Download presentation
Presentation is loading. Please wait.
1
1 Approaches to Behavioral Welfare Economics Building on the 20 th Century Economic Tradition More than one agent per person –e.g. hyperbolic discounting –a problem of welfare aggregation across agents Confusion (Cognitive Economics) –Preferences when well-informed and thoughtful are what count—a data issue Preferences over emotions
2
2 Preferences Over Emotions (Emotions in the Utility Function) People care about how they feel Preferences over ultimate goods (including emotions) can be taken as totally standard Emotions can have complex household production functions –Everything the person can control is an argument. The function itself cannot be chosen. –Psychological data pin down the production function for the emotion—thus, in principle there are no extra degrees of freedom beyond those in a standard utility function with the same number of arguments.
3
3 Example 1: Anger People care whether they feel angry or not. People want to be angry in certain situations. In other situations they want to not be angry. (Anger is an argument of preferences.) The genesis of anger is probably related to expectations and to preferences. If someone acts against our interests (=preferences) more than we would expect them to, we are more likely to feel angry. (Expectations and preferences are arguments of the production function for anger.) Note the circularity: anger↔preferences –indirect utility will be determined by a fixed-point mapping.
4
4 Example 2: Happiness People care whether they feel happy or not. Mostly, people would prefer to feel happier. (Happiness is an argument of preferences.) How happy one feels seems to involve (among other things) how well one is doing relative to expectations in relation to one’s preferences. (Expectations and preferences are arguments of the production function for happiness.) Note the circularity: happiness↔preferences –indirect utility will be determined by a fixed-point mapping.
5
5 The Economics of Happiness Miles Kimball
6
6 What I Know about Happiness “Utility and Happiness,” by Miles Kimball and Robert Willis (Not your usual paper about happiness. We may be wrong, but we are definitely different.) “Unhappiness After Hurricane Katrina” by Miles Kimball, Helen Levy, Fumio Ohtake and Yoshiro Tsutsui “The Dynamics of Happiness: Evidence from Daily Panel Data” by Miles Kimball, Fumio Ohtake and Yoshiro Tsutsui “The Dynamics of Happiness After Major Life Events” by Miles Kimball and Daniel Silverman Conversations with Norbert Schwarz
7
7 Why Happiness Matters for Economics 1. Preference for Happiness: Many people value happiness, as evidenced by the fact that they will sacrifice other things for the sake of happiness. 2. News and Happiness: Short-run spikes and dips in happiness –signal what people consider good and bad news, –which in turn signals what they care about.
8
8 Two Definitions of “Happiness” The Greatest Good for an Individual Feeling Happy
9
9 Who Judges the Greatest Good for an Individual? An Authority Figure or the Speaker –“True Happiness” used as a cudgel Economics Defers to the Individual –Utility
10
10 Measuring Happiness, in the Narrow Sense of Feeling Happy On a scale from one to seven, where one is “extremely unhappy” and seven is “extremely happy,” how do you feel right now?
11
11 Greater Happiness in the Narrow Sense is Not Always a Good Thing Mania: too much happiness Too much sacrificed for the sake of feeling happier –Example: changing one’s political beliefs in order to be happier.
12
12 Distinguishing preferences and happiness as a matter of logic. Preferences (Represented by Lifetime Utility) = The extent to which people get what they want, where what they want is revealed by their choices. Happiness (Current Affect) = How positive people’s feelings are at a given time.
13
13 The Ethical Question People’s own choices and feelings are the two non-paternalistic indicators we have for individual welfare (what makes an individual better off in the sense relevant for policy). A priori, both seem useful. What if public policy choice A accords with what people would choose, but policy choice B would make them feel best?
14
14 The Neobenthamites Currently, the standard view among psychologists and most economists working with happiness data—articulated most forcefully by Daniel Kahneman—is that a present discounted value of measured happiness is a good indicator of what people should be maximizing. To the extent that people are maximizing something else, it is viewed as a mistake. Factual mistakes people make in predicting their own future happiness are thought to be an important reason people make these optimization mistakes. (Return to this below.)
