Download presentation
Presentation is loading. Please wait.
1
Using Modern Nonexpected Utility Theories for Risky Decisions and Modern Tools from Experimental Economics to Revisit Classical Debates in Economics, and to Restore the Classical Utility Concept Peter P. Wakker; Erasmus University of Rotterdam (& Abdellaoui & Barrios; Ecole Normale Supérieure of Cachan) Make yellow comments invisible. ALT-View-O Make yellow comments invisible. ALT-View-O Two things you will not like (at least two): We had to resort to hypothetical choice. As I will explain, it is the only way to do this. Measuring utility of money is important, is essential, so I think it is still worthwhile. So I hope you will still want to listen, even though I know that many of you strongly object to it. Even worse, data based on no choice at all! Economists in general don't want to see that. Here even more I must ask for your patience, and for your cooperation. Utility central in economics. - We review history and classical debates ("ordinal revolution"). - We bring novelty, using modern nonexpected utility and modern experimental economics, rather than philosophy & armchair speculation. Motto: "don't talk but look".
2
2 Our purpose: Show that choiceless inputs can be useful in economics; revival of old cardinal utility … Many others have pleaded for it in the past and in the present. Special aspect of our plea: Not ad hoc. Not just going back to Bentham. Rather: Link choiceless inputs to revealed preference. Build on, reinforce, revealed preference. Don't abandon it. Novelty is not in use of choiceless inputs for economic questions. That's often done by applied people, for instance in health economics. Not unfounded.
3
1 st appearance of utility: Cramer (1728), Bernoulli (1738) 18 th century 1 st thorough analysis: Bentham (1789); Utility “intuitive.” 3 1. History of Utility Skip details of history and go immediately to ordinal revolution, saying only that people took utility intuitively.
4
Samuelson (1947, p. 206), about such views: "To a man like Edgeworth, steeped as he was in the Utilitarian tradition, individual utility—nay social utility—was as real as his morning jam." Utility still intuitive 19 th century 1870: the marginal revolution (Jevons 1871, Menger 1871, Walras 1874) Resolved Smith's (1776) paradox of value-in-use versus value-in-exchange (e.g. the "water-diamond" paradox). 4
5
Ordinal revolution: Pareto (1906), Hicks & Allen (1934) 1 st half of 20 th century Utility choice. al direct judgment abandoned Baumol 1958, Fisher 1892, Pareto 1906, Slutsky 1915 U ordinal in mathe- matical sense 5 “Utility” is the heritage of Bentham and his theory of pleasures and pains. For us his word is the more acceptable, the less it is entangled with his theory. [Italics from original( Sect14, Chapter 1)] Talk about observability. Be positive on ordinalism! Relate to logical positivism and Popper. Tree: Say that we should distinguish two points, an empirical and a mathematical aspect, aspects that have been confused. First branch: Say this is empirical substantial aspect, important for us. 2 nd is mathematical, not so central today. Tree: Say that we should distinguish two points, an empirical and a mathematical aspect, aspects that have been confused. First branch: Say this is empirical substantial aspect, important for us. 2 nd is mathematical, not so central today. Logical positivism: everything falsifiable. No metaphysics. In psychology: behaviorism. In economics:
6
6 von Neumann-Morgenstern (1944) with their expected-utility model for risky decisions: New hope for cardinal utility? General consensus: Cardinal in mathematical sense, not empirical neoclassical; vNM-U only for risk; not for welfare evaluations etc. Cardinal utility exists in subfields (risky, welfare, taxation, temporal) but strictly kept there. Ordinal view dominates. (So, no meaning for utility differences.) Most economists believe that marginal utility is: 1. nonexistent and also 2. diminishing. Most economists believe that marginal utility is: 1. nonexistent and also 2. diminishing.
7
7 First there were positive results and hope for ordinalism: Hicks & Allen (1934): Market phenomena only need ordinal utility. Samuelson (1938), Houthakker (1950): Preference revealed from market demand. de Finetti (1937), Savage (1954): Choice- basis of subjective beliefs. Debreu (1959): Existence of market equilibrium. Behalve regel 1 alles overslaan.
8
History of utility after 1950: No account of it known to us. There are several accounts of history up to and including ordinal revolution (Stigler 1950, Blaug 1962 & 1997). Yet, many changes occurred since 1950. Time for an update! 8 We think that new things are happening!
9
9 History of utility after 1950: Allais (1953) & Ellsberg (1961): > < EU First-generation models didn't yet question ordinal position: nonEU. However … Arrow (1951): No good social procedure when only ordinal information. Simon (1955): Bounded rationality; satisficing. Most serious blow for ordinalism: Preference reversals (Lichtenstein & Slovic '71, Grether & Plott '79). Skip most except serious blow. Of serious blow say that this morning, Starmer gave us hope that prospect theory can still model it.
