Presentation is loading. Please wait.

Presentation is loading. Please wait.

Metasemantics of Complex Expressions Michael Johnson Hong Kong University.

Similar presentations


Presentation on theme: "Metasemantics of Complex Expressions Michael Johnson Hong Kong University."— Presentation transcript:

1 Metasemantics of Complex Expressions Michael Johnson Hong Kong University

2 0. OUTLINE

3 Outline 0. Outline 1.Natural Language 2.The Language of Thought 3.The Direct Theory 4.Arguments for DT 5.Arguments against DT 6.Conclusion

4 1. NATURAL LANGUAGE

5 Compositionality Natural languages are compositional. What does that mean? Why should we care?

6 Computability I think those two questions are related: Natural languages are compositional in the sense that the meanings of complex NL expressions are computable from the meanings of their parts and the way that those parts are syntactically combined.

7 Understandability I think those two questions are related: We care about this claim regarding the compositionality of NLs, because only it (as opposed to other readings of compositional) explains how we can understand a potential infinitude of novel utterances, given our finite means (brains).

8 Note for the Savvy (Yes, I know computability compositionality, but you get the point…)

9 Interpretation (Finite Case) To understand a NL expression is to assign it a mental representation that shares its content. For the (finite) set of simple NL expressions we can understand them (assign them contents) via a lookup table that pairs each NL expression with a mental equivalent.

10 Interpretation: Infinite Case To understand a NL expression is to assign it a mental representation that shares its content. For the (infinite) set of complex NL expressions, we can understand them (assign them contents) by computing their contents from the contents assigned to their parts (& from their syntax), on the assumption that theyre compositional.

11 Example

12 Psychological Reality of Formal Semantics The general idea is that the sorts of ways we have of computing the meanings on paper are the same sorts of ways the mind goes about computing those things.

13 2. THE LANGUAGE OF THOUGHT

14 Interpreting Thoughts To understand a NL expression is to assign it a mental representation that shares its content. But this is not what it is to understand a thought (a mental representation).

15 Interpreting Thoughts We dont compute the meanings of our thoughts. We dont have to work out what were thinking. There are no garden path thoughts. We cant misinterpret our thoughts (wrong quantifier order, wrong meaning of BANK). To have a thought is to understand it.

16 The Infinite Regress If to understand a thought (mental representation) was to pair it with a distinct thought (mental representation) that had the same content as it, then either we wouldnt understand half our thoughts (the ones that interpreted the other half) or wed have an infinite number of thoughts (each of the interpreters would themselves be interpreted, and so on).

17

18 Understanding = Having To understand a thought is to think it, to have it, to token it. You neednt interpret it, translate it, or assign it a meaning.

19 No Regress And so even if LOT were compositional in the computational sense: That wouldnt be required by our ability to understand a potential infinitude of thoughts. If to understand a thought is to have it, then our ability to understand an infinite number of thoughts is explained by our ability to have an infinite number of them.

20 No Regress And so even if LOT were compositional in the computational sense: A recursive syntax gives us all we need to explain how we can have an infinite number of thoughts.

21 Compositionality New claim: LOT is compositional. What does that claim mean? Why should we care?

22 Metasemantics Heres a suggestion. Everyone agrees that an expressions having a meaning is not beyond the bounds of explanation. Expressions have meanings in virtue of certain facts that hold of them.

23 Compositionality as Metasemantics LOT is compositional = complex expressions of LOT have the contents they do in virtue of the contents their parts have, and the way those parts are syntactically combined. Compositionality, for LOT, solves the essence problem for the meaning relation (Carnap, Aufbau).

24 CMT Lets call the thesis that LOT is compositional in this sense compositionality as a metasemantic thesis. And lets also abbreviate compositionality as a metasemantic thesis to CMT.

25 3. THE DIRECT THEORY

26 Metasemantics But CMT is only one possible solution to the essence problem for the meaning relation (i.e. its only one possible metasemantic theory). That is, there are other possible answers to the question In virtue of what does a complex expression mean what it does, rather than something else, or nothing at all?

27 The Direct Approach For example, you might think that complex expressions get their meanings in the same way that simple ones do, however that is. Maybe the story is causal, or informational, or teleological, or inferential role-y, or real patterns-y, or whatever.