15
15 Our View Bob Willis and I are questioning this orthodoxy. When well-informed and thoughtful, we view people’s choices as the best indication of their individual welfare. People do often make optimization errors. But much of what this orthodoxy takes as evidence of optimization errors, we take as evidence that utility and “happiness” are not the same thing.
16
16 Utilitarianism (Jeremy Bentham, John Stuart Mill) “The greatest good of the greatest number” Solving social problems is important because it is a miserable experience to be poor, sick or downtrodden. It is also important to make things better, wherever we can, even if they are already good. Utilitarianism is part of the philosophical foundation of economics.
17
17 Measuring Utility: The Modern Tradition of Economics Look at an individual’s choices (preferences). What an individual chooses indicates what she wants, cares about and values. This works well when the individual is –Well informed –Thoughtful –Not at war with self
18
18 Evidence that Utility≠Happiness 1.People who knowingly, thoughtfully and without regret choose not to maximize long-run happiness indicate that utility≠happiness for them. 2.People make choices eagerly that they never regret, but which have no long-run effect on how happy they feel. –Moving to a new city –Buying a nice car 3. People thoughtfully make choices that they never regret, which lower their long-run felt happiness. –Commuting further to a higher-paying job. –Longer working hours to put one’s child through college. –Having a baby? –Doing one’s duty.
19
19 The Nature of Happiness (What Makes Us Feel Happy)
20
20 Key Facts about What Makes Us Feel Happy #1: Easterlin Paradox #2: Hedonic Adaptation
21
21 The Easterlin Paradox
22
22 The Evidence of Choices: Migration Flows Indicate that Income is Valuable to People Per capita GDP in Mexico is not far from what it was in the U.S. in the 1950’s. Large numbers of Mexicans choose to migrate to the U.S. Among the many costs of migration, their social rank often drops drastically when they migrate to the U.S. Despite this, they come.
23
Reevaluating the Easterlin Paradox Betsey Stevenson and Justin Wolfers challenge the facts behind the “Easterlin Paradox,” except for the U.S. Jean-Benoit Rousseau confirms these findings and adds insight about the U.S. However, Stevenson and Wolfers show that women’s happiness has declined relative to men’s, which is equally paradoxical. 23
24
24 Fact #1 In the long run, people can become better off without feeling happier.
25
25 Hedonic Adaptation: “This, too, shall pass.” 1. After time has passed, things that surely had a big effect on happiness right after the event have surprisingly little effect on happiness. (Not just money.) incarceration loss of the use of limbs serious burns death of a spouse winning the lottery 2. The dynamics of national happiness after news 3. The dynamics of happiness after major life events 4. The dynamics of happiness: evidence from daily panel data
26
26 Unhappiness After Hurricane Katrina Miles Kimball Helen Levy Fumio Ohtake Yoshiro Tsutsui
27
27 USA: The Happiness Index on the Reuters/UM Surveys of Consumers “Now think about the past week and the feelings you have experienced. Please tell me if each of the following was true for you much of the time this past week: 1.Much of the time during the past week, you felt you were happy. (Would you say yes or no)? 2.(Much of the time during the past week,) you felt sad. (Would you say yes or no?) 3.(Much of the time during the past week,) you enjoyed life. (Would you say yes or no?) 4.(Much of the time during the past week,) you felt depressed. (Would you say yes or no?)”
28
28
29
29
30
30
31
31
32
32
33
33 Implications of the October Dip in Happiness It is difficult to explain this dip in happiness on the grounds that lifetime utility is seriously effected in terms of self-interest. If this dip in happiness is due to altruism, the happiness data told us something we might not otherwise have known: Americans cared quite a bit about those hurt by the earthquake in Pakistan—more than one would suspect from the donation data. –Katrina and Rita: >$2.65 Billion –South Asian Tsunami: >$1.55 Billion
34
34 What does it mean to say that lifetime utility has fallen permanently? Revealed Preference is the measure of lifetime utility. If there were a lever to magically undo the damage of Katrina, we would pull it. –True for the harm to others. –True for the harm to self, narrowly construed. –True even if the past cannot be changed but only the harm from now on reversed.
