Download presentation
Presentation is loading. Please wait.
Published byGodfrey Harris Modified over 9 years ago
1
LDK R Logics for Data and Knowledge Representation Modal Logic Originally by Alessandro Agostini and Fausto Giunchiglia Modified by Fausto Giunchiglia, Rui Zhang and Vincenzo Maltese
2
2 Outline Introduction Syntax Semantics Satisfiability and Validity Kinds of frames Correspondence with FOL 2
3
Introduction We want to model situations like this one: 1. “Fausto is always happy” circumstances” 2. “Fausto is happy under certain In PL/ClassL we could have: HappyFausto In modal logic we have: 1. □ HappyFausto 2. ◊ HappyFausto As we will see, this is captured through the notion of “possible words” and of “accessibility relation” 3
4
Syntax We extend PL with two logical modal operators: □ (box) and ◊ (diamond) □ P : “Box P” or “necessarily P” or “P is necessary true” ◊P : “Diamond P” or “possibly P” or “P is possible” Note that we define □ P = ◊ P, i.e. □ is a primitive symbol The grammar is extended as follows: ::= A | B |... | P | Q |... | ⊥ | ⊤ | ::= | ¬ | ∧ | ∨ | | | □ | ◊ 4
5
Different interpretations 5 Philosophy □ P : “P is necessary” ◊P : “P is possible” Epistemic □ a P : “Agent a believes P ” or “Agent a knows P” Temporal logics □ P : “P is always true” ◊P : “P is sometimes true” Dynamic logics or logics of programs □ a P : “P holds after the program a is executed” Description logics □ HASCHILD MALE ∀ HASCHILD.MALE ◊ HASCHILD MALE ∃ HASCHILD.MALE
6
Semantics: Kripke Model A Kripke Model is a triple M = where: W is a non empty set of worlds R ⊆ W x W is a binary relation called the accessibility relation I is an interpretation function I: L pow(W) such that to each proposition P we associate a set of possible worlds I(P) in which P holds Each w ∈ W is said to be a world, point, state, event, situation, class … according to the problem we model For "world" we mean a PL model. Focusing on this definition, we can see a Kripke Model as a set of different PL models related by an "evolutionary" relation R; in such a way we are able to represent formally - for example - the evolution of a model in time. In a Kripke model, is called frame and is a relational structure. 6
7
Semantics: Kripke Model Consider the following situation: M = W = {1, 2, 3, 4} R = {,,,, } I(BeingHappy) = {2} I(BeingSad) = {1} I(BeingNormal) = {3, 4} 7 123 4 BeingHappy BeingSad BeingNormal
8
Truth relation (true in a world) Given a Kripke Model M =, a proposition P ∈ L ML and a possible world w ∈ W, we say that “w satisfies P in M” or that “P is satisfied by w in M” or “P is true in M via w”, in symbols: M, w ⊨ P in the following cases: 1. P atomicw ∈ I(P) 2. P = QM, w ⊭ Q 3. P = Q TM, w ⊨ Q and M, w ⊨ T 4. P = Q TM, w ⊨ Q or M, w ⊨ T 5. P = Q TM, w ⊭ Q or M, w ⊨ T 6. P = □ Q for every w’ ∈ W such that wRw’ then M, w’ ⊨ Q 7. P = ◊ Q for some w’ ∈ W such that wRw’ then M, w’ ⊨ Q NOTE: wRw’ can be read as “w’ is accessible from w via R” 8
9
Semantics: Kripke Model Consider the following situation: M = W = {1, 2, 3, 4} R = {,,,, } I(BeingHappy) = {2} I(BeingSad) = {1} I(BeingNeutral) = {3, 4} M, 2 ⊨ BeingHappy M, 2 ⊨ BeingSad M, 4 ⊨ □ BeingHappy M, 1 ⊨ ◊BeingHappy M, 1 ⊨ ◊BeingSad 9 123 4 BeingHappy BeingSad BeingNormal
10
Satisfiability and Validity Satisfiability A proposition P ∈ L ML is satisfiable in a Kripke model M = if M, w ⊨ P for all worlds w ∈ W. We can then write M ⊨ P Validity A proposition P ∈ L ML is valid if P is satisfiable for all models M (and by varying the frame ). We can write ⊨ P 10
11
Satisfiability Consider the following situation: M = W = {1, 2, 3, 4} R = {,,, } I(BeingHappy) = {2} I(BeingSad) = {1} I(BeingNormal) = {3, 4} M, w ⊨ □ BeingHappy for all w ∈ W, therefore □ BeingHappy is satisfiable in M. 11 123 4 BeingHappy BeingSad BeingNormal
