Download presentation
1
16.4 Competitive Market Efficiency
Pareto Efficient No alternate allocation of inputs and goods makes one consumer better off without hurting another consumer If another allocation improves AT LEAST ONE CONSUMER (without making anyone else worse off), the first allocation was Pareto Inefficient.
2
16.4 Competitive Market Efficiency
Pareto Efficiency has three requirements: Exchange Efficiency Goods cannot be traded to make a consumer better off 2) Input Efficiency Inputs cannot be rearranged to produce more goods
3
16.4 Competitive Market Efficiency
3) Substitution Efficiency Substituting one good for another will not make one consumer better off without harming another consumer
4
1) Exchange Efficiency Model Assumptions
2 people 2 goods, each of fixed quantity This allows us to construct an EDGEWORTH BOX – a graph showing all the possible allocations of goods in a two-good economy, given the total available supply of each good
5
1) Edgeworth Box Example
Two people: Maka and Susan Two goods: Food (f) & Video Games (V) We put Maka on the origin, with the y-axis representing food and the x axis representing video games If we connect a “flipped” graph of Susan’s goods, we get an EDGEWORTH BOX, where y is all the food available and x is all the video games:
6
1) Maka’s Goods Graph Food Video Games Ou is Maka’s food, and Ox
is Maka’s Video Games u Food O x Maka Video Games
7
1) Edgeworth Box Food Video Games Susan y O’
O’w is Susan’s food, and O’y is Susan’s Video Games r Total food in the market is Or(=O’s) and total Video Games is Os (=O’r) u Food w Each point in the Edgeworth Box represents one possible good allocation O x s Maka Video Games
8
1) Edgeworth and utility
We can then add INDIFFERENCE curves to Maka’s graph (each curve indicating all combinations of goods with the same utility) Curves farther from O have a greater utility We can then superimpose Susan’s utility curves Curves farther from O’ have a greater utility Remember that:
9
1) Maka’s Utility Curves
Maka’s utility is greatest at M3 Food M3 M2 M1 O Maka Video Games
10
1) Edgeworth Box and Utility
Susan O’ Susan has the highest utility at S3 r S1 S2 A S3 At point A, Maka has utility of M3 and Susan has Utility of S2 Food M3 M2 M1 O s Maka Video Games
11
1) Edgeworth Box and Utility
Susan O’ If consumption is at A, Maka has utility M1 while Susan has utility S3 r A B S3 C By moving to point B and then point C, Maka’s utility increases while Susan’s remains constant Food M3 M2 M1 O s Maka Video Games
12
1) Exchange Efficiency Food Video Games Susan O’
Point C, where the indifference curves barely touch is EXCHANGE EFFICIENT, as one person can’t be made better off without harming the other. r S3 C Food M3 M2 M1 O s Maka Video Games
13
1) Pareto Improvement When an allocation is NOT exchange efficient, it is wasteful (at least one person could be made better off)… A PARETO IMPROVEMENT makes one person better off without making anyone else worth off (like the move from A to C)… However, there may be more than one pareto improvement:
14
1) Pareto Improvements Food Video Games Susan O’
If we start at point A: -C is a pareto improvement that makes Maka better off -D is a pareto improvement that makes Susan better off -E is a pareto improvement that makes both better off r A S3 C S4 Food S5 E M3 M2 D M1 O s Maka Video Games
15
1) The Contract Curve Assuming all possible starting points, we can find all possible exchange efficient points and join them to create a CONTRACT CURVE All along the contract curve, opposing indifferent curves are TANGENT to each other Since each individual maximizes where his indifference curve is tangent to his budget line:
16
1) The Contract Curve Susan O’ r Food O s Maka Video Games
17
1) Example: House and Chase
Assume that House and Chase have the following utilities for books and coffee: The Exchange Efficiency Condition therefore becomes:
18
1) MATH – House and Chase If there are 10 books, and 4 cups of coffee, then the contract curve is expressed as: If House has 6 books, an exchange efficient allocation would be:
