it creates the “least bad” combination of incentives. So that’s Friedman’s take on duress and necessity.
34
Real duress versus fake duress
Court won’t enforce contracts signed under threat of harm “Give me $100 or I’ll shoot you” But many negotiations contain threats “Give me a raise, or I’ll quit” “$3,000 is my final offer for the car, take it or I walk” The difference? Threat of destruction of value versus failure to create value A promise is enforceable if extracted as price of cooperating in creating value; not if it was extracted by threat to destroy value One more thing about duress We said that the law will not enforce contracts signed under threat of harm – “give me $100 or I’ll shoot you.” However, lots of negotiations involve threats of some sort “give me a raise or I’ll quit and work for your competitor” “$3000 for my car is my final offer, take it or I walk.” This kind of threat is fine – it’s often necessary to tease out both sides’ threat points and figure out whether cooperation is efficient or not To distinguish between the two types of threats, note what happens in each case when bargaining fails In the second case, failure to reach a bargain results in a failure to create more value In the first case, failure to agree leads to destruction. In addition, successful bargains tend to create value, while contracts created under duress tend to just shift resources from one owner to another. In general, the following rule applies to distinguish duress: A promise is enforceable if it was extracted as the price of cooperating in creating value; a promise is unenforceable if it was extracted by a threat to destroy value
35
Example: Alaska Packers’ Association v Domenico (US Ct App 1902)
Captain hires crew in Seattle for fishing expedition to Alaska In Alaska, crew demands higher wages or they’ll quit, captain agrees Back in Seattle, captain refuses to pay the higher wages, claiming he agreed to them under duress Court ruled for captain Since crew had already agreed to do the work, no new consideration was given for promise of higher wage There’s a nice example of this in the textbook (They don’t cite the actual case, which is Alaska Packers’ Association v. Domenico, US Court of Appeals, 1902) A fishing boat captain hires a crew in Seattle for a fishing expedition to Alaska, agrees to pay them $50 each plus $0.02 per fish they catch Once they reach Alaska, the crew demands higher wages ($100), or else they won’t work Having little choice – they’re already there, and the fishing season is short – the captain agrees After they return to Seattle, the captain refuses to pay the higher wages, claiming he agreed to them under duress. While in Seattle, the crew that signed on faced competition from other fishermen Once in Alaska, they did not The captain had relied on their promise to work – by investing in fuel and supplies, and the time to sail to Alaska. While in Seattle, the crew’s only threat was to not cooperate in creating value – in which case the captain could have hired another crew Once in Alaska, the crew’s threat was to destroy value – by destroying the investment the captain had already made The court ruled the captain only had to pay the original wage – the renegotiated contract was not enforced
36
A performance excuse: impossibility
(That might be my answer to the slavery question from earlier. I would expect almost every time someone voluntarily sold him or herself into slavery, it would be a question of either incompetence, necessity, or duress. So almost all slave contracts should be unenforceable anyway, even if this type of contract was theoretically allowed. But it would be the “slave”’s responsibility to prove in court that he should be free, and the court would have to consider the case. So instead, we could just ban this sort of contract altogether to save time and money, rather than having to invalidate the contracts one by one.) Incompetence, duress, necessity are all formation defenses – reasons why a valid contract never existed Next, we turn to performance excuses – claims that even though a contract was signed in good faith, one of the parties should be allowed to break it without penalty
37
Next doctrine for voiding a contract: impossibility
When performance becomes impossible, should promisor owe damages, or be excused from performing? A perfect contract would explicitly state who bears each risk Contract may give clues as to how gaps should be filled Industry custom might be clear But in some cases, court must fill gap A surgeon agrees to perform an operation, then breaks his hand in a hideous golf cart accident the weekend before Clearly, he cannot perform the operation The question remains as to whether he is excused from performing, or whether he owes his would-be patient damages As we mentioned last week, a perfect contract would specify explicitly who would bear that risk But due to transaction costs, real contracts will generally not address risks that are very remote In some cases, even if it does not address the risk explicitly, the contract itself may give clues as to how the gap should be filled An example of this from the textbook: a drilling company agrees to drill a well for a landowner, but the drill runs into impenetrable granite Suppose that the driller was competing with other companies for the offer, but the landowner agreed to a price much higher than the competition The court might feel that the driller was implicitly guaranteeing performance, and should owe damages when performance became impossible Or industry custom might be for one side or the other to bear that risk. In situations where neither the contract itself nor the custom of the industry assigns the risk, the law has to
38
Next doctrine for voiding a contract: impossibility