12
Validity Prove that P: □ A ◊A is valid In all models M =, (1) □ A means that for every w ∈ W such that wRw’ then M, w’ ⊨ A (2) ◊A means that for some w ∈ W such that wRw’ then M, w’ ⊨ A It is clear that if (1) then (2) in the example (as we will see this is valid in serial frames) 12 12 3 A A
13
Kinds of frames Given the frame F =, the relation R is said to be: Serial iff for every w ∈ W, there exists w’ ∈ W s.t. wRw’ Reflexive iff for every w ∈ W, wRw Symmetric iff for every w, w’ ∈ W, if wRw’ then w’Rw Transitiveiff for every w, w’, w’’ ∈ W, if wRw’ and w’Rw’’ then wRw’’ Euclidianiff for every w, w’, w’’ ∈ W, if wRw’ and wRw’’ then w’Rw’’ We call a frame serial, reflexive, symmetric or transitive according to the properties of the relation R 13
14
Kinds of frames Serial: for every w ∈ W, there exists w’ ∈ W s.t. wRw’ Reflexive: for every w ∈ W, wRw Symmetric: for every w, w’ ∈ W, if wRw’ then w’Rw 14 123 12 12 3
15
Kinds of frames Transitive: for every w, w’, w’’ ∈ W, if wRw’ and w’Rw’’ then wRw’’ Euclidian: for every w, w’, w’’ ∈ W, if wRw’ and wRw’’ then w’Rw’’ 15 123 12 3
16
Valid schemas A schema is a formula where I can change the variables THEOREM. The following schemas are valid in the class of indicated frames: D: □ A ◊ Avalid for serial frames T: □ A Avalid for reflexive frames B:A □ ◊ Avalid for symmetric frames 4: □ A □□ Avalid for transitive frames 5: ◊ A □ ◊ Avalid for Euclidian frames NOTE: if we apply T, B and 4 we have an equivalence relation THEOREM. The following schema is valid: K: □ (A B) ( □ A □ B)Distributivity of □ w.r.t. 16
17
Proof for T : □ A A valid for reflexive frames Assuming M, w ⊨ □ A, we want to prove that M, w ⊨ A. From the assumption M, w ⊨ □ A, we have that for every w’ ∈ W such that wRw’ we have that M, w’ ⊨ A (1). Since R is reflexive we also have w’Rw, we then imply that M, w ⊨ A (by substituting w to w’ in (1)) 17 □A, A 12
18
Proof for B : A □◊A valid for symmetric frames Assume M, w ⊨ A. To prove that M, w ⊨ □ ◊ A we need to show that for every w’ ∈ W such that wRw’ then M, w ⊨ ◊ A. M, w ⊨ ◊ A is that for some w’’ ∈ W such that w’Rw’’ then M, w’’ ⊨ A. Therefore we need to prove that for every w’ ∈ W such that wRw’ and for some w’’ ∈ W such that w’Rw’’ then M, w’’ ⊨ A Since R is symmetric, from wRw’ it follows that w’Rw. For w’’ ∈ W such that w’’ = w, we have that w’Rw’’ and M, w’’ ⊨ A. Hence M, w ⊨ A. 18 12 3 A, □◊A ◊A
19
Reasoning services: EVAL Model Checking (EVAL) Given a (finite) model M = and a proposition P ∈ L ML we want to check whether M, w ⊨ P for all w ∈ W M, w ⊨ P for all w ? 19 EVAL M, P Yes No
20
Reasoning services: SAT Satisfiability (SAT) Given a proposition P ∈ L ML we want to check whether there exists a (finite) model M = such that M, w ⊨ P for all w ∈ W Find M such that M, w ⊨ P for all w 20 SAT P M No
21
Reasoning services: UNSAT Unsatisfiability (unSAT) Given a (finite) model M = and a proposition P ∈ L ML we want to check that does not exist any world w such that M, w ⊨ P Verify that ∃ w such that M, w ⊨ P 21 VAL M, P w No
22
Reasoning services: VAL Validity (VAL) Given a a proposition P ∈ L ML we want to check that M, w ⊨ P for all (finite) models M = and w ∈ W Verify that M, w ⊨ P for all M and w 22 VAL P Yes No
23
Correspondence between □ and ∀ ( ◊ and ∃ ) We can define a translation function T: L ML L FO as follows: 1. T(P) = P(x) for all propositions P in L ML 2. T( P) = T(P) for all propositions P 3. T(P * Q) = T(P) * T(Q) for all propositions P, Q and * ∈ { , , } 4. T( □ P) = ∀ x T(P) for all propositions P 5. T( ◊ P) = ∃ x T(P) for all propositions P THEOREM: For all propositions P in L ML, P is modally valid iff T(P) is valid in FOL. 23
Similar presentations
© 2025 SlidePlayer.com. Inc.
All rights reserved.