35
35
36
36
37
37
38
38 The Dynamics of Happiness After Major Life Events June 5, 2007 Dan Silverman and Miles Kimball Using HRS data to observe the relationships between economically quantifiable life-events, such as the death of a spouse, and a quantifiable measure of happiness.
39
39 Introduction Exploring the relationships between dramatic life-events and happiness, using longitudinal data from the HRS. Current work considers the death of one’s spouse, life- insurance, and associated levels of a happiness index. We define our happiness index using the Center for Epidemiologic Studies Depression Scale (CESD) questions in the HRS. We use data from individuals’ reports on dates of spousal death and information on spousal life-insurance. We consider men and women together and separately. We also consider those with and without life-insurance.
40
40 Non-parametric estimates, w/controls
41
41 With Life Insurance: Non-Parametric estimates (no FE)
42
42 Parametric estimates, no fixed effects: MEN
43
43 Parametric estimates, no fixed effects: WOMEN
44
44 Parametric estimates, no fixed effects: w/ LIFE INSURANCE
45
45 Parametric estimates, no fixed effects: NO LIFE INSURANCE
46
46 Findings Quick Hedonic Adaptation (Mean Reversion of Happiness) Men react more than women Those without life insurance react more than those who do have life insurance.
47
47 Two Strategies for Using Happiness Data to Value Non- Marketed Goods Divide the effect of the non-marketed good on the long-run level of happiness by the effect of money on the long-run level of happiness. Divide the effect of news about the non- marketed good on the dynamics of happiness (lost area under the curve) by the effect of news about money on the dynamics of happiness.
48
48 The Dynamics of Happiness: Evidence from Daily Panel Data Miles Kimball, Fumio Ohtake and Yoshiro Tsutsui RA’s: Yuki Kosaka and Noah Smith
49
49 Japan: The Osaka University Panel Study of Happiness Dynamics 71 Osaka University Undergraduates –49 male, 22 female Answered daily web survey for 273 days (so far). Often used web-capable cell-phones High response rates Total of 17258 person-day observations
50
50
51
51 Top of the First Page of the Paper Version
52
52
53
53 Personal News
54
54 National News
55
55 Histogram of Average Happiness (averaged across individuals)
56
56 Histogram of Average Personal News Ratings
57
57 Histogram of Average National News Ratings
58
58 Scatterplot of Happiness vs. Same- Day Personal News
59
59 Scatterplot of Happiness vs. Same- Day National News
60
60 Average Happiness vs. Average Personal News Rating
61
61 Average Happiness vs. Average National News Rating
62
62 Empirical Strategy Estimate the time series effect of innovations in personal and national news on happiness. Allow for individual fixed effects Regress personal news ratings on their own lags and treat the residuals from this regression as true personal news innovations (“whitened personal news”) Do the same for national news ratings to construct “whitened national news.” Check for nonlinearities in the relationship between news ratings and happiness.
63
63 News Ratings vs. Lifetime Utility Innovations Our theoretical concept of “news” is innovations in information about lifetime utility. These innovations should be unpredictable. However, the ordinary language meaning of “good news” and “bad news” may be somewhat predictable. We will purge the component of the news ratings that are predictable by past news ratings. We expect some remaining predictability of news ratings as today’s information is sometimes treated as “tomorrow’s expected news.” The theory then implies that today’s reported happiness should be correlated with tomorrow’s news ratings even after controlling for current and past news ratings.
64
64 Daily Happiness vs. Daily Personal News
65
65 Increments (Personal)
66
66 Cumulative Increments (Personal)
67
67 Daily Happiness and Daily National News
68
68 Increments (National)
69
69
70
70 Whitening (Personal)
71
71 Whitening (National)
72
72 Impulse Response (Personal & National)
73
73 Impulse Response (Personal)
74
74 Impulse Response (National)
75
75 Component Impulse Responses (Personal News)
76
76 Component Impulse Responses (National News)
77
77 Impulse Response + Neg. Sensitivity (Personal)
78
78 Impulse Response + Neg. Sensitivity (National)
79
79 Fact #2 about Happiness Happiness depends more on changes than on the absolute level of one’s circumstances. Analogy: We have no altimeter in our brains, but we can tell whether we are going up or down.
