Presentation is loading. Please wait.

Presentation is loading. Please wait.

Behavioural and Social Explanations of Tax Evasion Nigar Hashimzade University of Reading Gareth D. Myles University of Exeter Frank Page Indiana University.

Similar presentations


Presentation on theme: "Behavioural and Social Explanations of Tax Evasion Nigar Hashimzade University of Reading Gareth D. Myles University of Exeter Frank Page Indiana University."— Presentation transcript:

1 Behavioural and Social Explanations of Tax Evasion Nigar Hashimzade University of Reading Gareth D. Myles University of Exeter Frank Page Indiana University Matthew Rablen Brunel University Financial support from the ESRC/HMRC/HMT is gratefully acknowledged

2 Introduction An understanding of the individual tax compliance decision is important for revenue services Their aim is to design policy instruments to reduce the tax gap Tax evasion is an area where orthodox analysis has been challenged by behavioural economics Non-expected utility theory Social interaction

3 Standard Model The probability of being detected is p Taxpayer chooses declaration X to maximize expected utility max {X} E[U(X)] = [1 – p]U(Y n ) + pU(Y c ) Where Y n = Y – tX = [1 – t]Y + tE Y c = [1 – t]Y – Ft[Y – X] = [1 – t]Y – FtE The sufficient condition for evasion to take place (X < Y) is p < 1/[1 + F]

4 Standard Model The evasion decision can be written as max {E} E[U(E)] = [1 – p]U([1 – t]Y + tE) + pU([1 – t]Y – FtE ) So it follows that E = [1/t]  (. ) The result that compliance rises as t increases runs counter to "intuition" and has mixed empirical support Problem of separating aggregate and individual effects Weakness of experimental evidence

5 Behavioural Approach Behavioural economics can be seen as a loosening of modelling restrictions Two different directions can be taken: (i) Use an alternative to expected utility theory (ii) Reconsider the context in which decisions are taken The consequences of making such changes are now considered

6 Non-Expected Utility There are several non-expected utility models These have the general form V(X) = w 1 (p, 1 – p)v(Y c ) + w 2 (p, 1 – p)v(Y nc ) w 1 (p, 1 – p) and w 2 (p, 1 – p) are translations of p and 1 – p (probability weighting functions) v(. ) is some translation of U(. ) Different representations are special cases of this general form

7 Prospect Theory Prospect theory does three things Prospect theory (i) Translates the probabilities (ii) Assumes payoff is convex in losses and concave in gains (iii) Payoffs are measured relative to a reference point, R

8 Prospect Theory Yaniv (1999) studies the consequence of paying a tax advance With a tax advance of D Yaniv (1999) Use Y – D as the reference point D – tX is the gain if evasion is successful is the loss if evasion is unsuccessful

9 Prospect Theory Observe that D – tX is achieved for sure So write objective as Recall that prospect theory has v convex for losses and concave for gains Yaniv analyzes the comparative statics of the necessary condition

10 Prospect Theory Consider the power function First assume that D > tY The next slides illustrates V Y for the parameter values Y = 1, t = 0.2, p = 0.1, F = 2, D = 0.3

11 Prospect Theory

12 For the power function we can prove:prove "If there is an interior solution to the first-order condition it must be a minimum" The same comments (and result) apply to other functional forms The assumptions of prospect theory combine to create analytical problems

13 Prospect Theory Two figures for D < tY β = 0.5, γ = 4 p = 0.25, F = 4 p = 0.25, F = 20

14 Prospect Theory al-Nowaihi and Dhami (2007) argue that (i) The reference point should be R = (1 – t)Y (ii) Standard prospect theory should be used For this objective it can be shown A different reference point might change the result

15 Positive Results One way to make progress is to assume the probability of detection depends on declared income Within the prospect theory framework V PT = w ⁺ (1–p(X))v(t(Y – X)) + w ⁻ (p(X))v(–Ft(Y – X)) An appropriate form of p(X) can make the objective strictly concave Consider the power function of v( ) and p(X) = αp ₀ X/Y

