Download presentation
Presentation is loading. Please wait.
Published byBranden Benson Modified over 5 years ago
1
Philosophy 1100 Class #9 Title: Critical Reasoning
Instructor: Paul Dickey Address: Website: Today: Submit Final Essay Turn in Exercise 9-14 Return Portfolios In-Class Review Chapter 9, Exercise 9-2, 9-14. Discuss Chapter 10 Next Week: No physical class Final Exam (Take-home) 1
2
Final Exam will be posted on Quia by Wednesday, 11/12
Final Exam will be posted on Quia by Wednesday, 11/12. Note that there will be some exercises that may require drawing & free form text. Complete the exam in the following way: On the Scantron answer sheet, answer all multiple choice questions. On separate sheets of paper, answer all other questions. After you have finished taking the exam, either: Scan the Scantron answer sheet & all other pages as jpg, pdf or docx files and them to me at or (if necessary) physically mail Scantron sheet & other pages to me. (Address provided if requested) Postmark must be by end of business day 11/17/14, exams must be received no later than 6:00 P.M. on 11/17. Please Note: For every 8 hours (or partial) the exam is late, a full grade will be reduced. NO EXCEPTIONS. Exams received in mail will be docked TWO letter grades for each day posted after 11/17.
3
Chapter Nine Deductive Arguments: Categorical Logic
3
4
Class Workshop: Exercise 9-14 4
5
Team Game (if time available)
You must perform all of the following on the given argument: Translate the premises and conclusion to standard logical forms and put the argument into a syllogistic form. Identify the type of logical form for each statement. For each statement, give an equivalent statement and name the operation that you used to do so. Identify the minor, major, and middle terms of the syllogism. Draw the appropriate Venn Diagram for the premises. Identify all distributed terms of the argument and the number of negative claims in the premises and conclusion. What, if any, rules of validity are broken by the argument? State if the argument is valid or invalid.
6
Everything that Pete won at the carnival must be junk
Everything that Pete won at the carnival must be junk. I know that Pete won everything that Bob won, and all the stuff Bob won is junk. Translate the premises and conclusion to standard logical forms and put the argument into a syllogistic form. Identify the type of logical form for each statement. Define terms – P: Pete’s winnings at the carnival J: Thing that are junk B: Bob’s winnings at the carnival A-claim – All B is P A-claim - All B is J A-claim – All P is J
7
Everything that Pete won at the carnival must be junk
Everything that Pete won at the carnival must be junk. I know that Pete won everything that Bob won, and all the stuff Bob won is junk. For each statement, give an equivalent statement and name the operation that you used to do so. Identify the minor, major, and middle terms of the syllogism. A-claim – All B is P Contrapositive is equivalent – All non-P are non-B. A-claim - All B is J Obverse is equivalent – No B is non-J. A-claim – All P is J Obverse is equivalent – No P is non-J. Minor term is P; Major term is J; and Middle term is B.
8
Everything that Pete won at the carnival must be junk
Everything that Pete won at the carnival must be junk. I know that Pete won everything that Bob won, and all the stuff Bob won is junk. Draw the appropriate Venn Diagram for the premises.
9
Everything that Pete won at the carnival must be junk
Everything that Pete won at the carnival must be junk. I know that Pete won everything that Bob won, and all the stuff Bob won is junk. Identify all distributed terms of the argument and the number of negative claims in the premises and conclusion. What, if any, rules of validity are broken by the argument? State if the argument is valid or invalid. All B is P All B is J All P is J Since A-claims distribute their subject terms, B is Distributed in the premises and P is distributed in the conclusion. There are no negative claims in either the premises or the conclusion. Since P is distributed in the conclusion, but not in either premise rule 3 is broken. Thus, the argument is invalid.
10
The Game You must perform all of the following on the given argument:
Translate the premises and conclusion to standard logical forms and put the argument into a syllogistic form. Identify the type of logical form for each statement. For each statement, give an equivalent statement and name the operation that you used to do so. Identify the minor, major, and middle terms of the syllogism. Draw the appropriate Venn Diagram for the premises. Identify all distributed terms of the argument and the number of negative claims in the premises and conclusion. What, if any, rules of validity are broken by the argument? State if the argument is valid or invalid. Exercises 9-19, p. 277, Problems #5.
