Presentation is loading. Please wait.

Presentation is loading. Please wait.

Making Simple Decisions Chapter 16 Some material borrowed from Jean-Claude Latombe and Daphne Koller by way of Marie desJadines,

Similar presentations


Presentation on theme: "Making Simple Decisions Chapter 16 Some material borrowed from Jean-Claude Latombe and Daphne Koller by way of Marie desJadines,"— Presentation transcript:

1 Making Simple Decisions Chapter 16 Some material borrowed from Jean-Claude Latombe and Daphne Koller by way of Marie desJadines,

2 Topics Decision making under uncertainty –Utility theory and rationality –Expected utility –Utility functions –Multiattribute utility functions –Preference structures –Decision networks –Value of information

3 Uncertain Outcomes of Actions Some actions may have uncertain outcomes –Action: spend $10 to buy a lottery which pays $1000 to the winner –Outcome: {win, not-win} Each outcome is associated with some merit (utility) –Win: gain $990 –Not-win: lose $10 There is a probability distribution associated with the outcomes of this action (0.0001, 0.9999). Should I take this action?

4 Expected Utility Random variable X with n values x 1,…,x n and distribution (p 1,…,p n ) –X is the outcome of performing action A (i.e., the state reached after A is taken) Function U of X –U is a mapping from states to numerical utilities (values) The expected utility of performing action A is EU[A] =  i=1,…,n p(x i |A)U(x i ) Expected utility of lottery: 0.0001*99 0– 0.9999*10 = – 9.9811 Utility of each outcome Probability of each outcome

5 s0s0 s3s3 s2s2 s1s1 A1 0.20.70.1 1005070 U(S0|A1) = 100 x 0.2 + 50 x 0.7 + 70 x 0.1 = 20 + 35 + 7 = 62 One State/One Action Example

6 s0s0 s3s3 s2s2 s1s1 A1 0.20.70.1 1005070 A2 s4s4 0.20.8 80 U1(S0|A1) = 62 U2(S0|A2) = 74 U(S0) = max{U1(S0|A1),U2(S0|A2)} = 74 One State/Two Actions Example

7 s0s0 s3s3 s2s2 s1s1 A1 0.20.70.1 1005070 A2 s4s4 0.20.8 80 U1(S0|A1) = 62 – 5 = 57 U2(S0|A2) = 74 – 25 = 49 U(S0) = max{U1(S0|A1),U2(S0|A2)} = 57 -5-25 Introducing Action Costs

8 MEU Principle Decision theory: A rational agent should choose the action that maximizes the agent’s expected utility Maximizing expected utility (MEU) is a normative criterion for rational choices of actions Must have complete model of: –Actions –States –Utilities Even if you have a complete model, will be computationally intractable

9 Comparing outcomes Which is better: A = Being rich and sunbathing where it’s warm B = Being rich and sunbathing where it’s cool C = Being poor and sunbathing where it’s warm D = Being poor and sunbathing where it’s cool Multiattribute utility theory –A clearly dominates B: A  > B. A > C. C > D. A > D. What about B vs. C? –Simplest case: Additive value function (just add the individual attribute utilities) –Others use weighted utility, based on the relative importance of these attributes –Learning the combined utility function (similar to joint prob. table)

10 Multiattribute Utility Theory A given state may have multiple utilities –...because of multiple evaluation criteria –...because of multiple agents (interested parties) with different utility functions 10

11 Decision networks Extend Bayesian nets to handle actions and utilities –a.k.a. influence diagrams Make use of Bayesian net inference Useful application: Value of Information

12 R&N example

13 Decision network representation Chance nodes: random variables, as in Bayesian nets Decision nodes: actions that decision maker can take Utility/value nodes: the utility of the outcome state.

14 Evaluating decision networks Set the evidence variables for the current state. For each possible value of the decision node (assume just one): –Set the decision node to that value. –Calculate the posterior probabilities for the parent nodes of the utility node, using BN inference. –Calculate the resulting utility for the action. Return the action with the highest utility.

