Presentation is loading. Please wait.

Presentation is loading. Please wait.

to Prospect Theory Peter P. Wakker Theo Offerman Joep Sonnemans

Similar presentations


Presentation on theme: "to Prospect Theory Peter P. Wakker Theo Offerman Joep Sonnemans"— Presentation transcript:

1 Adapting de Finetti's proper scoring rules for Eliciting Bayesian Beliefs
to Prospect Theory Peter P. Wakker Theo Offerman Joep Sonnemans Gijs van de Kuilen July 6, 2006 IAREP, Paris Topic: Our chance estimates of France to become world-champion. F: France will win. not-F: Italy.

2 Imagine following bet: You choose 0  r  1, as you like.
2 Imagine following bet: You choose 0  r  1, as you like. We call r your reported probability of France. You receive F not-F   1 – (1– r) – r2 What r should be chosen?

3 Optimal r = your true subjective probability of France winning.
First assume EV. After some algebra:  p true subjective probability;  optimizing p(1 – (1– r)2) + (1–p) (1–r2);  1st order condition 2p(1–r) – 2r(1–p) = 0;  r = p. Optimal r = your true subjective probability of France winning. Easy in algebraic sense. Conceptually: !!! Wow !!! de Finetti (1962) and Brier (1950) were the first neuro-economists! 3

4 "Bayesian truth serum" (Prelec, Science, 2005).
4 "Bayesian truth serum" (Prelec, Science, 2005). Superior to elicitations through preferences . Superior to elicitations through indifferences ~ (BDM). Widely used: Hanson (Nature, 2002), Prelec (Science 2005). In accounting (Wright 1988), Bayesian statistics (Savage 1971), business (Stael von Holstein 1972), education (Echternacht 1972), medicine (Spiegelhalter 1986), psychology (Liberman & Tversky 1993; McClelland & Bolger 1994), experimental economics (Nyarko & Schotter 2002). We want to introduce these very nice features into prospect theory.

5 Survey Part I. Deriving r from theories:  expected value;
5 Survey Part I. Deriving r from theories:  expected value;  expected utility;  nonexpected utility for probabilities;  nonexpected utility for ambiguity. Part II. Deriving theories from observed r. In particular: Derive beliefs/ambiguity attitudes. Will be surprisingly easy. Proper scoring rules <==> Prospect theory: Mutual benefits. Part III. Implementation in an experiment.

6 Part I. Deriving r from Theories (EV, and then 3 deviations).
6 Part I. Deriving r from Theories (EV, and then 3 deviations).

7 Let us assume that you strongly believe in France (Zidane …)
7 Let us assume that you strongly believe in France (Zidane …) Your "true" subj. prob.(F) = 0.75. EV: Then your optimal rF = 0.75.

8 8 0.25 0.50 0.75 1 p R(p) Reported probability R(p) = rF as function of true probability p, under: EU nonEU EV rEV rEU (a) expected value (EV); 0.69 0.61 (b) expected utility with U(x) = x (EU); rnonEU rnonEUA (c) nonexpected utility for known probabilities, with U(x) = x0.5 and with w(p) as common; rnonEUA: nonexpected utility for unknown probabilities ("Ambiguity"). next p. go to p. 11, Example EU go to p. 15, Example nonEU go to p. 19, Example nonEUA

9 Deviation 1 from EV: EU with U nonlinear Now optimize
9 So far we assumed EV (as does everyone using proper scoring rules, but as no-one does in modern decision theory...) Deviation 1 from EV: EU with U nonlinear Now optimize pU(1 – (1– r)2) + (1 – p)U(1 – r2)

10 Reversed (and explicit) expression:
10 U´(1–r2) U´(1 – (1–r)2) (1–p) p + p r = Reversed (and explicit) expression: U´(1–r2) U´(1 – (1–r)2) (1–r) r + r p =

11 How bet on France? [Expected Utility]. EV: rEV = 0.75.
11 How bet on France? [Expected Utility]. EV: rEV = 0.75. Expected utility, U(x) = x: rEU = 0.69. You now bet less on France. Closer to safety (Winkler & Murphy 1970). go to p. 8, with figure of R(p)

12 12 Deviation 2 from EV: nonexpected utility for probabilities (Allais 1953, Machina 1982, Kahneman & Tversky 1979, Quiggin 1982, Schmeidler 1989, Gilboa 1987, Gilboa & Schmeidler 1989, Gul 1991, Levy-Garboua 2001, Luce & Fishburn 1991, Tversky & Kahneman 1992, Birnbaum 2005) For two-gain prospects, virtually all those theories are as follows: For r  0.5, nonEU(r) = w(p)U(1 – (1–r)2) + (1–w(p))U(1–r2). r < 0.5, symmetry; soit! Different treatment of highest and lowest outcome: "rank-dependence."

13 Figure. The common weighting function w.
13 p w(p) 1 Figure. The common weighting function w. w(p) = exp(–(–ln(p))) for  = 0.65. w(1/3)  1/3; 1/3 w(2/3)  .51 2/3 .51

14 ) ( (1–w(p)) Now w(p) r = U´(1–r2) w(p) + U´(1 – (1–r)2)
14 Now U´(1–r2) U´(1 – (1–r)2) (1–w(p)) w(p) + w(p) r = U´(1–r2) U´(1 – (1–r)2) (1–r) r + r p = Reversed (explicit) expression: w –1 ( )

15 How bet on France now? [nonEU with probabilities]. EV: rEV = 0.75.
15 How bet on France now? [nonEU with probabilities]. EV: rEV = 0.75. EU: rEU = 0.69. Nonexpected utility, U(x) = x, w(p) = exp(–(–ln(p))0.65). rnonEU = 0.61. You bet even less on France. Again closer to safety. go to p. 8, with figure of R(p) Deviations were at level of behavior so far, not of be-liefs. Now for something different; more fundamental.