In most situations, when neither contract nor industry norm offers guidance, promisor is held liable for breach But there are exceptions Change “destroyed a basic assumption on which the contract was made” In most typical cases, the promisor is liable for breach, even when the breach is not his fault (To put it another way, contract liability is strict.) So a construction company that finishes a building late due because or unexpected complications is generally liable. However, there are some instances where non-performance is excused by physical impossibility A famous artist agrees to paint someone’s portrait, and then dies; his estate does not owe for the breach of the promise A manufacturer whose factory burns down might be excused from performance Similarly, breach is typically excused if performance became illegal A shipping company takes a bunch of orders, but then its ships are commandeered to carry military cargo during a war; the company is excused from its civilian commitments. One legal theory in these cases is that an unexpected contingency destroyed “a basic assumption on which the contract was made” The painter assumed he would be alive the manufacturer assumed his factory would be useable Under this theory, if a contract is made in good faith and then events destroy one of its basic assumptions, breach is excused. Of course, the question then becomes, when is something a “basic assumption” and when is it not? The book sidesteps this question, and instead moves to what efficiency would require:
39
Next doctrine for voiding a contract: impossibility
In most situations, when neither contract nor industry norm offers guidance, promisor is held liable for breach But there are exceptions Change “destroyed a basic assumption on which the contract was made” Efficiency requires assigning liability to the party that can bear the risk at least cost How to determine who that is? Efficiency requires assigning liability to the party who can bear the risk at least cost. That is, nonperformance due to impossibility is just another type of risk; so for efficiency, it should be allocated to whichever party is the low-cost bearer of the risk. In many cases, one party can take precautions to minimize the risk the manufacturer can install sprinklers in his factory the painter can prioritize commissioned pieces over other work and so on In those cases, that party is typically the low-cost avoider, and efficiency suggests they should bear the risk. When the risk cannot be reduced, the book claims that liability should lie with the party who can best spread the risk, through insurance or diversification. (We already saw the general principle of gap-filling by allocating risk to the low-cost avoider, that is, the person who can most cheaply mitigate or bear the risk The rationale is that this is what the original contract would have done, if it had bothered to consider that risk.)
40
Who is the efficient bearer of a particular risk?
Friedman offers several bases for making this determination Spreading losses across many transactions Moral hazard: who is in better position to influence outcome? Friedman offers several ways to figure out who this is First: spreading losses “Suppose I am having a house built by a large firm that builds many houses each year. There is some risk that the house might burn down while it is being built. We could allocate that risk either to me, by specifying that I will have to pay for the additional construction costs in such a case, or to the builder. Since the builder is building many houses in different places, he can spread the risk; I cannot. From that standpoint at least, our contract should specify a fixed price, whether or not something goes wrong. If the contract does not specify who bears the risk, risk spreading provides an argument for assigning it to the builder.” Second: who is in a better position to influence the outcome? “In the case of a firm that builds houses the two arguments go in the same direction. The builder is not only in a better position than I am to spread the risk, he is also in a better position than I am to keep the house from burning down while he is building it.” (This is the argument that Baxendale should have borne the risk of a shipping delay – he’s the one who decided how to ship the broken crankshaft, so his actions influenced the outcome.)
41
Who is the efficient bearer of a particular risk?
Friedman offers several bases for making this determination Spreading losses across many transactions Moral hazard: who is in better position to influence outcome? Adverse selection: who is more aware of risk, even if he can’t do anything about it? “…The party with control over some part of the production process is in a better position both to prevent losses and to predict them. It follows that an efficient contract will usually assign the loss associated with something going wrong to the party with control over that particular something.” For the third rule, Friedman gives the following question. I promise to sell you 10,000 widgets; a drunk driver crashes into my factory, destroying half of them. I deliver them late, costing you money. Do I owe you damages? “A third factor in allocating risk is adverse selection. …I did not know that that particular drunk driver was going to crash through that particular wall. But I probably do know a good deal more than you do about the chance that something – accident, strike, or bad planning – will prevent me from delivering the widgets to you on schedule. If our contract makes me liable for the resulting loss, you don’t have to worry about that risk in deciding whom to buy your widgets from. You know what price I am charging, and you know that I am insuring you against the risk of nondelivery. If the contract specified that you had to bear the risk, you would need to know the reliability of alternative sellers as well as their price in order to decide which one is offering the best deal. “As this example suggests, moral hazard and adverse selection tend to cut in the same direction. As a general rule the party with control over some part of the production process is in a better position both to prevent losses and to predict them. It follows that an efficient contract will usually assign the loss associated with something going wrong to the party with control over that particular something.”
