Download presentation
Presentation is loading. Please wait.
Published byClaribel Hall Modified over 9 years ago
1
Proper Scoring Rules and Prospect Theory August 20, 2007 SPUDM, Warsaw, Poland Topic: Our chance estimates of Hillary Clinton to become next president of the US. H: Hillary will win. not-H: someone else. Peter P. Wakker Theo Offerman Joep Sonnemans Gijs van de Kuilen
2
Proper scoring rules: beautiful tool to measure subjective probabilities ("read minds"; see later). Developed in 1950s. Based on theory of those days: expected value. Still widely applied today; never been updated yet … (prospect theory …); such updating is getting high time! Mutual benefits: Proper scoring rules Prospect theory 2
3
Proper scoring rules explained: (Suggestion for whole lecture: don't read the algebra; numerical examples will clarify.) You choose 0 r 1, as you like. We call r your reported probability of H (Hillary president). You receive following prospect H not-H 1 – (1– r) 2 1 – r 2 What r should you choose? 3
4
First assume EV. After some algebra: p true subjective probability; optimizing p(1 – (1– r) 2 ) + (1–p) (1–r 2 ); 1 st order condition 2p(1–r) – 2r(1–p) = 0; r = p. Optimal r = your true subjective probability of Hillary winning. Easy in algebraic sense. Conceptually: !!! Wow !!! de Finetti (1962) and Brier (1950) were the first neuro-scientists! 4
5
"Bayesian truth serum" (Prelec, Science, 2005). Superior to elicitations through preferences . Superior to elicitations through indifferences ~ (BDM). Widely used: Hanson (Nature, 2002), Prelec (Science 2005). In accounting (Wright 1988), Bayesian statistics (Savage 1971), business (Stael von Holstein 1972), education (Echternacht 1972), medicine (Spiegelhalter 1986), psychology (Liberman & Tversky 1993; McClelland & Bolger 1994), experimental economics (Nyarko & Schotter 2002). Remember: based on expected value! We want to introduce these very nice features into prospect theory. 5
6
Survey Part I. Theoretical Analysis. Part II. Theoretical Analysis "reversed." Part III. Implementation in an experiment. 6
7
Part I. Deriving r from Theories ------------------------------------------------------- EV (already done) & 3 deviations. ------------------------------------------------------- Two deviations from EV regarding risk attitude (that we want to correct for): 1. Utility curvature; 2. Probability weighting; ------------------------------------------------------- Third deviation concerning subjective beliefs (that we want to measure): 3. Nonadditive beliefs and ambiguity aversion. 7
8
Let us assume that you strongly believe in Hillary (charming husband …) Your "true" subj. prob.(H) = 0.75. Before turning to deviations, graph for EV. EV: Then your optimal r H = 0.75. 8
9
9 Reported probability R(p) = r H as function of true probability p, under: nonEU 0.69 EU 0.61 r EV EV r nonEU r nonEUA r nonEUA : nonexpected utility for unknown probabilities ("Ambiguity"). (c) nonexpected utility for known probabilities, with U(x) = x 0.5 and with w(p) as common; (b) expected utility with U(x) = x (EU); (a) expected value (EV); r EU next p. go to p. 12, Example EU go to p. 16, Example nonEU 0.25 0.50 0.75 1 0 p R(p) 0 0.50 1 0.25 0.75 go to p. 20, Example nonEUA
10
So far we assumed EV (as does everyone using proper scoring rules, but as does no decision theorist in SPUDM...) Deviation 1 from EV: EU with U nonlinear Now optimize pU ( 1 – (1– r) 2 ) + ( 1 – p )U (1 – r 2 ) 10
11
11 U´(1–r 2 ) U´(1 – (1–r) 2 ) (1–p) p + p r = Reversed (and explicit) expression: U´(1–r 2 ) U´(1 – (1–r) 2 ) (1–r) r + r p =
12
How bet on Hillary? [ Expected Utility ]. EV: r EV = 0.75. Expected utility, U(x) = x: r EU = 0.69. You now bet less on Hillary. Closer to safety (Winkler & Murphy 1970). 12 go to p. 9, with figure of R(p)
13
Deviation 2 from EV : nonexpected utility for given probabilities ( Allais 1953, Machina 1982, Kahneman & Tversky 1979, Quiggin 1982, Schmeidler 1989, Gilboa 1987, Gilboa & Schmeidler 1989, Gul 1991, Levy-Garboua 2001, Luce & Fishburn 1991, Tversky & Kahneman 1992, Birnbaum 2005) 13 For two-gain prospects, virtually all those theories are as follows: For r 0.5, nonEU(r) = w(p)U ( 1 – (1–r) 2 ) + ( 1–w(p) ) U(1–r 2 ). r < 0.5, symmetry; soit! Different treatment of highest and lowest outcome: "rank-dependence."