80
80 The Elation Theory of Happiness Experienced happiness is the sum of two components: elation: short-run happiness that depends on recent news about lifetime utility baseline mood: long-run happiness that depends on one’s daily actions
81
Project 2: Well-Being and Utility in Economics Project Leader: Miles Kimball Co-Investigators: David Albouy, Daniel Benjamin, Dan Silverman, Robert Willis (+Jean-Benoit Rousseau)
82
A. Specific Aims 1.Continue to develop and validate the technique of using the short-run dynamics of happiness to gauge the size of shocks to lifetime utility. 2.Analyze the determinants of long-run happiness using the HRS psychosocial leave-behind. 3.Compare different methods for valuing non-market goods.
83
A. Specific Aims (cont.) 4. Examine the relationship between happiness literacy, degree of preference for happiness, time budget and happiness. 5. Test the implications of the elation theory for measuring marginal utility.
84
B. Background and Significance 1.Valuing Non-Market Goods 2.Dealing with the Possibility of Mistakes 3.The Claims of the Existing Economic Literature on Happiness a. Long-run happiness regressions can value non-market goods?? b. Happiness data can diagnose mistakes?? 4. Price Theory of Happiness 5. Marginal Utility in Empirical Economics
85
C. Preliminary Studies 1.Elation Theory of Utility and Happiness 2.Empirics of Elation Determination a.Financial and Non-Financial Dimensions of Major Life Events in the HRS b.Katrina c.Elections d.Daily Web Panel of News and Happiness 3.Happiness and Expectations
86
C1. Elation Theory of Utility and Happiness a. Happiness≠Utility 1.Utility = U(Happiness, Other Goods) 2.Maximizing Happiness is Not the Object b. Happiness Dynamics and Innovations to Lifetime Utility 1. Happiness = Baseline Mood(Genes, Time Use, Goods) + Elation(Recent News About Lifetime Utility) 2. Hypothesis: Size of Innovation to Lifetime Utility is Proportional to the Extra Area or Lost Area Under a Graph of Happiness Versus Time. 3. Intensity and Duration of Effects on Happiness
87
C1b4: Model of the Short-Run Dynamics of Happiness Happiness it = α i + β i f(ΔV i,t) + ε it α i = Individual Fixed Effect β i = Emotional Sensitivity Parameter t = Time Lapse Since Shock V i = H(W) + J(Z); W=Wealth; Z=Non-Mkt Wealth Shock: ΔV i = H(W 0 +ΔW) - H(W 0 ) Non-Market Shock: ΔV i = J(Z 0 +ΔZ) – J(Z 0 )
88
C2a. Empirics of Elation: Major Life Events in the HRS 1.Variation in both the financial and non- financial dimensions of dated shocks: widowing, divorce, health events 2.Imputing a value based on the dynamics of happiness in reaction to the financial and non-financial dimensions of shocks 3.Exponential: no evidence within HRS that duration depends on size of shock
90
Parametric Estimates, By Life Insurance Status Parameter With Life Insurance Point estimate (s.e.) Without Life Insurance Point estimate (s.e.) c 84.42 (1.21) 80.53 (2.05) -2.27 (1.61) -4.47 (2.68) -4.50 (3.72) -5.53 (6.19) -24.66 (5.26) -56.58 (12.62) 0.120 (0.045) 0.227 (0.076)
91
C2b. Empirics of Elation: Katrina 1.Important national news events can have a significant effect on average happiness in the U.S. 2.Even for Hurricane Katrina—a quite big event—this effect was short-lived, lasting only a few weeks. 3.The dip in the average happiness in the U.S. after Katrina may provide non- market evidence of altruism.
92
92
93
C2c. Empirics of Elation: Elections 1.Partisan movements in happiness near elections reflect heterogeneity in preferences over non-market goods. 2.Happiness reaction depends on both intensity of political preferences and expectations. (2006 elections) 3.Potential for validation of happiness movements as a strength of preferences measure.