42
That’s why Hadley v Baxendale was “surprising”
Baxendale (shipper) could influence speed of delivery, Hadley could not So Baxendale was efficient bearer of the risk of delay Court ruled he didn’t owe damages for lost profits, forcing Hadley to bear much of this risk Only makes sense as a “penalty default” Rule creates incentive for Hadley to reveal urgency of this shipment
43
Contracts based on bad information (probably won’t get to)
44
Contracts based on faulty information
Four doctrines for invalidating a contract Fraud Failure to disclose Frustration of purpose Mutual mistake
45
Fraud Fraud: one party was deliberately tricked
This is a piece of wood, painted to look a little bit like an iPad This is a story of a woman in South Carolina who was approached in a McDonald’s parking lot and paid $180 for an iPad Fraud covers situations where one party was deliberately tricked The guy with the escort was similarly claiming fraud – saying he was originally promised one price, and then a different price was demanded later In the example from the textbook – the farmer pays $25 for a sure method of killing grasshoppers – the contract would be overturned due to fraud (the farmer was tricked), and he would get his money back If you are selling me a used car, and specifically lie to me about the condition that it’s in – you tell me you just replaced the clutch when in fact you did not – I could later get the contract overturned (force you to buy back the car) based on fraud Similarly, if I ask you a specific question about the car, you have to answer me honestly The economic rationale is obvious. The point of contracts is to allow us to transact. The point of transacting is to allocate rights and resources efficiently. If people are allowed to “trick” other people into buying things they don’t really value, this doesn’t increase efficiency – and makes it more costly to achieve valuable trades, since people have to be more careful. source:
46
What if you trick someone by withholding information?
Under the civil law, there is a duty to disclose If you fail to supply information you should have, contract will be voided – failure to disclose Less so under the common law Seller has to share information about hidden dangers… …but generally not information that makes a product less valuable without making it dangerous Exception: new products come with “implied warranty of fitness” Another exception: Obde v Schlemeyer In the civil law tradition, a contract may be void because you did not supply the information that you should have The doctrine here is failure to disclose Under the common law, however, a seller is not forced to tell a buyer everything he knows about what he’s selling He is forced to warn the buyer about any hidden dangers – such as the side effects of a drug, or failing brakes on a car But under the common law, there is not a general duty to disclose information that makes a product less valuable without making it dangerous (If you’re selling me a used car, you have to tell me if the brakes don’t work; you don’t have to mention that the stereo doesn’t work.) But there are a couple of exceptions: If you’re selling a new product, it’s assumed that it can perform the basic function it’s intended for – new products come with an “implied warranty of fitness” Another exception was introduced by the Washington Supreme Court in 1960
47
Duty to disclose under common law
Under common law, seller required to inform buyer about hidden safety risks, generally not other information But… Obde v Schlemeyer (1960, Sup Ct of WA) Seller knew building was infested with termites, did not tell buyer Termites should have been exterminated immediately to prevent further damage Court in Obde imposed duty to disclose (awarded damages) Obde v Schlemeyer (1960): a seller knew his building was infested with termites and did not tell the buyer The buyer discovered the termites after the sale was completed, and sued The termites should have been exterminated immediately to prevent further damage The court in Obde deviated from tradition and imposed a duty to disclose
48
Duty to disclose under common law
Under common law, seller required to inform buyer about hidden safety risks, generally not other information But… Obde v Schlemeyer (1960, Sup Ct of WA) Seller knew building was infested with termites, did not tell buyer Termites should have been exterminated immediately to prevent further damage Court in Obde imposed duty to disclose (awarded damages) Some states require used car dealers to reveal major repairs done, sellers of homes to reveal certain types of defects… In Obde, the seller did not offer the fact that the building had termites, but also did not lie about it – the buyer didn’t ask If the buyer had asked, and the seller claimed there were no termites, we would have been in the case of fraud Other common-law courts and legislatures have also begun imposing a duty to disclose in particular situations Lenders now must disclose the APR on all consumer loans Many states require used car dealers to reveal major repairs done on the car being sold Many states require sellers of homes to reveal certain types of defects Such requirements are meant to improve information exchange and lower transaction costs
49
Failure to disclose? source:
50
What if both parties were misinformed?