11
Chapter Ten Deductive Arguments: Truth-Functional Logic
11
12
Truth Functional logic is important because it gives us a consistent tool to determine whether certain statements are true or false based on the truth or falsity of other statements. A sentence is truth-functional if whether it is true or not depends entirely on whether or not partial sentences are true or false. For example, the sentence "Apples are fruits and carrots are vegetables" is truth-functional since it is true just in case each of its sub-sentences "apples are fruits" and "carrots are vegetables" is true, and it is false otherwise. Note that not all sentences of a natural language, such as English, are truth-functional, e.g. Mary knows that the Green Bay Packers won the Super Bowl.
13
Truth Functional Logic: The Basics
Please note that while studying Categorical Logic, we used uppercase letters (or variables) to represent classes about which we made claims. In truth-functional logic, we use uppercase letters (variables) to stand for claims themselves. In truth-functional logic, any given claim P is true or false. Thus, the simplest truth table form is: P _ T F
14
Truth Functional Logic: The Basics
Perhaps the simplest truth table operation is negation: P ~P T F F T
15
Truth Functional Logic: The Basics
Now, to add a second claim, to account for all truth-functional possibilities our representation must state: P Q T T T F F T F F And the operation of conjunction is represented by: P Q P & Q T T T T F F F T F F F F
16
Truth Functional Logic: The Basics
The operation of disjunction is represented by: P Q P V Q T T T T F T F T T F F F The operation of the conditional is represented by: P Q P -> Q T T T T F F F T T F F T
17
Using Truth Tables To Test Validity
Now, consider the following argument: Premise: If Paula goes to work, then Quincy and Rogers will get a day off. Conclusion: If Paula goes to work and Quincy gets a day off, then Rogers will get a day off. We symbolize the conclusion as (P & Q) -> R Thus, the argument is: P -> (Q & R) (P & Q) -> R Is this a valid argument?
18
Using Truth Tables To Test Validity
Is this a valid argument? We can determine whether or not it is by constructing a truth table that presents the premise(s) and conclusion. In this case, to do so we add to the previous truth table the necessary columns to represent the conclusion. P Q R Q&R P -> (Q & R) P & Q (P & Q) -> R T T T T T T T T T F F F T F T F T F F F T T F F F F F T F T T T T F T F T F F T F T F F T F T F T F F F F T F T Now, remembering the definition of a deductive argument, we look for a row in the table in which the premise(s) is true but the conclusion is not true. If we find one, the argument is invalid. If there is none, then the argument is valid.
19
Using Truth Tables To Test Validity
We can determine whether or not a deductive argument is valid or invalid by constructing a truth table that presents the premise(s) and conclusion. A deductive argument is valid when if the premises are true, the conclusion has to be true. Or in other words, an argument is valid if there are no possible states or conditions in which the premises are true and the conclusion is false. And, of course, a truth table represents all the possible states or conditions of the claims. Thus, an argument is valid when there are NO rows of the truth table in which the premise(s) are true and the conclusion is not true. If there is even one, the argument is invalid.
20
Consider the following argument:
P -> Q ~P _________ ~Q P Q T T T F F T F F Construct the appropriate truth table to include all possible t-f scenarios for all variables in the argument. If there are x (e.g. 2) variables, note that there with always be x (so in this case, 2) columns in the truth table at this point and there will be 2**x (or 2 to the x power) number of rows (in this case, 4). P1 P Q P->Q T T T T F F F T T F F T 2. Add a column to the truth table to express the first premise based on the truth tables for the basic operations. You may have to do this in multiple steps.
21
Consider the following argument:
P -> Q ~P _________ ~Q P P2 P Q P->Q ~P T T T F T F F F F T T T F F T T 3. For each remaining premise (there more may be more than one) add a column to the truth table to express the premise based on the truth tables for the basic operations. P P C P Q P->Q ~P ~Q T T T F F T F F F T F T T T F F F T T T 4. Add a column to the truth table to express the conclusion based on the truth tables for the basic operations. You may have to do steps #3 and #4 also in multiple steps.
