Presentation is loading. Please wait.

Presentation is loading. Please wait.

The Structure of Networks

Similar presentations


Presentation on theme: "The Structure of Networks"— Presentation transcript:

1 The Structure of Networks
with emphasis on information and social networks Game Theory: Chapter 6&7 Ýmir Vigfússon

2 Mixed strategies Do Nash equilibria always exist?
Matching Pennies game Player #1 wins if mismatch, #2 if match Example of a zero-sum game What one player gains, the other loses E.g. Allied landing in Europe on June 6, 1944 How would you play this game? Heads Tails -1, +1 +1, -1

3 Mixed strategies You randomize your strategy
Instead of choosing H/T directly, choose a probability you will choose H. Player 1 commits to play H with some probability p Similarly, player 2 plays H with probability q This is called a mixed strategy As opposed to a pure strategy (e.g. p=0) What about the payoffs?

4 Mixed strategies Suppose player 1 evaluates pure strategies
Player 2 meanwhile chooses strategy q If Player 1 chooses H, he gets a payoff of -1 with probability q and +1 with probability 1-q If Player 1 chooses T, he gets -1 with probability 1-q and +1 with probability q Is H or T more appealing to player 1? Rank the expected values Pick H: expect (-1)(q) + (+1)(1-q) = 1-2q Pick T: expect (+1)(q) + (-1)(1-q) = 2q -1

5 Mixed strategies Def: Nash equilibrium for mixed strategies
A pair of strategies (now probabilities) such that each is a best response to the other. Thm: Nash proved that this always exists. In Matching Pennies, no Nash equilibrium can use a pure strategy Player 2 would have a unique best response which is a pure strategy But this is not the best response for player 1... What is Player 1‘s best response to strategy q? If 1-2q ≠2q-1, then a pure strategy (either H or T) is a unique best response to player 1. This can‘t be part of a Nash equilibrium by the above So must have 1-2q=2q-1 in any Nash equilibrium Which gives q=1/2. Similarly p=1/2 for Player 1. This is a unique Nash equilibrium (check!)

6 Mixed strategies Intuitively, mixed strategies are used to make it harder for the opponent to predict what will be played By setting q=1/2, Player 2 makes Player 1 indifferent between playing H or T. How do we interpret mixed equilibria? In sports (or real games) Players are indeed randomizing their actions Competition for food among species Individuals are hardwired to play certain strategies Mixed strategies are proportions within populations Population as a whole is a mixed equilibrium Nash equilibrium is an equilibrium in beliefs If you believe other person will play a Nash equilibrium strategy, so will you. It is self-reinforcing – an equilibrium

7 Mixed strategies: Examples
American football Offense can run with the ball, or pass forward What happens? Suppose the defense defends against a pass with probability q P: expect (0)(q) + (10)(1-q) = 10-10q R: expect (5)(q) + (0)(1-q) = 5q Offense is indifferent when q=2/3 Defend run Defend pass Pass 0, 0 10, -10 Run 5, -5

8 Mixed strategies: Examples
American football Offense can run with the ball, or pass forward What happens? Suppose offense passes with probability p Similarly, defense is indifferent when p=1/3 (1/3,2/3) is a Nash equilibrium Expected payoff to offense: 10/3 (yard gain) Defend run Defend pass Pass 0, 0 10, -10 Run 5, -5

9 Mixed strategies: Examples
Penalty-kick game Soccer penalties have been studied extensively Suppose goalie defends left with probability q Kicker indifferent when (0.58)(q) + (0.95) (1-q) = (0.93)(q) + (0.70) (1-q) Get q =0.42. Similarly p=0.39 True values from data? q=0.42 , p=0.40 !! The theory predicts reality very well Defend left Defend right Left 0.58, -0.58 0.95, -0.95 Right 0.93, -0.93 0.70, -0.70