19
1) MATH – House and Chase Therefore, House would have 6 books and 2.4 cups of coffee, and Chase would have 4 (10-6) books and 1.6 (4-2.4) cups of coffee, for utilities of:
20
2) Input Efficiency Model Assumptions
2 producers/firms 2 inputs (Labor and Capital), each of fixed quantity This lead to a EDGEWORTH BOX FOR INPUTS– a graph showing all the possible allocations of fixed quantities of labor and capital between two producers
21
2) Edgeworth Box For Inputs Example
Two firms: Apple and Google Two inputs: Labor (L) and capital (K) We put Apple the origin, with the y-axis representing capital and the x axis representing labor If we connect a “flipped” graph of Google’s inputs, we get an EDGEWORTH BOX FOR INPUTS, where y is all the capital available and x is all the labor:
22
2) Apple’s Input Graph Capital Labor
Ou is Apple’s capital, and Ox is Apple’s labor. u Capital O x Apple Labor
23
2) Edgeworth Box For Inputs
Google y O’ O’w is Google’s capital, and O’y is Google’s labor r Total capital in the market is Or(=O’s) and total labor is Os (=O’r) u Capital w Each point in the Edgeworth Box represents one possible input allocation O x s Apple Labor
24
2) Edgeworth and Production
We can then add ISOQUANT curves to APPLE’s graph (each curve indicating all combinations of inputs producing the same output) Curves farther from O produce more We can then superimpose Google’s Isoquants Curves farther from O’ produce more Remember that the slope of the Isoquant is MRTS and:
25
2) Apple’s Isoquants Capital Labor Apple produces the most at A3 A3 A2
26
2) Edgeworth Box for Inputs
Google O’ Google produces the most at G3 r G1 G2 A G3 At point A, Apple makes A3 Google produces G2 Capital A3 A2 A1 O s Apple Labor
27
2) Edgeworth Box and Utility
Google O’ If production is at A, Apple produces A1 while Google produces G3 r A B G3 C By moving to point B and then point C, Apple produces more while Google’s production remains constant Capital A3 A2 A1 O s Apple Labor
28
2) Input Efficiency Capital Labor Google O’
Point C, where the isoquant curves barely touch is INPUT EFFICIENT, as one firm can’t produce more without the other firm producing less. r G3 C Capital A3 A2 A1 O s Apple Labor
29
2) Pareto Improvement When an input allocation is NOT input efficient, it is wasteful (at least one firm COULD produce more)… A PARETO IMPROVEMENT allows one firm to produce more without reducing the output of the other firm(like the move from A to C) However, there may be more than one pareto improvement:
30
2) Pareto Improvements Capital Labor Google O’ If we start at point A:
-C is a pareto improvement where Apple produces more -D is a pareto improvement where Google produces more -E is a pareto improvement where both firms produce more r A G3 C G4 Capital G5 E A3 A2 D A1 O s Apple Labor
31
2) Input Contract Curve Similar to the goods market, a contract curve can be derived in the input market: All along the contract curve, opposing isoquant curves are TANGENT to each other Since each firm maximizes where their isoquant curve is tangent to their isocost line:
32
2) Input Contract Curve Google O’ r Capital O s Apple Labor
33
2) Example: Apple and Google
Assume that Apple and Google have the following production functions: The Exchange Efficiency Condition therefore becomes:
34
The isoquant slope for Apple is:
35
The isoquant slope for Google is:
36
2) MATH – Apple and Google
If there are 1000 workers, and 125 capital in Silicon valley, then the contract curve is expressed as:
37
2) MATH – Apple and Google
Is the market input efficient if Apple has 200 workers and 50 capital? No – Apple needs fewer capital (Google needs more capital) AND/OR Google needs fewer workers (Apple needs more workers)
38
3) Substitution Efficiency
Substitution Efficiency can be analyzed using the PRODUCTION POSSIBILITIES CURVE/FRONTIER The PPC shows all combinations of 2 goods that can be produced using available inputs The slope of the PPC shows how much of one good must be SUBSTITUTED to produce more of the other good, or MARGINAL RATE OF TRANSFORMATION (x for y) (MRTxy)