94
C2d. Empirics of Elation: Daily Web Panel 1.Subjective ratings of both personal and national news (-5 to +5 scale of bad news to good news) are tightly related to subsequent happiness dynamics. 2.News on a given day affects happiness for about two weeks. 3.Personal news has a bigger effect on happiness than national news. 4.Proportional: duration is indep. of size
101
C3. Happiness and Expectations a.Both the individual fixed effect component of happiness and variations in happiness are related to expectations reports b.Interesting variations in which types of expectations measures are affected most c.Weather can be used as an instrument to see if variations in happiness can cause shifts in expectations d.Are these shifts in expectations shifts that affect behavior? Sunny days and stock mkt.
102
D. Research Design and Methods 1.Continue to develop and validate the technique of using the short-run dynamics of happiness to gauge the size of shocks to lifetime utility. 2.Analyze the determinants of long-run happiness using the HRS psychosocial leave-behind. 3.Compare different methods for valuing non-market goods.
103
D. Research Design and Methods (cont.) 4. Examine the relationship between happiness literacy, degree of preference for happiness, time budget and happiness. 5. Test the implications of the elation theory for measuring marginal utility.
104
D1. Developing and Validating Techniques for Using Elation to Measure Utility Shocks a.Continue SCA data collection b.Daily Web Panel on the ALP in collaboration with Osaka University c.Experiments dosing people with money –Vary amount, probabilities and time lapse –Establish functional form of happiness dynamics in relation to monetary values probabilities and time. –Feeds into design of MU elicitation
105
D2. Analyze determinants of long-run happiness with HRS psychosocial leave-behind. a.HRS Psychosocial Leave-Behind has rich data on hobbies; religious attendance, belief and prayer; quality of relationships with spouses, children, relatives, and friends; loneliness; positive and negative thinking; quality of local community, locus of control; perceived discrimination; past traumas; management of emotions; rank on social ladder; addictions; …
106
D2. Analyze determinants of long-run happiness with HRS psychosocial leave-behind. a.… anxiety; job quality; date of being robbed, death of child, natural disaster, assault, life-threatening illness or accident, physical abuse. b.Extra data on happiness. c.Preference for happiness makes the production function for long-run happiness matter. d.Feeds into subprojects D3 and D4.
107
D3. Compare different methods for valuing non-market goods. a.Elation-based measures on HRS b.Ratios of happiness regression coefficients as in the existing happiness literature. –Use rich psychosocial leave-behind data –doubles as an investigation of the determinants of baseline mood. c. Hypothetical-revealed-preference and predicted happiness measures using vignettes
108
D4. Happiness Literacy and Happiness a. Retirement Makes Possible the Major Input Into Long- Run Happiness: Time b. Factors That May Limit Happiness: 1.May Not Know the Household Production Function for Happiness 2.May Not Want to Make Feeling Happy a Priority c. Develop New Measures 1.Happiness Literacy 2.Preference (Motivation) for Happiness d. Implement New Measures as an HRS Module and Compare to HRS Measure of Happiness
109
D5. Test the implications of the elation theory for measuring marginal utility. a.Marginal utility of wealth a key concept for life-cycle C and labor supply; ALP planned to have C and labor data. b.Happiness does not measure utility, but the magnitude and duration of short-run spikes in happiness should be a useful indicator of marginal utility. c.We can elicit such an indicator of marginal utility on the ALP.
110
Reminder: Model of the Short- Run Dynamics of Happiness Happiness it = α i + β i f(ΔV i,t) + ε it α i = Individual Fixed Effect β i = Emotional Sensitivity Parameter t = Time Lapse Since Shock V i = H(W) + J(Z); W=Wealth; Z=Non-Mkt Wealth Shock: ΔV i = H(W 0 +ΔW) - H(W 0 ) Non-Market Shock: ΔV i = J(Z 0 +ΔZ) – J(Z 0 )
111
D5c. Collecting an Indicator of Marginal Utility on the ALP Measure Happiness Random doses of $5 to $50, with average expense of $15--$20 per respondent. Ask expectations questions to provide time lapse AND study the effects of exogenous movements in happiness on expectations Measure Happiness Again
112
112 An Integrated Theory of Utility and Happiness A. Preference for Happiness: Many people value happiness, as evidenced by the fact that they will sacrifice other things for the sake of happiness. B. News and Happiness: Short-run spikes and dips in happiness –signal what people consider good and bad news, –which in turn signals what they care about.