22
Consider the following argument:
P -> Q ~P ______ ~Q P P C P Q P->Q ~P ~Q T T T F F T F F F T F T T T F F F T T T Ask yourself “Are there any rows in the truth table that I have just created in which all premises are true and the conclusion is false?” 6. If the answer is yes, then write “invalid.” If the answer is no, write “valid.” Invalid
23
Class Workshop: Exercise 10-4, #4. 23
24
Laziness is the Mother of Invention
However there is often an easier way to demonstrate validity with truth tables. It is called the short truth-table method. The basic principle of this method simply is to look for a row that makes the argument invalid. As soon as you find one, you are done. If you exhaust all opportunities and can’t, then the argument is valid. Consider the argument: P -> Q ~Q -> R ~P -> R The argument could be invalid only if the conclusion is false while the premises are true. P Q R F T F Thus, the argument is invalid.
25
Now, consider the argument:
(P v Q) -> R S -> Q S -> R The argument could be invalid only if the conclusion is false while the premises are true. To make the conclusion false -- P Q R S F T To make the second premise true -- T F T But there is no way now to make the first premise true, so the argument is valid.
26
Exercises 10-6 1. K -> (L & G) M -> (J & K) B & M B & G
To make the third premise true – B M T T But to make premise 2 true B M J K T T T T But to make premise 1 true, B M J K L G T T T T T T But there is no way now to make the conclusion false, so the argument is valid.
27
2. L v (W -> S) P v ~S ~L -> W P To make the conclusion false – P_ F But to make premise 2 true, P S F F But to make premise 1 true, we have to introduce additional rows. There are three ways compatible with the truth-table so far, such that L & W can be assigned so that premise 3 is true. P S L W (W->S) F F T T F *** F F T F T *** F F F F T *** The first two of these rows makes premise 3 true, so the argument is invalid.
28
Class Workshop (Short Method) Translation Exercise:
If Scarlet is guilty of the crime, then Ms. White must have left the back door unlocked and the colonel must have retired before ten o’clock. However, either Ms. White did not leave the back door unlocked, or the colonel did not retire before ten. Therefore, Scarlet is not guilty of the crime. Now, is is this valid? Look at page 302 for the long proof. Wow! Now, let’s be “lazy”…
29
Deductive Arguments: Rules of Induction
30
Deduction: Group 1 Rules
The basic valid argument patterns of deductive logic (If doubted, all the rules we discuss below can be confirmed by the truth-table method) is another method to prove a deductive argument (that is, to show that it is valid). Modus Ponens (MP) P -> Q P____ Q -- Affirming the antecedent P Q P->Q T T T T F F F T T F F T
31
Deduction: Group 1 Rules
Modus Tollens (MT) P -> Q ~Q____ ~P -- Denying the consequent
32
Deduction: Group 1 Rules
Okay, now that we have two rules to play with, let’s stop for a minute and see how we prove an argument valid using the rules. (P & Q) -> R S S -> ~R / .’. ~ ( P&Q) ~R 2,3, MP ~ (P & Q) 1,4, MT
33
Chain Argument (CA) P -> Q Q -> R____ P -> R Disjunctive Argument (DA) P v Q P v Q ~P ~Q__ Q P Simplification (SIM) P & Q P & Q P Q Conjunction (CONJ) P Q__ P & Q
34
Addition (ADD) P Q P v Q P v Q Constructive Dilemma (CD) P –> Q R -> S P v R Q v S Destructive Dilemma (DD) ~Q v ~S ~P v ~R
35
Exercises 9-10 #1 R -> P Q -> R / .’. Q -> P
Q -> P 1,2, CA #2 P -> S P v Q Q -> R / .’. S v R S v R 1,2,3, CD #10 (T v M) -> ~Q (P -> Q) & (R-> S) T / .’. ~P T v M 3, ADD ~ Q 1, 4, MP P -> Q 2, SIMP ~P 5, 6, MT
36
Class Workshop: Exercise 10-7, #1 & #2 36
Similar presentations
© 2024 SlidePlayer.com. Inc.
All rights reserved.