Presentation is loading. Please wait.

Presentation is loading. Please wait.

1 Introduction to Computability Theory Lecture13: Mapping Reductions Prof. Amos Israeli.

Similar presentations


Presentation on theme: "1 Introduction to Computability Theory Lecture13: Mapping Reductions Prof. Amos Israeli."— Presentation transcript:

1 1 Introduction to Computability Theory Lecture13: Mapping Reductions Prof. Amos Israeli

2 So far, we presented several reductions: From to, from to, from to, from to, and several other. Each of these reductions had some special form not shared with the others. Can we generalize? Mapping Reductions 2

3 Mapping reductions constitute the generalization we are looking for. They are always in a specified form which: 1.Preserves the intrinsic difficulty of finding a reduction. 2.Ease the “red tape” requirements. Mapping Reductions 3

4 In other words: Assume we want to prove that B is undecidable by reduction from A that is known to be undecidable. If our reduction has the form of a Mapping reduction then the proof is complete. Nothing else is required. Mapping Reductions 4

5 The idea of a mapping reduction is very simple: If the instances (candidate elements) of one language, say A, are mapped to the instances of another language, say B, by a computable mapping M in a way that iff, then a decider for B can be used to devise a decider for A. Mapping Reductions 5

6 The sought for decider for A works as follows: Upon input I do: 1.Compute. 2.Use the decider for B to determine whether. 3.If accept - otherwise - reject. Mapping Reductions 6

7 This scheme works but there is one delicate point here. Can you see where it is? The mapping must be computable. Given the input I, your ordinary Turing machine must be able to compute. For this we need the notion of Computable Functions. Mapping Reductions 7

8 Let be an alphabet: A function is a computable function if there exists a TM, M such that for every, if M computes with input w, it halts with on its tape. Computable Functions 8

9 1. Let m and n be natural numbers, let be a string encoding of m and n, and let be the string representing their sum. The function, is computable. 2. The function is a computable function. Can you devise TM-s to compute f and g ? Examples of Computable Functions 9

10 3. Let be an encoding of TM M and let be an encoding of another TM M’ satisfying: 1.. 2. TM M’ never makes four consecutive steps in the same head direction. The function t defined below is computable: Examples of Computable Functions 10

11 In the reduction from to - TM M from the input to was modified by TM S, the decider to TM s.t. all ending computations on M would become accepting computations on. Since was carried out by TM S, it is obviously a computable function. Use of Comp. Func. for Reductions 11

12 Another example is the reduction from to - TM M from the input to, was modified by TM S, to TM s.t. is regular iff. Once again, this is a computable function. Now we turn to define mapping reductions: Use of Comp. Func. for Reductions 12

13 Let A and B be two languages over. A computable function is a mapping reduction from A to B if the following holds: For each, iff. The function f is called reduction of A to B. The arguments of the reduction are often called instances. Mapping Reductions 13

14 If there exists a mapping reduction from A to B, We say that A is mapping reducible to B and denote it by. A pictorial illustration of a mapping reduction appears in the next slide. Mapping Reductions 14

15 . A Pictorial Illustration of_______ 15

16 Assume that. Can we say something about the relationship between and ? Answer: Yes An Observation about__and_____ 16

17 If language A is mapping reducible to language B, then a solution for B, can be used to derive a solution for A. This fact is made formal in the following theorem: Using Mapping Reductions 17

18 If and B is decidable, then A is decidable. Theorem 18

19 Let M be a decider for B and let f be the reduction from A to B. Consider TM N : N= “On input w : 1. Compute. 2. Run M on and output whatever M outputs. “ Clearly N accepts iff. QED Proof 19

20 If and A is undecidable, then B is undecidable. Corollary 20

21 The previous corollary is our main tool for proving undecidability. Notice that in order to prove B undecidable we reduce from A which is known to be undecidable to B. The reduction direction is often a source of errors. A similar tool is used in Complexity theory. Discussion 21

22 On the previous lecture we proved that is undecidable. Now, we prove this theorem once more by demonstrating a mapping reduction from to. Revisited 22

23 Theorem The language Is undecidable. Revisited 23

24 Proof The proof is by reduction from. In the next slide we show that. By the previous corollary it follows that is undecidable. Revisited 24

25 The mapping reduction is presented by TM F : F= “On input : 1. Construct TM M’. M’= “On input x : 1. Run M on x. 2. if M accepts accept. 3. If M rejects, enter a loop.” 2. Output.” Mapping Reduction from to__ 25

26 It is not hard to see that iff. In other words:. Since is undecidable, the previous corollary implies that is undecidable too. Proof (cont.) 26

27 What happens if the input does not contain a valid description of a TM? By the specification of we know that in this case. Therefore in this case TM F should output any string s satisfying. The Halting Problem Revisited 27

28 Theorem The language Is undecidable. Revisited 28

29 Proof The proof is by reduction from which is known to be undecidable. In the next slide we show that. By the previous corollary it follows that is undecidable. Revisited 29

30 Let be an encoding of a TM that rejects all its inputs. The mapping f is defined as follows: For each instance of,,. It is not hard to verify that Meaning:. QED Mapping Reduction from to__ 30

31 If and B is Turing recognizable, then A is Turing recognizable. Theorem 31

32 Let M be a decider for B and let f be the reduction from A to B. Consider TM N : N= “On input w : 1. Compute. 2. Run M on and output whatever M outputs.” Clearly N accepts iff. QED Proof 32 Turing Recognizer N recognizes B. - if M halts,

33 If and A is not Turing recognizable, then B is not Turing recognizable. Corollary 33

34 Theorem is neither Turing recognizable nor co- Turing recognizable. Reminder A language L is co-Turing recognizable if its complement,, is Turing recognizable. The Status of______ 34

35 If by a mapping f, then by the same mapping it holds that. Since we know that is not Turing recognizable, we can prove that language A is not Turing recognizable by reducing to. Proof 35

36 Now we use the previous remark and prove that is not Turing recognizable, by showing that. Since, we conclude that and since we know that is not Turing recognizable we conclude that so is. Proof 36

37 F= “ on input, where M is a TM: 1. Construct that accepts on any input and that accepts if M accepts w. 2. Output. It is not hard to see that F computes a reduction from to. Proof 37

38 G= “ on input, where M is a TM: 1. Construct that rejects on any input and that accepts if M accepts w. 2. Output. It is not hard to see that G computes a reduction from to. Proof 38

39 Since we conclude that is not Turing recognizable. Since we conclude that is not co-Turing recognizable, hence is not Turing recognizable. QED Proof 39


Download ppt "1 Introduction to Computability Theory Lecture13: Mapping Reductions Prof. Amos Israeli."

Similar presentations


Ads by Google