113
113 Preference for Happiness Axiom: Preferences depend on the joint stochastic process of S: vector of state variables C: vector of control variables H: current happiness (affect) B: other outputs of household production functions (e.g. health) There is an intertemporal expected utility representation over these ultimate goods at least weakly increasing in H at every date and in every state of nature.
114
114 Evidence in Favor of a Preference for Happiness The preference for happiness shows up in both household and firm behavior: Purchases of therapy, Prozac, self-help books, magazines featuring “happiness.” Advertising that tries to suggest that a product will make one feel happy.
115
115 Contrast with the Neobenthamite View People value happiness (and will sacrifice other goods for it) versus People should be maximizing happiness (often interpreted as saying that happiness is the true utility function).
116
116 Arguments of Happiness beyond S,C,B J t = state variables that do not matter directly for preferences but affect household production: genes, underlying physical and psychological states, unknown parameter values and shocks. Q t = control variables that do not matter directly for preferences, but affect household production of happiness (empty set? psychoactive and other medical drugs, recreational drugs?) v t, v t-1, v t-2,… = the history of lifetime utility. (Note: B=B(S,J,C,Q))
117
117 News and Happiness The relationship between circumstances and happiness is weak in the long run, BUT No one disputes that in the short run happiness responds in an intuitive way to news about lifetime utility. Thus, we argue that an important component of happiness is due to recent news about lifetime utility.
118
118 The News and Happiness Axioms 1.Happiness at time t is a function of the other ultimate goods, S, C and B, an additional state variable vector J (unobserved?) an additional control variable vector Q, and the history of realized lifetime utility v through time t. --Holding all other arguments of happiness fixed, the agent is 2. Happier if current expected lifetime utility is of a preferred future. 3. Less happy if past expected lifetime utility was of a preferred future.
119
119 Simultaneous Determination of Utility and Happiness News and Happiness Axiom 4 is an ordinal version of the kind of assumptions that guarantee a contraction mapping, so that there is a well-defined solution to the simultaneous determination of utility and happiness. Although preferences over ultimate goods exhibit intertemporal expected utility, the derived preferences over the fundamentals (S, J)=K and (C,Q)=X can exhibit reference- dependence and loss aversion as in Prospect Theory.
120
120 Lifetime Utility in the Additively Separable Case
121
121 The Innovation ι in Lifetime Utility v (Additive Separability, Observed K) Note about the lifetime utility innovation: so
122
122 News and Happiness Axioms + Additive Separability Imply Axiom 2→ Axiom 3→
123
123 Baseline Mood M and Elation e
124
124 The Elation Theory of Happiness
125
125 The Elation Theory of Happiness (In Words) Experienced happiness is the sum of two components: elation: short-run happiness that depends on recent news about lifetime utility baseline mood: long-run happiness that is the output of a household production function (like health, entertainment, or nutrition.)
126
126 Key Implications of the Happiness and News Axioms A theory of happiness can be described in terms of the objects that are well-defined by revealed preference: –The fundamentals (state and control variables and outputs of household production functions) that people care about and –The history of which indifference curves for lifetime plans one has been on. Old news about the future matters less for happiness than recent news about the future.
127
127 Loss Aversion from Elation Theory: Happiness Additively Separable with Elation Concave in Lifetime Utility Innovations U(K,X,H,A)=F(K,X)+M(K,X) +α 0 min(ι t, ι t /2) + α 1 min(ι t-1, ι t-1 /2) + …
128
128 Elation-Independence: Additively Separable Happiness with Elation Linear in Lifetime Utility Innovations U(K,X,H)=u(K,X)+M(K,X) +α 0 ι t + α 1 ι t-1 + …
129
129 Factual Mistakes about Happiness Need Not Cause Decision Mistakes Given rational expectations, adding a linear combination of lifetime utility innovations to the utility function has no effect on the preferences represented. In this case, mistakes about the rate of hedonic adaptation cause no harm to utility maximization. However, mistakes about the controllable determinants of baseline mood will cause material harm.