10 Pareto optimality Even playing best responses does not always reach a good outcome as a group E.g. prisoner‘s dilemma Want to define a socially good outcome Def: A choice of strategies is Pareto optimal if no other choice of strategies gives all players a payoff at least as high, and at least one player gets a strictly higher payoff Note: Everyone must do at least as well

11 Social optimality Def: Example:
A choice of strategies is a social welfare maximizer (or socially optimal) if it maximizes the sum of the players‘ payoffs. Example: The unique Nash equilibrium in this game is socially optimal Presentation Exam 98,98 94,96 96,94 92,92

12 Game theory Regular game theory Evolutionary game theory
Individual players make decisions Payoffs depend on decisions made by all The reasoning about what other players might do happens simultaneously Evolutionary game theory Game theory continues to apply even if no individual is overtly reasoning or making explicit decisions Decisions may thus not be conscious What behavior will persist in a population?

13 Background Evolutionary biology
The idea that an organism‘s genes largely determine its observable characteristics (fitness) in a given environment More fit organisms will produce more offspring This causes genes that provide greater fitness to increase their representation in the population Natural selection

14 Evolutionary game theory
Key insight Many behaviors involve the interaction of multiple organisms in a population The success of an organism depends on how its behavior interacts with that of others Can‘t measure fitness of an individual organism So fitness must be evaluated in the context of the full population in which it lives Analogous to game theory! Organisms‘s genetically determined characteristics and behavior = Strategy Fitness = Payoff Payoff depends on strategies of organisms with which it interacts = Game matrix

15 Motivating example Let‘s look at a species of a beetle
Each beetle‘s fitness depends on finding and processing food effectively Mutation introduced Beetles with mutation have larger body size Large beetles need more food What would we expect to happen? This makes them less fit for the environment The mutation will thus die out over time But there is more to the story...

16 Motivating example Beetles compete with each other for food
Large beetles more effective at claiming above-average share of the food Assume food competition is among pairs Same sized beetles get equal shares of food A large beetle gets the majority of food from a smaller beetle Large beetles always experience less fitness benefit from given quantity of food Need to maintain their expensive metabolism

17 Motivating example The body-size game between two beetles
Something funny about this No beetle is asking itself: “Do I want to be small or large?“ Need to think about strategy changes that operate over longer time scales Taking place as shifts in population under evolutionary forces Small Large 5, 5 1, 8 8, 1 3, 3

18 Evolutionary stable strategies
The concept of a Nash equilibrium doesn‘t work in this setting Nobody is changing their personal strategy Instead, we want an evolutionary stable strategy A genetically determined strategy that tends to persist once it is prevalent in a population Need to make this precise...

19 Evolutionarily stable strategies
Suppose each beatle is repeatedly paired off with other beetles at random Population large enough so that there are no repeated interactions between two beetles A beetle‘s fitness = average fitness from food interactions = reproductive success More food thus means more offspring to carry genes (strategy) to the next generation Def: A strategy is evolutionarily stable if everyone uses it, and any small group of invaders with a different strategy will die off over multiple generations

20 Evolutionarily stable strategies
Def: More formally Fitness of an organism in a population = expected payoff from interaction with another member of population Strategy T invades a strategy S at level x (for small x) if: x fraction of population uses T 1-x fraction of population uses S Strategy S is evolutionarily stable if there is some number y such that: When any other strategy T invades S at any level x < y, the fitness of an organism playing S is strictly greater than the fitness of an organism playing T

21 Motivating example Is Small an evolutionarily stable strategy?
Let‘s use the definition Suppose for some small number x, a 1-x fraction of population use Small and x use Large In other words, a small invader population of Large beetles What is the expected payoff to a Small beetle in a random interaction? With prob. 1-x, meet another Small beetle for a payoff of 5 With prob. x, meet Large beetle for a payoff of 1 Expected payoff: 5(1-x) + 1x = 5-4x

22 Motivating example Is Small an evolutionarily stable strategy?
Let‘s use the definition Suppose for some small number x, a 1-x fraction of population use Small and x use Large In other words, a small invader population of Large beetles What is the expected payoff to a Large beetle in a random interaction? With prob. 1-x, meet a Small beetle for payoff of 8 With prob. x, meet another Large beetle for a payoff of 3 Expected payoff: 8(1-x) + 3x = 8-5x