16 Positive Results Now combine the Yaniv model with linear probability p L (X) = α[1 – (1-p ₀ )(X/Y)] Advance payment below the true tax liability ( D < tY ) t = 0.2, X/Y = 0.74, p = 0.236 t = 0.3, X/Y = 0.50, p= 0.45 Solid: t = 0.2 Dashed: t = 0.3

17 Social Interaction Social interaction allows information to be transmitted through a network This information affects evasion behaviour by changing beliefs The network is determined endogenously through choices that are made The choices are: Occupation (employed or self-employed) Level of evasion if self-employed

18 Occupational Choice Assume that a choice is made between employment and self-employment Employment is safe (wage is fixed) but tax cannot be evaded (UK is PAYE) Self-employment is risky (outcome random) but permits provides opportunity to evade Selection into self-employment is dependent on personal characteristics

19 Occupational Choice A project is a pair {v b, v g } with v b < v g An individual is described by a triple {w,  q} Evasion level is chosen after outcome of project is known So in state i, i = b, g, E i solves max EU i = pU((1–t)v i – FtE i ) + (1–p)U((1–t) v i +tE i ) The payoff from self-employment is EU s = (1–q) EU b (E b *) + qEU g (E g *)

20 Occupational Choice Occupational choice compares payoffs from the alternatives Self-employment is chosen if EU s (q, v b, v g ) > U e (w) What is the outcome in this setting? (i) Assume CRRA utility U = Y (1 –  ) /(1 –  ) (ii) Assume a uniform distribution for ( , q, w)

21 Occupational Choice Employment above the locus Self-employment below the locus The less risk-averse choose self- employment But these people will also evade more Separation of population p = 0.5, t = 0.25, F = 0.75, v b = 0.5, v g = 2, q = 0.5 Employed Self-employed

22 Occupational Choice The aggregate level of evasion can be increasing in the tax rate This is the consequence of intensive/extensive margins The result extends to borrowing to invest E t E t Aggregate evasion With borrowing

23 Social Interaction A network is a symmetric matrix A of 0 s and 1 s (bi- directional links) The network shown is described by 1 2 3 4

24 Social Interaction Each period an action is chosen The network is revised as a consequence of chosen actions A random selection of meetings occur (a matrix C of 0 s, 1 s) Set of permissible meetings is determined by the network ( M = A.*C ) At a meeting information is exchanged Beliefs are updated

25 Tax Evasion Network There are n individuals Individual characteristics { , w, p, q, v b, v g } are randomly drawn at the outset A choice is made between e and s If s is chosen outcome b or g is randomly realised Given the outcome evasion decision is made Those in s are then randomly audited

26 Tax Evasion Network If audited p i goes to 1 other p i decays p i =  p i,  ≤ 1 Type s only meet type s Links in network evolve as a consequence of choice Meetings occur randomly between linked individuals Information on p is exchanged p i =  p i + (1 –  ) p j

27 Results The model has been run for CRRA utility n = 1000,  = 100  uniform on [0, 10], True audit probability a = 0.05  = 0.95,  = 0.75 t = 0.25, F = 1.5  p Mean audit probability (belief)

28 Results Employed Mean risk aversion Self-employed Mean risk aversion  

29 Results The outcome is little changed if decay is increased Figure uses  = 0.25 The average belief about audit probability remains high  p

30 Conclusions Non-expected utility delivers nothing that is not given by adopting subjective probabilities in the EU model It requires variable probability to reverse the tax result Occupational choice selects those who will evade into situations where evasion is possible Social interaction can lead subjective probability to differ from objective probability


Download ppt "Behavioural and Social Explanations of Tax Evasion Nigar Hashimzade University of Reading Gareth D. Myles University of Exeter Frank Page Indiana University."

Similar presentations


Ads by Google