14
14 p w(p) 1 1 0 Figure. The common weighting function w. w(p) = exp(–(–ln(p)) ) for = 0.65. w(1/3) 1/3; 1/3 w(2/3) .51 2/3.51
15
Now 15 U´(1–r 2 ) U´(1 – (1–r) 2 ) ( 1–w(p) ) w(p) + w(p) r = U´(1–r 2 ) U´(1 – (1–r) 2 ) (1–r) r + r p = Reversed (explicit) expression: w –1 ( )
16
How bet on Hillary now? [nonEU with probabilities ]. EV: r EV = 0.75. EU: r EU = 0.69. Nonexpected utility, U(x) = x, w(p) = exp(–(–ln(p)) 0.65 ). r nonEU = 0.61. You bet even less on Hillary. Again closer to safety. 16 go to p. 9, with figure of R(p) Deviations were at level of behavior so far, not of be- liefs. Now for something different; more fundamental.
17
Deviation 3 from EV: Nonadditive Beliefs and Ambiguity. Of different nature than previous two. Not to correct for, but the thing to measure. Unknown probabilities; ambiguity = belief/decision-attitude? (Yet to be settled). How deal with unknown probabilities? Have to give up Bayesian beliefs descriptively. According to some even normatively. 17
18
18 Instead of additive beliefs p = P(H), nonadditive beliefs B(H) (Dempster&Shafer, Tversky&Koehler, etc.) All currently existing decision models: For r 0.5, nonEU(r) = w(B(H))U ( 1 – (1–r) 2 ) + ( 1–w(B(H)) ) U(1–r 2 ). Don't recognize? I s just '92 prospect theory = Schmeidler (1989)! Write W(H) = w(B(H)). Can always write B(H) = w –1 (W(H)). For binary gambles: Pfanzagl 1959; Luce ('00 Chapter 3); Ghirardato & Marinacci ('01, "biseparable").
19
19 U´(1–r 2 ) U´(1 – (1–r) 2 ) ( 1–w(B(H)) ) w(B(H)) + w(B(H)) r H = U´(1–r 2 ) U´(1 – (1–r) 2 ) (1–r) r + r B(H) = Reversed (explicit) expression: w –1 ( )
20
How bet on Hillary now? [Ambiguity, nonEUA]. r EV = 0.75. r EU = 0.69. r nonEU = 0.61 (under plausible assumptions). Similarly, r nonEUA = 0.52. r's are close to insensitive "fifty-fifty." "Belief" component B(H) = w –1 (W) = 0.62. 20 go to p. 9, with figure of R(p)
21
Our contribution: through proper scoring rules with "risk correction" we can easily measure B(H). Debates about interpretation of B(H): ambiguity attitude /=/ beliefs can come later, and we do not enter. We come closer to beliefs than traditional analyses of proper scoring rules, that completely ignore all deviations from EV. 21
22
22 We reconsider reversed explicit expressions: U´(1–r 2 ) U´(1 – (1–r) 2 ) (1–r) r + r p = w –1 ( ) U´(1–r 2 ) U´(1 – (1–r) 2 ) (1–r) r + r B(H) = w –1 ( ) Corollary. p = B(H) if related to the same r!! Part II. Deriving Theoretical Things from Empirical Observations of r
23
23 Example (participant 25) stock 20, CSM certificates dealing in sugar and bakery- ingredients. Reported probability: r = 0.75 91 For objective probability p = 0.70, also reported probability r = 0.75. Conclusion: B(elief) of ending in bar is 0.70! We simply measure the R(p) curves, and use their inverses: is risk correction.
24
24 Our proposal takes the best of several worlds! Need not measure U,W, and w. Get "canonical probability" without measuring indifferences (BDM …; Holt 2006). Calibration without needing many repeated observations. Do all that with no more than simple proper- scoring-rule questions.
25
25 Directly implementable empirically. We did so in an experiment, and found plausible results.
26
Part III. Experimental Test of Our Correction Method 26
27
Method Participants. N = 93 students. Procedure. Computarized in lab. Groups of 15/16 each. 4 practice questions. 27
28
28 Stimuli 1. First we did proper scoring rule for unknown probabilities. 72 in total. For each stock two small intervals, and, third, their union. Thus, we test for additivity.
29
29 Stimuli 2. Known probabilities: Two 10-sided dies thrown. Yield random nr. between 01 and 100. Event E: nr. 75 (p = 3/4 = 15/20) (etc.). Done for all probabilities j/20. Motivating subjects. Real incentives. Two treatments/conditions. 1. All-pay. Points paid for all questions. 6 points = €1. Average earning €15.05. 2. One-pay (random-lottery system). One question, randomly selected afterwards, played for real. 1 point = €20. Average earning: €15.30.
30
30 Results
31
31 Average correction curves
32
32 0.8 0.9 1 -2.0-1.5-0.50.00.51.01.5 ρ F(ρ) treatment one treatment all Individual corrections
33
33 Corrections reduce nonadditivity, but more than half remains: ambiguity generates more deviation from additivity than risk. Fewer corrections for Treatment t=ALL. Better use that if no correction possible.
34
Summary and Conclusion Modern decision theories: proper scoring rules are heavily biased. We correct for those biases, with benefits for proper-scoring rule community and for prospect-theory community. Experiment: correction improves quality; reduces deviations from ("rational"?) Bayesian beliefs. We do not remove all deviations from Baye- sian beliefs. Beliefs seem to be genuinely nonadditive/nonBayesian/sensitive-to- ambiguity. 34
Similar presentations
© 2025 SlidePlayer.com. Inc.
All rights reserved.