39
Production Possibilities Curve
Here the MRTSpr is equal to (7-5)/(2-1)=-2, or two robots must be given up for an extra pizza. 10 9 8 The marginal cost of the 3rd pizza, or MCp=2 robots 7 6 The marginal cost of the 6th and 7th robots, or MCr=1 pizza Robots 5 4 Therefore, MRTxy=MCx/MCy 3 2 Therefore, MRTpr=2/1=2 1 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 Pizzas
40
3) Substitution Efficiency and Production
If production is possible in an economy, the Pareto efficiency condition becomes: Assume MRTpr=3 and MRSpr=2. -Therefore Maka could get 3 more robots by transforming 1 pizza -BUT Maka would exchange 2 robots for 1 pizzas to maintain utility -Therefore 1 pizza is sacrificed for 3 robots, increasing Maka’s utility through the 3rd robot -The Market isn’t Pareto Efficient
41
The First Fundamental Theorem Of Welfare Economics
IF All consumers and producers act as perfect competitors (no one has market power) and 2) A market exists for each and every commodity Then Resource allocation is Pareto Efficient
42
First Fundamental Theorem of Welfare Economics Proof:
From microeconomic consumer theory, we know that: Since prices are the same for all people: Therefore perfect competition leads to exchange efficiency
43
First Fundamental Theorem of Welfare Economics Proof:
From microeconomic theory of the firm, we know that: Since each firm in an industry faces the same wages and rents: Perfect competition leads to input efficiency
44
First Fundamental Theorem of Welfare Economics Origins
From the PPF, we know that Therefore a perfectly competitive market is Pareto Efficient:
45
Efficiency≠Fairness Government would exist to protect property rights
If Pareto Efficiency was the only concern, competitive markets automatically achieve it and there would be very little need for government: Government would exist to protect property rights Laws, Courts, and National Defense But Pareto Efficiency doesn’t consider distribution. One person could get all society’s resources while everyone else starves. This isn’t typically socially optimal.
46
Fairness Food Video Games Susan O’ r
Points A and B are Pareto efficient, but either Susan or Maka get almost all society’s resources B C Food A Many would argue C is better for society, even though it is not Pareto efficient O s Maka Video Games
47
Fairness For each utility level of one person, there is a maximum utility of the other Graphing each utility against the other gives us the UTILITY POSSIBILITIES CURVE:
48
Utility Possibilities Curve
All points on the curve are Pareto efficient, while all points below the curve are not. Any point above the curve is unobtainable B Maka’s Utility C A O Maka Susan’s Utility
49
Fairness Typical utility is a function of goods consumed: U=f(x,y)
Societal utility can be seen as a function of individual utilities: W=f(U1,U2) This is the SOCIAL WELFARE FUNCTION, and can produce SOCIAL INDIFFERENCE CURVES:
50
Typical Social Indifference Curves
An indifference curve farther from the origin represents a higher level of social welfare. Maka’s Utility O Maka Susan’s Utility
51
Fairness If we superimpose social indifference curves on top of the utilities possibilities curve, we can find the Pareto efficient point that maximizes social welfare This leads us to the SECOND FUNDAMENTAL THEOREM OF WELFARE ECONOMICS
52
Maximizing Social Welfare
ii is preferred to i, even though ii is not Pareto efficient i ii The highest possible social welfare, iii, is Pareto efficient Maka’s Utility iii O Maka Susan’s Utility
53
Second Fundamental Theorem of Welfare Economics
The SECOND FUNDAMENTAL THEOREM OF WELFARE ECONOMICS states that: Society can attain any Pareto efficient allocation of resources by: 1) making a suitable assignments of original endowments, and then 2) letting people trade
54
Second Fundamental Theorem of Welfare Economics
Susan O’ r By redistributing income, society can pick the starting point in the Edgeworth box, therefore obtaining a desired point on the Utility Possibility Frontier: Starting Point Goal Food O s Maka Video Games
55
Why Is Government so Big?