Frustration of Purpose Change in circumstance made the original promise pointless Coronation Cases “When a contingency makes performance pointless, assign liability to party who can bear risk at least cost” Fraud and failure to disclose are situations where one party is misinformed The other two doctrines cover situations in which both parties to the contract are misinformed When a change in circumstance makes performance of a promise pointless, the contract will often not be enforced based on the doctrine of frustration of purpose I buy tickets to the Super Bowl, and prepay a separate vendor $100 for game-day parking close to the stadium For some reason, the game is delayed a week, so I no longer want an expensive parking space in Indianapolis for February 5, but the vendor wants to keep my money This is basically what happened in the Coronation Cases, which established the rule In the early 1900s, rooms in buildings along certain streets in London were rented in advance for the day of the new king’s coronation parade The new king became ill, and the coronation was postponed The renters, then, did not want the rooms But some of the owners tried to collect the rent anyway The courts ruled that a change in circumstance had “frustrated the purpose” of the original contracts, and refused to enforce them Impossibility was a doctrine for assigning the risk that performance becomes impossible Frustration of purpose is a doctrine for assigning the risk that performance becomes pointless The same economic principle applies: When a contingency makes performance pointless, assign liability to the party who can bear the risk at least cost. In this case, the property owners could eliminate their losses by renting the rooms a second time, for the rescheduled parade Thus, there was hardly any cost to the owners from bearing the risk So efficiency would seem to allocate the risk to them Which is exactly what happened
51
What if both parties were misinformed?
Frustration of Purpose Change in circumstance made the original promise pointless Coronation Cases “When a contingency makes performance pointless, assign liability to party who can bear risk at least cost” Mutual Mistake Mutual mistake about facts Circumstances had already changed, but we didn’t know Logger buys land with timber on it, but forest fire had wiped out the timber the week before Mutual mistake about identity Disagreement over what was being sold The other doctrine for misinformation is mutual mistake – there are different types There could be a mutual mistake about facts This can be thought of as a contingency already having arisen before the parties signed the contract, but without their knowledge. A logger contracts to buy some land with timber on it As it happens, the timber was destroyed by forest fire the week before the contract was signed, but neither party knew about it The owner at the time of the accident is usually the low-cost avoider of the risk – that is, the buyer is unlikely to be able to prevent forest fires on someone else’s land Having the owner bear this risk means not enforcing the contract I buy a painting at an auction, and the gallery and I learn later the painting was a forgery Another type of mutual mistake is mutual mistake about identity One of our early examples featured a beat-up Chevy and a shiny new Cadillac The seller believed he was negotiating the sale of the Chevy The buyer thought she was negotiating the purchase of the Cadillac In this case, the court would typically invalidate the contract based on mutual mistake, and simply return the buyer’s money and the seller’s keys. When there is mutual mistake about the object being sold, enforcing the contract would have the effect of making an involuntary exchange We assume that voluntary exchange is efficient; involuntary exchange may not be So efficiency agrees with the doctrine of setting aside contracts based on mutual mistake of this type.
52
Another principle for allocating risks efficiently: uniting knowledge and control
Hadley v Baxendale (miller and shipper) Hadley knew shipment was time-critical But Baxendale was deciding how to ship crankshaft (boat or train) Party that had information was not the party making decisions Efficiency generally requires uniting knowledge and control Contracts that unite knowledge and control are generally efficient, should be upheld Contracts that separate knowledge and control may be inefficient, should more often be set aside We’ve seen a few principles for determining the efficient bearer of a particular risk Another principle for allocating risks was illustrated in Hadley v Baxendale, the miller with the broken crankshaft In that case, heavy losses were incurred because the party with information was not the one making decisions That is, Hadley, knew how time-critical his shipment was But it was Baxendale who chose to ship the crankshaft by boat instead of train This brings us to a general principle about information: Efficiency generally requires uniting knowledge and control. If I value some land more than you, it may be because I have knowledge of a way to derive more value from the land The land has coal underneath, and I know how to mine it Or the land is good for growing tomatoes, and I know how to grow tomatoes. In those cases, selling the object to the party who values it more unites knowledge and control, and therefore increases efficiency. As a general principle, then, contracts that unite knowledge and control should generally be upheld, and contracts that separate knowledge and control should more often be set aside This gives us another way to look at the doctrines related to information
53
Mutual vs. Unilateral Mistake
Mutual mistake: neither party had correct information Contract neither united nor separated knowledge and control Unilateral mistake: one party has mistaken information I know your car is a valuable antique, you think it’s worthless You sell it to me at a low price Contracts based on unilateral mistake are generally upheld When we looked at mutual mistake, neither party had correct information So the contract neither united nor separated knowledge and control So we did not discuss it in those terms However, there are situations where one party to a contract has mistaken information and one does not This is called unilateral mistake. Suppose you have an old car and you think it’s just a worthless old car But I know it’s a classic and worth a lot of money I agree to buy it from you at a low price, and afterwards, you learn the truth The contract was based on unilateral mistake – you were wrong about the value of the car, but I knew the truth. In these cases, the contract is generally enforced While contracts based on mutual mistake will generally be set aside, contracts based on unilateral mistake are generally enforced.