23 Motivating example Expected fitness of Large beetles is 8-5x
Expected fitness of Small beetles is 5-4x For small enough x (and even big x), the fitness of Large beetles exceeds the fitness for Small Thus Small is not evolutionarily stable What about the Large strategy? Assume x fraction are Small, rest Large. Expected payoff to Large: 3(1-x) + 8x = 3+5x Expected payoff to Small: 1(1-x) + 5x = 1+4x Large is evolutionarily stable

24 Motivating example Summary
A few large beetles introduced into a population consisting of small beetles Large beetles will do really well: They rarely meet each other They get most of the food in most competitions Population of small beetles cannot drive out the large ones So Small is not evolutionarily stable

25 Motivating example Summary The structure is like prisoner‘s dilemma
Conversely, a few small beetles will do very badly They will lose almost every competition for food A population of large beetles resists the invasion of small beetles Large is thus evolutionarily stable The structure is like prisoner‘s dilemma Competition for food = arms race Beetles can‘t change body sizes, but evolutionarily forces over multiple generations are achieving analogous effect

26 Motivating example Even more striking feature!
Start from a population of small beetles Evolution by natural selection is causing the fitness of the organisms to decrease over time Does this contradict Darwin‘s theory? Natural selection increases fitness in a fixed environment Each beetle‘s environment includes all other beetles The environment is thus changing It is becoming increasingly more hostile for everyone This naturally decreases the fitness of the population

27 Evolutionary arms races
Lots of examples Height of trees follows prisoner‘s dilemma Only applies to a particular height range More sunlight offset by fitness downside of height Roots of soybean plants to claim resources Conserve vs. Explore Hard to truly determine payoffs in real- world settings

28 Evolutionary arms races
One recent example with known payoffs Virus populations can play an evolutionary version of prisoner‘s dilemma Virus A Infects bacteria Manifactures products required for replication Virus B Mutated version of A Can replicate inside bacteria, but less efficiently Benefits from presence of A Is B evolutionarily stable?

29 Virus game Look at interactions between two viruses
Viruses in a pure A population do better than viruses in pure B population But regardless of what other viruses do, higher payoff to be B Thus B is evolutionarily stable Even though A would have been better Similar to the exam-presentation game A B 1.00, 1.00 0.65, 1.99 1.99, 0.65 0.83, 0.83

30 What happens in general?
Under what conditions is a strategy evolutionarily stable? Need to figure out the right form of the payoff matrix How do we write the condition of evolutionary stability in terms of these 4 variables, a,b,c,d? Organism 2 S T a, a b, c c, b d, d Organism 1

31 What happens in general?
Look at the definition again Suppose again that for some small number x: A 1-x fraction of the population uses S An x fraction of the population uses T What is the payoff for playing S in a random interaction in the population? Meet another S with prob. 1-x. Payoff = a Meet T with prob. x. Payoff = b Expected payoff = a(1-x)+bx Analogous for playing T Expected payoff = c(1-x)+dx

32 What happens in general?
Therefore, S is evolutionarily stable if for all small values of x: a(1-x)+bx > c(1-x)+dx When x is really small (goes to 0), this is a > c When a=c, the left hand side is larger when b > d In other words In a two-player, two-strategy symmetric game, S is evolutionarily stable precisely when either a > c, or a = c, and b > d

33 What happens in general?
Intuition In order for S to be evolutionarily stable, then: Using S against S must be at least as good as using T against S Otherwise, an invader using T would have higher fitness than the rest of the population If S and T are equally good responses to S S can only be evolutionarily stable if those who play S do better against T than what those who play T do with each another Otherwise, T players would do as well against the S part of the population as the S players

34 Relationship with Nash equilibria
Let‘s look at Nash in the symmetric game When is (S,S) a Nash equilibrium? S is a best response to S: a ≥ c Compare with evolutionarily stable strategies: (i) a > c or (ii) a = c and b > d Very similar! S T a, a b, c c, b d, d

35 Relationship with Nash equilibria
We get the following conclusion Thm: If strategy S is evolutionary stable, then (S,S) is a Nash equilibrium Does the other direction hold? What if a = c, and b < d? Can we construct such an example?