Government has to ensure property laws are protected. (1st Theorem) Government has to redistribute income to achieve equity. (2nd Theorem) Often the assumptions of the First Welfare Theorem do not hold (Econ 350)
56
Why Trade and Not Tax? Taxes and penalties punish income-enhancing behavior, encouraging people to work less. Subsidies and incentives give an incentive to stay in a negative state to keep receiving subsidies and incentives. Lump sum transfers have the least distortion, AND TRADE ALWAYS BENEFITS BOTH PARTIES…
57
16.5 Gains From Free Trade Trade ALWAYS makes society better off by increasing the productivity of scarce resources The basis for the gains from specialization and trade is Comparative Advantage
58
Theory of Comparative Advantage:
Production Possibilities : Carl and Mike: retired neighbours: hobbies are making wine and beer PPF’s for 1 month’s production: Carl’s Production Possibilities Mike’s Production A B C Wine (btls) Beer (btls.) ,
59
Carl’s Proposition “Lets each of us do what we do best and trade. This will give each of us more than we now have without either of us working any harder.” Notice that voluntary trade does not take place unless both parties benefit.
60
Mike’s Production Possibilities/ Opportunity Costs
Bottles of beer In a month Mike can produce either 80 bottles of wine or 80 bottles of beer Opp cost of 80 wine is 80 beer Opp cost of 1 wine is 1 beer Opp cost of 80 beer is 80 wine Opp cost of 1 beer is 1 wine • A B Consumption choice before trade 80 • C 40 • Bottles of wine 40 80
61
Carl’s Production Possibilities/ Opportunity Costs
Opp cost 100 wine is 1000 beer Opp Cost 1 wine is 10 beer Opp cost of 1000 beer is 100 wine Opp Cost 1 beer is 1/10 wine Bottles of beer • A 100 B Consumption choice before trade • 700 C • 30 100 Bottles of wine
62
Opportunity Cost Table
Theory of Comparative Advantage: When producer A has a lower opportunity cost of producing good A compared to another producer, then producer A is said to have a comparative advantage in the production of good A. Opportunity Cost Table Opportunity cost of 1 beer Opportunity cost of 1 wine Carl 1/10 wine 10 beer Mike 1 wine 1 beer
63
Comparative Advantage: Specialization
Carl has a “comparative advantage” (lowest opportunity cost producer) in the production of beer and therefore specializes in beer production. Mike has a “comparative advantage” in the production of wine and therefore specializes in wine production As long as opportunity costs differ, there is comparative advantage
64
Comparative Advantage: Specialization
Theory of Comparative Advantage if specialization takes place according to comparative advantage (the lowest opportunity cost producer) and then trade takes place…. both parties can benefit: that is, move outside their current PPF’s.