130
130 Elation and Hedonic Adaptation Because it is based on recent news, elation fades, –News doesn’t stay news for very long. –The initial burst of elation dissipates once the full import of news is emotionally and cognitively processed. –This can help explain why, in the long run, becoming better off may not lead to greater happiness.
131
131 The Evolutionary Psychology of Elation and Dismay Functionally, elation and dismay may motivate cognitive processing—much like curiosity. –Elation: after good news, it pays to think what you did right, so you can do it again think how to take advantage of the new opportunities –Dismay: after bad news, it pays to think what you did wrong, so you can avoid doing it again think how to mitigate the harm of the bad news –Curiosity: after news that is neither clearly good nor bad, it pays to learn more for the sake of option value
132
132 The Evolutionary Psychology of Hedonic Adaptation Analogy: Adjustments in the pupil of the eye protect the eye and enhance sensitivity. Protect: Being too happy or too sad has physical costs. Hedonic adaptation protects from these costs. Enhance Sensitivity: “Hedonic adaptation may also increase our sensitivity to, and motivation to make, local changes in our objective circumstances….” (Frederick and Loewenstein)
133
133 Speculations on The Evolutionary Psychology of Baseline Mood High social rank makes it safe to look more for opportunities than for dangers. –Thus, it makes sense to stimulate the same machinery turned on by the receipt of good news. Optimists and pessimists need each other. Quirks in the system? –Pinker’s cheesecake
134
134 The Trend in Utility: Choose between 1955 and 2005 The electronics revolution and the Internet have vastly expanded access to a rapidly growing quantity of culture and science. Crime, teenage pregnancy and drug abuse worsened at first but now trend downward. Greater equality between races and sexes. War on Terror better than Cold War. Better medical care and greater longevity.
135
135 Life Expectancy
136
136 Would you want to go back to the way things used to be? –No computers or electronics –No Ben and Jerry’s –No Harry Potter –No Beatles music yet released –Jim Crow, strong male dominance –Cold War –Few modern drugs
137
137 Elation and Loss Aversion There is evidence that happiness rises less with good news than it falls with bad news. Assume also that the duration of the effect of bad news on happiness is at least as long. The greater effect of bad news, combined with a preference for happiness, implies loss-aversion, a key aspect of Prospect Theory. Thus, loss aversion (=first-order risk aversion) can arise from rational preferences over one’s own emotions. Here, the agent needs to understand happiness.
138
138 Applying Price Theory to Elation For given nonlinearity in happiness as a function of news, people should exhibit more first-order risk aversion if they 1.care more about happiness and 2.believe that their happiness will be affected a lot, for a long-time by events
139
139 Anticipation Effects Empirically, seasonals should capture most of the anticipation effects that are not idiosyncratic. Theoretically, anticipation effects can arise from a multiple-agent model of the psyche, where some agents have high utility discount rates. Different information sets? Model happiness for multiple agents in the same way as for a unified self. Even when an agent is not in charge, it cares about events. Happiness reporting: agent in charge, frequency weighted average.
140
140 Can Manipulating One’s Perceptions Raise Utility? With elation in the utility function, manipulating ones perception of lifetime utility innovations becomes an issue. –Lowering expectations is mostly a wash because it lowers happiness now in order to raise happiness later. It may also interfere with optimization. –The greatest potential gain from manipulating one’s perceptions is to lower one’s memory of past expectations. (“Attitude of gratitude”)
141
141 Manipulating Perceptions of Locus of Control Elation may respond more to news about whether one’s choices worked out than to news about things beyond one’s control. This would make it possible to manipulate elation by labeling good events as due to one’s efforts, while bad events were beyond one’s control.
142
142
143
143 Hedonic Adaptation is Not the Same Thing as Habit Formation Hedonic adaptation is a statement about happiness, as measured by psychologists. Habit formation is a statement about utility, as measured by economists. If happiness were equal to flow utility, data on hedonic adaptation would imply very strong habit formation.
144
144 Evidence on Habit Formation Constantinides Form: 1. Joseph Lupton estimates θ≈.75 based on portfolio choices 2. Impulse responses for consumption choices suggest θ close to zero unless the lags in the habit H are very long. 3. Because of the speed of hedonic adaptation, long lags are inconsistent with U=Affect.