16 16 3rd violation of EV: Ambiguity (unknown probabilities; belief/decision-attitude? Yet to be settled). No objective data on probabilities. How deal with unknown probabilities? Have to give up Bayesian beliefs descriptively. According to some even normatively.

17 All currently existing decision models: For r  0.5, nonEU(r) =
Instead of additive beliefs p = P(F), nonadditive beliefs B(F) (Dempster&Shafer, Tversky&Koehler, etc.) 17 All currently existing decision models: For r  0.5, nonEU(r) = w(B(F))U(1 – (1–r)2) + (1–w(B(F)))U(1–r2). Don't recognize? Is just '92 prospect theory = Schmeidler (1989)! Write W(F) = w(B(F)). Can always write B(F) = w–1(W(F)). For binary gambles: Pfanzagl 1959; Luce ('00 Chapter 3); Ghirardato & Marinacci ('01, "biseparable").

18 ) ( (1–w(B(F))) w(B(F)) rF = U´(1–r2) w(B(F)) + U´(1 – (1–r)2)
18 U´(1–r2) U´(1 – (1–r)2) (1–w(B(F))) w(B(F)) + w(B(F)) rF = U´(1–r2) U´(1 – (1–r)2) (1–r) r + r B(F) = Reversed (explicit) expression: w –1 ( )

19 How bet on France now? [Ambiguity, nonEUA]. rEV = 0.75. rEU = 0.69.
19 How bet on France now? [Ambiguity, nonEUA]. rEV = 0.75. rEU = 0.69. rnonEU = 0.61 (under plausible assumptions). Similarly, rnonEUA = 0.52. r's are close to always saying fifty-fifty. "Belief" component B(F) = w–1(W) = 0.62. go to p. 8, with figure of R(p)

20 B(F): ambiguity attitude /=/ beliefs??
20 B(F): ambiguity attitude /=/ beliefs?? Before entering that debate, first: How measure B(F)? Our contribution: through proper scoring rules with "risk correction."

21 Part II. Deriving Theoretical Things from Empirical Observations of r
21 We reconsider reversed explicit expressions: U´(1–r2) U´(1 – (1–r)2) (1–r) r + r p = w –1 ( ) B(F) = Corollary. p = B(F) if related to the same r!!

22 Example (participant 25)
22 stock 20, CSM certificates dealing in sugar and bakery-ingredients. Reported probability: r = 0.75 91 For objective probability p=0.70, also reports r = 0.75. Conclusion: B(elief) of ending in bar is 0.70! We simply measure the R(p) curves, and use their inverses: is risk correction.

23 Our proposal takes the best of several worlds!
23 Our proposal takes the best of several worlds! Need not measure U,W, and w. Get "canonical probability" without measuring indifferences (BDM …; Holt 2006). Calibration without needing many repeated observations. Do all that with no more than simple proper-scoring-rule questions.

24 Mutual benefits prospect theory <==> proper scoring rules
24 Mutual benefits prospect theory <==> proper scoring rules We bring insights of modern prospect theory to proper scoring rules. Make them empirically more realistic. (EV is not credible in …) We bring insights of proper scoring rules to prospect theory. Make B very easy to measure and analyze. Directly implementable empirically. We did so in an experiment, and found plausible results.

25 Part III. Experimental Test of Our Correction Method
25 Part III. Experimental Test of Our Correction Method

26 Method Participants. N = 93 students.
26 Method Participants. N = 93 students. Procedure. Computarized in lab. Groups of 15/16 each. 4 practice questions.

27 Stimuli 1. First we did proper scoring rule for unknown probabilities
Stimuli 1. First we did proper scoring rule for unknown probabilities. 72 in total. 27 For each stock two small intervals, and, third, their union. Thus, we test for additivity.

28 Stimuli 2. Known probabilities: Two 10-sided dies thrown.
Yield random nr. between 01 and 100. Event F: nr.  75 (etc.). Done for all probabilities j/20. 28 Motivating subjects. Real incentives. Two treatments. 1. All-pay. Points paid for all questions points = €1. Average earning €15.05. 2. One-pay (random-lottery system). One question, randomly selected afterwards, played for real. 1 point = €20. Average earning: €15.30.

29 29 Results

30 Average correction curves.
30

31 Individual corrections
31 F( ρ ) 1 0.1 0.2 0.3 0.4 0.5 0.6 0.7 0.9 Individual corrections 0.8 treatment one treatment all ρ -2.0 -1.5 -1.0 -0.5 0.0 0.5 1.0 1.5

32 32 Figure 9.1. Empirical density of additivity bias for the two treatments Fig. b. Treatment t=ALL 0.6 20 40 60 80 100 120 140 160 0.4 0.2 0.2 0.4 0.6 Fig. a. Treatment t=ONE For each interval [(j2.5)/100, (j+2.5)/100] of length 0.05 around j/100, we counted the number of additivity biases in the interval, aggregated over 32 stocks and 89 individuals, for both treatments. With risk-correction, there were 65 additivity biases between and in the treatment t=ONE, and without risk-correction there were 95 such; etc. corrected uncorrected

33 Summary and Conclusion
33 Summary and Conclusion Modern decision theories: proper scoring rules are heavily biased. We correct for those biases, with benefits for proper-scoring rule community and for nonEU community. Experiment: correction improves quality; reduces deviations from ("rational"?) Bayesian beliefs. Do not remove all deviations from Bayesian beliefs. Beliefs seem to be genuinely nonadditive/nonBayesian/sensitive-to- ambiguity.


Download ppt "to Prospect Theory Peter P. Wakker Theo Offerman Joep Sonnemans"

Similar presentations


Ads by Google