28 Contrast The contrast is this. CMT requires that complex expressions get their meanings in a different way from simple ones. They inherit their meanings from their constituents (compositionally), whereas simple expressions cant do this because, being simple, they have no constituents.

29 The Direct Theory For the purposes of this talk, Im going to assume that the correct metasemantic story for simple expressions is a broadly causal one (Stampe, Dretske, and Fodor are paradigm examples). For simplicitys sake, Ill often state the view as x means y in virtue of the fact that y appropriately causes x.

30 The Direct Theory And Im going to defend the claim that the same story applies to complex expressions. Ill call this claim the direct theory or DT, to contrast it with CMT, the inheritance theory, where complex expressions dont get their meanings directly, but inherit them from simple expressions that do.

31 4. ARGUMENTS FOR DT

32 Arguments For There are 4 basic considerations that tell in favor of DT: Its intuitively correct Its ontologically safe by virtue of its neutrality Its theoretically beautiful (uniform) Its non-arbitrary in an important way

33 Intuitive Correctness Suppose an agent has three mental representations A, B, and C. A is caused, appropriately, by artistic things B is caused, appropriately, by brown things C is caused, appropriately, by cow things

34 Intuitive Correctness Further suppose, though, that the complex expression ABC in the agent is caused, normally, not by artistic brown cow things, but by brown cow things of any aesthetic ability. Were inclined to think that ABC means brown cow, rather than artistic brown cow.

35 Intuitive Correctness CMT demands that ABC mean artistic brown cow. Thats what its parts, jointly, mean, and it inherits its meaning from its parts, jointly. DT gets the right answer. It says that ABC means what causes it, appropriately, which is in this instance brown cows. So it means brown cow.

36 Ontological Neutrality Suppose Krayzie Bone tells you he shot your homeboy foe tha sake of money.

37 Ontological Neutrality A lot of philosophers dont believe in sakes, they think theyre non-existent. But if thats true, sake means nothing; and so I shot x foe tha sake of money means nothing, if we hold to CMT.

38 Ontological Neutrality But if we endorse DT, we can say that the meaning of x shot y foe tha sake of money is true whenever the situations that appropriately cause tokenings of that expression obtain.

39 Ontological Neutrality This is so even if we assign sake a null content.

40 Local Uniformity Causal theories, in general, have a problem with causally isolated things, like numbers and numerical functions, abstract objects, logical relations, etc. If you think or means what causes or appropriately, then or doesnt mean disjunction, for disjunction causes nothing.

41 Local Uniformity However, you can maintain a causal theory for simple expressions by endorsing DT. If complex expressions get their meanings directly, then even if or does not mean disjunction, P or Q might still mean P or Q, in particular, if P or Q is appropriately caused by states where either P or Q obtain.

42 Local Uniformity Any non-standard meaning for the simple expression or doesnt percolate up to complex expressions involving it, because DT is a direct theory, not an inheritance theory. So long as dogs or cats appropriately cause dogs or cats the latter means the former, even if or means nothing, or something other than or.

43 Global Uniformity Also, if DT is true then (by definition) complex expressions get their meanings in the same way as simple expressions. There is only one theory of how expressions get their meanings. CMT is decidedly non-uniform: if its true, then complex expressions inherit their meanings, whereas simple expressions, obviously, dont.

44 Theoretical Beauty I think this is significant. If youre inclined towards a causal theory for some simple expressions (natural kind terms, for example), you have to have a different metasemantic theory for other simple expressions (or, for instance) unless you deny CMT.

45 Theoretical Beauty I think this is significant. And if you accept DT, you not only get to treat all simple expressions in the same way, you get to treat all complex expressions in the way you treat the simple ones. Thats true theoretical beauty if ever there was any.

46 Hocceity If youre a compositionalist, you have to decide how to compose meanings. For example, if brown means B = {x: x is brown} and cow means C = {x: x is a cow}, does brown cow mean the intersection of B and C, the union of them, the complement, the complement of the union…?

47 Hocceity If youre a compositionalist about language, you can just say that convention determines how syntactic combination relates to composition.