65
Carl & Mike Before Specialization & Trade
Carl Produces & Consumes Mike Produces & Consumes Total Consumption + = Wine (btls.) Beer (btls.) 30 700 40 70 740 Carl & Mike After Specialization, but Before Trade Mike Produces & Can Consume + = Wine (btls.) Beer (btls.) 1,000 80 Carl Produces & Can Consume Total Production & Consumption Total Gains +10 +260
66
(terms of trade: 5 beer for 1 wine)
Trade: The Benefits of Specialization Carl proposes, after specialization, that he trade Mike 175 beer for 35 wine. (terms of trade: 5 beer for 1 wine) Carl gets wine for a reduced sacrifice 35 wine for 175 beer instead of 350 beer, the opportunity cost before trade Mike gets beer for a reduced sacrifice 175 beer for 35 wine instead of 175 wine, the opportunity cost before trade
67
Terms of Trade: 1 Wine for 5 Beer
Since voluntary trade requires that both parties benefit from the trade. Before trade: Carl: 1 wine “trades” for 10 beer Mike: 1 wine trades for 1 beer Carl is better off as he now only has to give up 5 beer for a wine After trade 1 wine “trades” for 5 beer Mike is better off as he now only has to give up 1/5 wine for a beer The Terms of Trade are between the personal ones that exist before trade, thus producing gains for both parties participating in the trade
68
Trade Between Carl & Mike
175 Bottles of Beer To Trades away 1 Wine trades for 5 Beer or 1 Beer trades for 1/5 Wine Mike (specializes in wine) Carl (specializes in beer) 35 Bottles of Wine Trades away To Before trade Mike gave up 1 wine to get 1 beer, after trade1/5 wine Before trade Carl gave up 10 beer to get a wine, after trade 5 beer
69
Carl & Mike After Specialization & Trade
Trades For (+) Away (-) Consumes After Trade Produced & Consumed Before Trade Gains from Trade Produces Wine (btls.) Beer (btls.) 1,000 +35 -175 35 825 30 700 +5 +125 Mike Trades For (+) Away (-) Consumes After Trade Produced & Consumed Before Trade Gains from Trade Produces Wine (btls.) Beer (btls.) 80 -35 +175 45 175 40 +5 +135
70
Mike’s Production Possibilities After Trade
Bottles of beer Mike produces 80 wine and then trades 35 wine for 175 beer, leaving him with 45 wine and 175 beer, point D • D Consumption after trade 175 • A B 80 • C 40 • Bottles of wine 40 45 80
71
Carl’s Production Possibilities/ Opportunity Costs, After Trade
Bottles of beer Carl produces 1000 beer and trades 175 beer to Mike for 35 wine, leaving him with 825 beer and 35 beer, point D • A 100 D • Consumption after trade 825 B • 700 C • 30 35 100 Bottles of wine
72
Absolute Advantage When a producer with of set of inputs can produce more output than another with the same inputs, the first producer has an absolute advantage in production of the output. Carl has an absolute advantage in the production of both wine and beer.
73
Gains from Specialization and Trade
Specialization produces gains for both traders, even when one trader enjoys an absolute advantage in both endeavors. Unless two people/firms/countries have IDENTICAL opportunity costs, Trade is always beneficial
74
Why No Free Trade? Misunderstanding: people misunderstand the facts or hold to political or ideological dogma, or confuse voluntary jobs with enforced slavery Short-run effects: in the SHORT-RUN, there may be some unpopular adjustments: Richer, developed countries may lose jobs to developing countries with a comparative advantage Poorer, developing countries may have short-run environmental damage until the higher incomes lead to environmental protection
75
Chapter 16 Conclusions General equilibrium requires simultaneous equilibrium in multiple markets One change can cause a cascade of changes through markets until a new equilibrium is reached An equilibrium is Pareto Efficient if no other allocation of inputs can make one person better off without making another worse off.
76
Chapter 16 Conclusions 4) Pareto Efficiency requires exchange efficiency (goods can’t be traded), input efficiency (more can’t be produced) and substitution efficiency (substituting production won’t improve outcome) 5) The First Fundamental Theorem of Welfare Economics states that if all perfectly competitive markets exist, allocations are Pareto Efficient
77
Chapter 16 Conclusions 6) The Second Fundamental Theorem of Welfare Economics states that governments can redistribute wealth to reach any pareto efficient outcome 7) Free Trade is always beneficial to all parties 8) Economic truths, when properly applied and explained, can cut through ideologies and make people cry
Similar presentations
© 2024 SlidePlayer.com. Inc.
All rights reserved.