10
A new, recent, blow. Kahneman (1994, & al.) for intertemporal choice. Big irrationalities: People seemingly prefer prolongation of pain. Shows that: Often, human species cannot integrate over time. Then: No revealed preference. Better resort back to Bentham's "experienced utility." 10
11
- a property of the commodity? - a property of the consumer? Typical Questions for cardinal utility (not discussed here): 11 Is utility - ultimate index of goodness? -index for other good things (expected offspring …). If child reveals clear preference for candy over medicine, then how about utility thereof? If two persons have different utilities, must it be due to different background/circumstances of an objective kind? Skip most; purpose is to show that we don't want to discuss these things!
12
2.Experimental Economics and Utility; Plan of Paper 12 For questions: "Do cardinal and/or ordinal utility exist?" "Are they the same?" experimental economics' answer is: (Try to) measure them, and see! No philosophical contemplations here. A table organizing some utility-related phenomena, and positioning our contribution: Don't talk but look.
13
Intertemporal Welfare Risk 13 cardinal utility choiceless Utilities within rectangles are commonly restricted to their domains. Strength of preferences Experienced (Kahneman) Mark Machina, Jun'02: “The word utility has too many meanings. I avoid using the word utility.” We: not more concepts, but fewer. Relate them. choice-based ordinal utility Market equilibria : Relation obtained in this paper. Say on 1 st appearance that choice-based in a column and ordinal utility a row. just noticeable differences; minimally perceptible thresholds just noticeable differences; minimally perceptible thresholds We hope to get Machina and others back to using the concept of utility.
14
First, measure utility through risky decisions (choice-based). -Empirical problems for traditional EU; have frustrated utility measurements. - Can be fixed using prospect theory (Bleichrodt, Pinto, & Wakker 2001, Management Science). Next, measure utility through strength of preference; direct judgments (choiceless). Finally, compare these utilities. 3. Plan of paper 14 They also had data where reference dependence plays a role. So where you get straight preference reversals, and by applying the CPT parameters of T&K'92, and plausible reference points, you can reconcile the inconsistencies. They also give a precise elaborated quantitative model for it; but, had no state- dependence of the reference point.
15
1 st utility measurement: Tradeoff (TO) method (Wakker & Deneffe 1996) Completely choice-based. 4. The Experiment 15
16
( U(t 1 ) U(t 0 ) ) = ( U(2000) U(1000) ) U(1000) + U(t 1 ) = U(2000) + U(t 0 ); _ ( U(2000) U(1000) ) Tradeoff (TO) method t2t2 1000 2000 t 1 ~ t6t6 1000 2000 t 5 ~ 1000 2000 5000 (= t 0 ) EU = U(t 2 ) U(t 1 ) = =...... = U(t 6 ) U(t 5 ) = U(t 1 ) U(t 0 ) =...... 16 _ ( U(2000) U(1000) ) _ ( U(2000) U(1000) ) 6,000 ~ 200,000 t 1 18, 1 curve
17
? ? ? Tradeoff (TO) method 17 _ ( U(2000) U(1000) ) t2t2 1000 2000 t 1 ~ t6t6 1000 2000 t 5 ~ 1000 2000 5000 (= t 0 ) EU = U(t 2 ) U(t 1 ) = =...... = U(t 6 ) U(t 5 ) = U(t 1 ) U(t 0 ) =...... _ ( U(2000) U(1000) ) _ ( U(2000) U(1000) ) 12,000 ~ 200,000 t 1 Prospect theory: weighted prob s (even unknown prob s ) 11 22 11 22 11 22 ! ! ! 21, curves; then 23, CE 1/3
18
1 0 U $ Normalize: U(t 0 ) = 0; U(t 6 ) = 1. t0t0 t1t1 t6t6 1/6 t5t5 5/6 t4t4 4/6 t3t3 3/6 t2t2 2/6 Consequently: U(t j ) = j/6. 18 If I teach students, I let them draw their own utility curves in this manner.