48 Hocceity But how does this work in the case of the mind? What your mental states mean is in no way conventional. Were inclined to say that brown cow means the intersection of B and C, because thats what causes brown cow. The extra degree of freedom is only resolved non-ad-hocly by assuming DT!

49 Summary DT gets the right intuitive results in cases of under- or overarticulation of constituents, as compared with CMT. Its intuitively correct. DT is ontologically neutral: it doesnt commit us to the parts of meaningful things themselves having meaning. As such, its ontologically safe, when compared with CMT.

50 Summary Causal theorists who deny DT have an unified metasemantics. They are even forced to deny that all simple expressions are causal. Accepting DT, on the other hand, is theoretically beautiful. Finally, composition rules for the mind are ad hoc, and a compositionalist can only discover them by assuming DT! DT is pro hoc.

51 ARGUMENTS AGAINST DT

52 Arguments Against There are three concerns I imagine you might have about accepting DT and rejecting CMT: Productivity Systematicity Intuitive incorrectness

53 Productivity If compositionality is false (for LOT) how do we produce and understand a potential infinitude of thoughts?

54 Productivity Production is easy. If you believe in LOT, thoughts are a type of sentences. How do you produce, potentially, infinitely many of them? By having a recursive syntax for LOT.

55 Understandability Understanding is easy too. As I noted before, to have a thought is to understand it. So how do you understand infinitely many thoughts? By producing infinitely many thoughts. And again, you do that with a recursive syntax for LOT.

56 Systematicity A language is systematic when expressions that have similar constituents in the language have similar meanings in that language. For example, in English, John loves Mary and Mary loves John have similar (identical even!) constituents and also have similar meanings (each meaning involves John, Mary, and loving).

57 Systematicity Fodor and Lepore (both jointly and separately) think that systematicity entails or at least guarantees in a very strong way compositionality.

58 Systematicity There are fancy things I can say, but Ill just say this one unfancy thing. The facts are that John loves Mary and Mary loves John have similar meanings. If DT assigns the correct meanings to those expressions, then it explains those facts. If it doesnt, then systematicity is not the issue: incorrectness is. If DT assigns radically unrelated meanings to M loves J and J loves M then it assigns the wrong meanings to them.

59 Systematicity But give me a case! Show me where DT violates systematicity!

60 Intuitive Incorrectness I argued previously that DT was intuitively correct whereas CMT was intuitively incorrect. But some data seems to go the other way.

61 Intuitive Incorrectness There are cases where we have some complex expression CE and the intuitive content (IC) of CE cant cause CE: IC is in the future of CEs tokening. IC is causally isolated. Tokeners of CE are insensitive to IC. Etc.

62 Examples IC = the world will end tomorrow. CE = the world will end tomorrow. IC = something is red and blue all over. CE = something is red and blue all over. IC = my son likes the Lakers. CE = my son likes the Lakers.

63 Intuitive Incorrectness But this has really nothing to do with DT vs. CMT (unlike, I should note, the cases I gave of CMTs intuitive incorrectness). These are just problems with causal theories of content. And they arise, identically, for causal theories of simple expressions.

64 Examples IC = futurity Simple expression = future IC = impossibility Simple expression = impossible IC = untokenability Simple expression = untokenable

65 Summary DT has no problem explaining how we produce and understand an infinite number of thoughts, given the equivalence of producing and understanding thoughts. And while it might have a problem with systematicity, this would really just amount to getting things wrong. But theres no evidence DT gets things wrong.

66 Summary OK, well maybe theres evidence that it gets things wrong, but its the same sort of evidence that causal theories of simple expressions get things wrong. We may have to fix our theories, but this isnt a motivation to abandon the direct approach.

67 CONCLUSION

68 Conclusion The main motivation for compositionality is learnability concerns. These dont exist for LOT. When compositionality is reinterpreted along the lines of CMT, we can see that other concerns like productivity, systematicity, etc. also have no tooth.

69 Conclusion DT is intuitively correct, ontologically safe, theoretically beautiful, and pro hoc. So Im right.


Download ppt "Metasemantics of Complex Expressions Michael Johnson Hong Kong University."

Similar presentations


Ads by Google