Download presentation
Presentation is loading. Please wait.
Published byChristine Conley Modified over 9 years ago
1
Week 2 - Friday
2
What did we talk about last time? Predicate logic Negation Multiple quantifiers
4
There are two lengths of rope Each one takes exactly one hour to burn completely The ropes are not the same lengths as each other Neither rope burns at a consistent speed (10% of a rope could take 90% of the burn time, etc.) How can you burn the ropes to measure out exactly 45 minutes of time?
5
When doing a negation, negate the predicate and change the universal quantifier to existential or vice versa Formally: ~( x, P(x)) x, ~P(x) ~( x, P(x)) x, ~P(x) Thus, the negation of "Every dragon breathes fire" is "There is one dragon that does not breathe fire"
6
Argue the following: "Every unicorn has five legs" First, let's write the statement formally Let U(x) be "x is a unicorn" Let F(x) be "x has five legs" x, U(x) F(x) Its negation is x, ~(U(x) F(x)) We can rewrite this as x, U(x) ~F(x) Informally, this is "There is a unicorn which does not have five legs" Clearly, this is false If the negation is false, the statement must be true
7
The previous slide gives an example of a statement which is vacuously true When we talk about "all things" and there's nothing there, we can say anything we want
8
Recall: Statement: p q Contrapositive:~q ~p Converse:q p Inverse:~p ~q These can be extended to universal statements: Statement: x, P(x) Q(x) Contrapositive: x, ~Q(x) ~P(x) Converse: x, Q(x) P(x) Inverse: x, ~P(x) ~Q(x) Similar properties relating a statement equating a statement to its contrapositive (but not to its converse and inverse) apply
9
The ideas of necessary and sufficient are meaningful for universally quantified statements as well: x, P(x) is a sufficient condition for Q(x) means x, P(x) Q(x) x, P(x) is a necessary condition for Q(x) means x, Q(x) P(x)
11
So far, we have not had too much trouble converting informal statements of predicate logic into formal statements and vice versa Many statements with multiple quantifiers in formal statements can be ambiguous in English Example: “There is a person supervising every detail of the production process.”
12
“There is a person supervising every detail of the production process.” What are the two ways that this could be written formally? Let D be the set of all details of the production process Let P be the set of all people Let S(x,y) mean “x supervises y” y D, x P such that S(x,y) x P, y D such that S(x,y)
13
Intuitively, we imagine that corresponding “actions” happen in the same order as the quantifiers The action for x A is something like, “pick any x from A you want” Since a “for all” must work on everything, it doesn’t matter which you pick The action for y B is something like, “find some y from B” Since a “there exists” only needs one to work, you should try to find the one that matches
14
Is the following statement true? “For all blue items x, there is a green item y with the same shape.” Write the statement formally. Reverse the order of the quantifiers. Does its truth value change? a a c c g g b b d d f f i i k k e e h h j j
15
Given the formal statements with multiple quantifiers for each of the following: There is someone for everyone. All roads lead to some city. Someone in this class is smarter than everyone else. There is no largest prime number.
16
The rules don’t change Simply switch every to and every to Then negate the predicate Write the following formally: “Every rose has a thorn” Now, negate the formal version Convert the formal version back to informal
17
As show before, changing the order of quantifiers can change the truth of the whole statement However, it does not necessarily Furthermore, quantifiers of the same type are commutative: You can reorder a sequence of quantifiers however you want The same goes for Once they start overlapping, however, you can’t be sure anymore
19
Quantification adds new features to an argument The most fundamental is universal instantiation If a property is true for everything in a domain (universal quantifier), it is true for any specific thing in the domain Example: All the party people in the place to be are throwing their hands in the air! Julio is a party person in the place to be Julio is throwing his hands in the air
20
Formally, x, P(x) Q(x) P(a) for some particular a Q(a)Q(a) Example: If any person disses Dr. Dre, he or she disses him or herself Tammy disses Dr. Dre Therefore, Tammy disses herself
21
Much the same as universal modus ponens Formally, x, P(x) Q(x) ~Q(a) for some particular a ~P(a) Example: Every true DJ can skratch Ted Long can’t skratch Therefore, Ted Long is not a true DJ
22
Unsurprisingly, the inverse and the converse of universal conditional statements do not have the same truth value as the original Thus, the following are not valid arguments: If a person is a superhero, he or she can fly. Astronaut John Blaha can fly. Therefore, John Blaha is a superhero. FALLACY A good man is hard to find. Osama Bin Laden is not a good man. Therefore, Osama Bin Laden is not hard to find. FALLACY
23
We can test arguments using Venn diagrams To do so, we draw diagrams for each premise and then try to combine the diagrams Touchable things This
24
All integers are rational numbers is not rational Therefore, is not an integer rational numbers integers rational numbers integers
25
All tigers are cats Panthro is a cat Therefore, Panthro is a tiger cats tigers cats Panthro cats tigers cats tigers Panthro
26
Diagrams can be useful tools However, they don’t offer the guarantees that pure logic does Note that the previous slide makes the converse error unless you are very careful with your diagrams
28
Proofs and counterexamples Basic number theory
29
Assignment 1 is due tonight at midnight Read Chapter 4 Start on Assignment 2
Similar presentations
© 2024 SlidePlayer.com. Inc.
All rights reserved.