15 Exercise: Umbrella network Weather Forecast Umbrella Happiness take/don’t take f w p(f|w) sunny rain 0.3 rainy rain 0.7 sunny no rain 0.8 rainy no rain 0.2 P(rain) = 0.4 U(lug, rain) = -25 U(lug, ~rain) = 0 U(~lug, rain) = -100 U(~lug, ~rain) = 100 Lug umbrella P(lug|take) = 1.0 P(~lug|~take)=1.0 EU(take) = U(lug, rain)*P(lug)*p(rain) + U(lug, ~rain)*P(lug)*p(~rain) = -25*0.4 + 0*P(~rain) = -25*0.4 = -10 EU(~take) = U(~lug, rain)*P(~lug)*p(rain) + U(~lug, ~rain)*P(~lug)*p(~rain) = -100*0.4 + 100*0.6 = 20

16 Umbrella network Weather Forecast Umbrella Happiness take/don’t take f w p(f|w) sunny rain 0.3 rainy rain 0.7 sunny no rain 0.8 rainy no rain 0.2 P(rain) = 0.4 U(lug, rain) = -25 U(lug, ~rain) = 0 U(~lug, rain) = -100 U(~lug, ~rain) = 100 Lug umbrella P(lug|take) = 1.0 P(~lug|~take)=1.0 Decision may be helped with forecast (additional information) D(F=Sunny) = Take D(F=Rainy) = Not_Take

17 Value of Perfect Information (VPI) How much is it worth to observe (with certainty) a random variable X? Suppose the agent’s current knowledge is E. The value of the current best action  is: EU(α | E) = max A ∑ i U(Result i (A)) p(Result i (A) | E, Do(A)) The value of the new best action after observing the value of X is: EU(α’ | E,X) = max A ∑ i U(Result i (A)) p(Result i (A) | E, X, Do(A)) …But we don’t know the value of X yet, so we have to sum over its possible values The value of perfect information for X is therefore: VPI(X) = ( ∑ k p(x k | E) EU(α xk | x k, E)) – EU (α | E) Probability of each value of X Expected utility of the best action given that value of X Expected utility of the best action if we don’t know X (i.e., currently)

18 Umbrella network Weather Forecast Umbrella Happiness take/don’t take f w p(f|w) sunny rain 0.3 rainy rain 0.7 sunny no rain 0.8 rainy no rain 0.2 P(rain) = 0.4 U(lug, rain) = -25 U(lug, ~rain) = 0 U(~lug, rain) = -100 U(~lug, ~rain) = 100 Lug umbrella P(lug|take) = 1.0 P(~lug|~take)=1.0 Decision may be helped with forecast (additional information) D(F=Sunny) = Take D(F=Rainy) = Not_Take

19 Exercise: Umbrella network f w p(f|w) sunny rain 0.3 rainy rain 0.7 sunny no rain 0.8 rainy no rain 0.2 p(rain|sunny) = 0.12 *5/3 = 0.2 p(~rain|sunny) = 0.48*5/3 = 0.8 Similarly, we have p(rain|rainy) = 0.12 *2.5 = 0.7 p(~rain|rainy) = 0.28*2.5 = 0.3 p(W|F) = α*p(F|W)*P(W) p(sunny|rain)*p(rain) = 0.3*0.4 = 0.12 P(sunny|~rain)*p(~rain) = 0.8*0.6 = 0.48 α = 1/(0.12+0.48) = 5/3 EU(take|f=sunny)) = -25*P(rain|sunny) + 0*P(~rain|sunny) = -25*0.2 = -5 EU(~take|f=sunny) = -100*0.2 + 100*0.8 = 60 a1 = ~take EU(take|f=rainy)) = -25*P(rain|rainy) + 0*P(~rain|rainy) = -25*0.7 = -17.5 EU(~take|f=rainy) = -100*0.7 + 100*0.3 = -40 a2 = take VPI(F) = 60*P(f=sunny) – 17.5*p(f=rainy) – 20 = 60*0.6 – 17.5*0.4 – 20 = 9 P(rain) = 0.4


Download ppt "Making Simple Decisions Chapter 16 Some material borrowed from Jean-Claude Latombe and Daphne Koller by way of Marie desJadines,"

Similar presentations


Ads by Google