19
2 nd utility measurement: Strength of Preference (SP) Based on direct judgment, not choice-based. 19
20
For which s 2 is ?s2s2 Strength of Preference (SP) For which s 6 is s 6 s 5 ~* t 1 t 0 ?...... We assume: U(s 2 ) – U(t 1 ) = U(t 1 ) – U(t 0 ) U(s 3 ) – U(s 2 ) = U(t 1 ) – U(t 0 ) U(s 6 ) – U(s 5 ) = U(t 1 ) – U(t 0 ) 20...... t1t0t1t0 t1t1 ~* For which s 3 is ?s3s3 t1t0t1t0 s2s2 ~* This U just comes out of the blue. We're even using the same symbol U … This U just comes out of the blue. We're even using the same symbol U …
21
CE 2/3 (EU) CE 2/3 (PT) corrects CE 2/3 (EU) FF CE 1/3 CE 2/3 (PT) SP TO Utility functions (group averages) 0 1/6 2/6 3/6 4/6 5/6 1 7/6 U t 0 = FF5,000 21 t 6 = FF26,068 22, nonTO,nonEU 24, power? 26, which th? PT! (then TO)) 28,concl 25, CE 2/3 23, CE 1/3 TO(PT) = TO(EU) CE 1/3 (PT) = CE 1/3 (EU) (gr.av.) FF 5,000: € 1000 = $ 1300 FF 5,000: € 1000 = $ 1300 Real incentives discussed after first two curves. Questions of statistical power etc., don't discuss them at this page but go to the powerpoint slides that have them.
22
Question: Could this identity have resulted because the TO method does not properly measure choice-based risky utility? 22 (And, after answering this, what about nonEU?) Reassure them that analyses will remain valid under nonEU.
23
Certainty equivalent CE 1/3 (with good-outcome probability 1/3) 3 d utility measurement: t0t0 t 6 c2c2 ~ t0t0 c 2 c2c2 t 6 EU U(c 2 ) = 1/3 U(c 1 ) = 1/9 U(c 3 ) = 5/9 23 For which c 2 : ? c1c1 ~ For which c 1 : ? c3c3 ~ For which c 3 : ? 21, curves & RDU & PT (for gr.av.) 21, curves (Chris Starmer, June 24, 2005) on inverse-S: "It is not universal. But if I had to bet, I would bet on this one.". At PT: Discuss that no individual w's were known. If lack of time: skip all algebra. Only discuss choice of w.
24
24 Questions Could this identity have resulted because our experiment is noisy (cannot distinguish anything)? How about violations of EU?
25
Certainty equivalent CE 4 th utility measurement: t0t0 t 6 d2d2 ~ t0t0 d 2 d2d2 t 6 CE 2/3 (EU): U(d 2 ) = 2/3 U(d 1 ) = 4/9 U(d 3 ) = 8/9 CE 2/3 (PT) (gr.av): U(d 2 ) =.51 U(d 1 ) =.26 U(d 3 ) =.76 25 d3d3 ~ For which d 3 : ? d1d1 ~ For which d 1 : ? For which d 2 : ? 21, curves 2/3 (with good-outcome probability 2/3) If lack of time: skip all algebra.
26
And, EU is violated. 26 So, our experiment does have the statistical power to distinguish. Which alternative theory to use? Prospect theory.
27
p w 1 1 0 1/3 Figure. The common weighting fuction w(1/3) = 1/3; 27 16,TOmethod 1/3 w(2/3) =.51 2/3.51 We re-analyze preceding measurements in terms of prospect theory; first TO.
28
5. Conclusions Under EU: usual discrepancies for risky ut., U CE 2/3 U CE 1/3, U TO Risky choice-based U = riskless choiceless U?? However: = U SP 28 Under one risky utility, U CE 2/3 = U CE 1/3 = U TO RDU PT : At one risky utility, say that we reconfirm BP&W. They also had preference reversals and reference dependence.
29
Gilboa & Schmeidler (2001), "A Cognitive Model of Individual Well-Being," Social Choice and Welfare 18, 269–288. Fox, Craig R. & Amos Tversky (1998), "A Belief-Based Account of Decision under Uncertainty," Management Science 44, 879 895. Kahneman (1994), "New Challenges to the Rationality Assumption," Journal of Instit. & Theor. Ec s 150,18 36. Tinbergen, Jan (1991), “On the Measurement of Welfare,” Journal of Econometrics 50, 7 13. van Praag, Bernard M.S. (1968), "Individual Welfare Functions and Consumer Behavior.” North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1968. Interest in choiceless inputs in economics: 29 Especially useful if choice anomalies are prominent. We: relate choiceless inputs to revealed preference. Show how choiceless inputs can reinforce revealed preference!
30
30 Experimental economics has shed new light on classical debates about utility: Don't talk but look.
31
Appendix on Analysis of Data All analyses with ANOVA (so, correcting for individual variation). We tested on raw data, and on parametric fittings. Parametric fittings of utility of: 1.Power (CRRA); 2.Exponential (CARA); 3.We developed a one-parametric subfamily of Saha's expo-power satisfying economic desiderata; first presented in ESA- Amsterdam, October 2000. Later used by Holt & Laury (2002). 31
Similar presentations
© 2025 SlidePlayer.com. Inc.
All rights reserved.