54
Mutual vs. Unilateral Mistake
Mutual mistake: neither party had correct information Contract neither united nor separated knowledge and control Unilateral mistake: one party has mistaken information I know your car is a valuable antique, you think it’s worthless You sell it to me at a low price Contracts based on unilateral mistake are generally upheld Contracts based on unilateral mistake generally unite knowledge and control And, enforcing them creates an incentive to gather information This makes sense for two reasons First, if I know the car is more valuable and manage to buy it from you, this unites knowledge and control I probably know the car is valuable because I’m more into classic cars, and will thus take better care of it Much as it’s disappointing to you to get screwed out of something valuable, this may well be efficient. And second, this creates an incentive to gather information Sometimes gathering information is costly And often, having better information leads to efficiency Rewarding people for having better information (allowing them to profit from it) leads to an incentive to gather information, which may be a good thing (Of course, if you sued to try to void our contract, it would put me in a funny position Mutual mistake is a valid formation defense So you could claim neither of us knew the value of the car when you sold it to me. So now I have to get up in court and claim, no, I wasn’t ignorant, I was just trying to rip you off And if I can convince the court I was trying to rip you off, I get to keep the car.)
55
Unilateral mistake: Laidlaw v Organ (U.S. Supreme Court, 1815)
War of 1812: British blockaded port of New Orleans Price of tobacco fell, since it couldn’t be exported Organ (tobacco buyer) learned the war was over Immediately negotiated with Laidlaw firm to buy a bunch of tobacco at the depressed wartime price Next day, news broke the war had ended, price of tobacco went up, Laidlaw sued Supreme Court ruled that Organ was not required to communicate his information There was a famous case in 1815 that concerned unilateral mistake, Laidlaw v Organ During the War of 1812, the British blockaded the port of New Orleans This depressed the price of tobacco, since nobody could make money exporting it Organ was a tobacco buyer; he received private information that a treaty had been signed, ending the war That same day, he negotiated with the Laidlaw firm, which did not know about the treaty, to buy some tobacco at the depressed price The next day, news broke that the war was over, the price of tobacco soared, and Laidlaw sued Despite it being a unilateral mistake – Organ knew the war was over, Laidlaw did not – the contract was set aside at the original trial It was appealed to the Supreme Court, who ruled that Organ was not required to communicate his knowledge and ordered a retrial Things get a bit fuzzy from there, and the doctrine does not seem to be rock-solid But nonetheless, unilateral error is generally not considered a valid reason to void a contract.
56
Uniting knowledge and control
Laidlaw v. Organ established: contracts based on unilateral mistake are generally valid Agrees with efficiency: these contracts typically unite knowledge and control What about Obde v. Schlemeyer? The termites case was based on unilateral mistake Court still upheld contract, but punished seller for hiding information In that case, contract separated knowledge from control
57
Unilateral mistake: productive versus redistributive information
Productive information: information that can be used to produce more wealth Redistributive information: information that can be used to redistribute wealth in favor of informed party Cooter and Ulen Contracts based on one party’s knowledge of productive information should be enforced… …especially if that knowledge was the result of active investment Contracts based on one party’s knowledge of purely redistributive information, or fortuitously acquired information, should not be enforced We said that one of the reasons for enforcing contracts based on unilateral mistake is to create an incentive to gather information Cooter and Ulen go further, by drawing a distinction between productive information and redistributive information productive information is information that can be used to produce more wealth productive information could be that farmland is resting atop valuable underground minerals, or the existence of a water route between Europe and China redistributive information is information that can be used to redistribute wealth in favor of the informed party redistributive information could be that the state plans to build a highway through a particular piece of land, changing property values nearby Productive information increases total wealth So efficiency requires giving people incentives to it Thus, letting people profit from productive information is good so enforcing contracts signed under unilateral error is good when the private information is productive Redistributive information does not create additional wealth So efficiency does not require giving incentives to discover it Letting people profit from redistributive information is inefficient – leads to too much investment in this type of information Cooter and Ulen also point out that to create incentives, information only needs to be rewarded when it was acquired through effort or investment, not by chance Thus, they come to the principle: Contracts based upon one party’s knowledge of productive information – especially if that knowledge was the result of active investment – should be enforced Whereas contracts based upon one party’s knowledge of purely redistributive information or fortuitously acquired information should not be enforced.
Similar presentations
© 2025 SlidePlayer.com. Inc.
All rights reserved.