36 From last time Stag Hunt Two equilibria, but “riskier“ to hunt stag
If hunters work together, they can catch a stag On their own they can each catch a hare If one hunter tries for a stag, he gets nothing Two equilibria, but “riskier“ to hunt stag What if other player hunts hare? Get nothing Similar to prisoner‘s dilemma Must trust other person to get best outcome! Hunt Stag Hunt Hare 4, 4 0, 3 3, 0 3, 3

37 Counterexample Modify the game a bit Want: a = c, and b < d 4, 4
Hunt Stag Hunt Hare 4, 4 0, 3 3, 0 3, 3 S T a, a b, c c, b d, d

38 Counterexample Modify the game a bit Want: a = c, and b < d
We‘re done! Hunt Stag Hunt Hare 4, 4 0, 4 4, 0 3, 3 S T a, a b, c c, b d, d

39 Relationship with Nash equilibria
We get the following conclusion: Thm: If strategy S is evolutionarily stable, then (S,S) is a Nash equilibrium Does the other direction hold? Won‘t hold if some game has a = c, and b < d Can we construct such an example? Yes! However! Look at a strict Nash equilibrium The condition gives a > c Thm: If (S,S) is a strict Nash equilibrium, then strategy S is evolutionarily stable The equilibrium concepts refine one another

40 Summary Nash equilibrium Evolutionarily stable strategies
Rational players choosing mutual best responses to each other‘s strategy Great demands on the ability to choose optimally and coordinate on strategies that are best responses to each other Evolutionarily stable strategies No intelligence or coordination Strategies hard-wired into players (genes) Successful strategies produce more offspring Yet somehow they are almost the same!

41 Mixed strategies It may be the case that no strategy is evolutionarily stable The Hawk-Dove game is an example Hawk does well in all-Dove population Dove does well in population of all Hawks The game even has two Nash equilibria! We introduced mixed strategies to study this phenomenon How should we define this in our setting?

42 Mixed strategies Suppose: Expected payoff for organism 1 In total:
Organism 1 plays S with probability p Plays T with probability 1-p Organism 2 plays S with probability q Plays T with probability 1-q Expected payoff for organism 1 Probability pq of (S,S) pairing, giving a Probability p(1-q) of (S,T) pairing, giving b Probability (1-p)q of (T,S) pairing, giving c Probability p(1-q) of (T,T) pairing, giving d In total: V(p,q) = pqa+p(1-q)b+(1-p)qc+(1-p)(1-q)d

43 Mixed strategies Fitness of an organism = expected payoff in a random interaction More precisely: Def: p is an evolutionary stable mixed strategy if there is a small positive number y s.t. when any other mixed strategy q invades p at any level x<y, then the fitness of an organism playing p is strictly greater than the fitness of an organism playing q

44 Mixed strategies Let‘s dig into this condition
p is an evolutionarily stable mixed strategy if: For some y and any x < y, the following holds for all mixed strategies q ≠ p: (1-x)V(p,p) + xV(p,q) > (1-x)V(q,p) + xV(q,q) This parallels what we saw earlier for mixed Nash equilibria If p is an evolutionarily stable mixed strategy then V(p,p) ≥ V(q,p), Thus p is a best response to q So (p,p) is a mixed Nash equilibrium

45 Example: Hawk-Dove See book

46 Interpretation Can interpret this in two ways
All participants in the population are mixing over two possible pure strategies with given probability Members genetically the same Population level: 1/3 of animals hard-wired to play D and 2/3 are hard-wired to always play H


Download ppt "The Structure of Networks"

Similar presentations


Ads by Google