145
145 Modeling Choice: Habit Formation or Just Hedonic Adaptation? 1. Equivalent to 2. Let’s keep the economic theory simple and put the complexity in the utility-happiness relationship. a. It’s clearer and simpler. b. It avoids the misleading impression that there is anything wrong with the more traditional functional form. Suppose and and happiness=first difference of flow utility.
146
146 Does Habit Formation Affect the Choice between 1955 and 2005? To include the effects of habit formation on the decision, imagine you had to give your newborn, whom you care a lot about, up for adoption. Which world you would want your newborn to grow up in? (cf. John Rawls) –Beware of nostalgia. –Remember the problems that have now been partly or wholly resolved. –Hold relative social rank constant. –Think about relative mortality rates.
147
147 (Long-Run) Happiness and Health Like health, happiness can be measured independently is only one argument of the flow utility function depends on different things than flow utility does (or on the same things with different weights) has a complex household production function
148
148 Utility≠Happiness Summary of the Argument a.If only innovations in lifetime utility mattered for happiness, maximizing happiness and maximizing lifetime utility would be equivalent. b.Focusing on only changes leaves out Rawlsian preferences. c.Any predictable effect of choice variables on happiness implies innovations in lifetime utility are not the only component of happiness. d.People who knowingly, thoughtfully and without regret choose not to maximize long-run happiness indicate that utility≠happiness for them.
149
149 The Standard View in Psychology Currently, the standard view among psychologists and most economists working with happiness data—articulated most forcefully by Daniel Kahneman—is that a present discounted value of measured happiness is a good indicator of what people should be maximizing. To the extent that people are maximizing something else, it is viewed as a mistake. Factual mistakes people make in predicting their own future happiness are thought to be an important reason people make these optimization mistakes. (Return to this below.)
150
150 Our View We are questioning this orthodoxy. When well-informed and thoughtful, we view people’s choices as the best indication of their individual welfare. People do often make optimization errors. But much of what this orthodoxy takes as evidence of optimization errors, we take as evidence that utility and “happiness” are not the same thing.
151
151 Relationship to the Orthodoxy of Other Happiness Researchers People value happiness (and will sacrifice other goods for it) versus People should be maximizing happiness (economists often interpret this as saying that happiness is the true utility function).
152
152 Factual Mistakes about Happiness Need Not Cause Decision Mistakes Given rational expectations, adding a linear combination of lifetime utility innovations to the utility function has no effect on the preferences represented. In this case, mistakes about the rate of hedonic adaptation cause no harm to utility maximization. However, mistakes about the controllable determinants of baseline mood will cause material harm.
153
153 Factual Mistakes about Happiness Need Not Cause Decision Mistakes Given rational expectations, adding a linear combination of lifetime utility innovations to the utility function has no effect on the preferences represented. In this case, mistakes about the rate of hedonic adaptation cause no harm to utility maximization. However, mistakes about the controllable determinants of baseline mood will cause material harm.
154
154 Can Happiness Data Alone Diagnose Optimization Mistakes? No. Happiness data alone cannot diagnose a mistake without strong assumptions about the relationship between utility and happiness. Even the relevance of mistakes in predicting future happiness depends on the relationship between happiness and utility. In Section 8 C, we illustrate how people could make mistakes in the impulse response pattern of future happiness without impairing optimization at all.
155
155 Applying Price Theory to Baseline Mood: The Demand for Prozac If you learn more about the household production function for happiness, your behavior will change in a direction that takes advantage of that to raise happiness. Example: Demand for Prozac will go up if information arrives that it is more effective in raising happiness than previously thought (with no new information about side effects). Demand will go down if information arrives that it is less effective at raising happiness than previously thought.
156
156 The Validity of Self-Reported Happiness Correlated with observer ratings of happiness structured coding of facial expressions electrical measures of face muscle activation voice tone skin conductance, heart rate, blood pressure, etc. writing speed judgment of probabilities word association and word completion startle reflex left pre-frontal cortex activity (which can also be induced by seeing pictures of a smiling baby and reduced by seeing pictures of a deformed baby)
Similar presentations
© 2025 SlidePlayer.com. Inc.
All rights reserved.