Presentation is loading. Please wait.

Presentation is loading. Please wait.

Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 13.

Similar presentations


Presentation on theme: "Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 13."— Presentation transcript:

1 Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 13

2 1  Breach of contract  Reliance  How liability for breach creates incentive for both, paradox of compensation  Default rules  C&U: impute the rule the parties would have wanted and apply that  That’s whatever rule would have been efficient – allocating each risk to whoever can bear it most cheaply  Ayres/Gertner: use default rule to “penalize” one or both  Create incentive for one party to reveal information, or for both parties to address contingency in contract So far in contract law…

3 2  Old urban legend: A man bought a box of extremely rare and expensive cigars, and insured them against loss or damage. After smoking them, he filed an insurance claim, saying they had been destroyed in 20 separate small fires. The insurance company refused to pay, the man sued and won. But as he was leaving the courtroom, he was arrested on 20 counts of arson.  Serious question: If the intent of a contract is clear, but different from the literal meaning, which should be enforced? Discussion question

4 3 When should a contract not be enforced?

5 4  Going back to property law…  Coase Theorem: to get efficient outcomes, we should let people trade whenever they want to  But also saw some exceptions – some trades that aren’t, and shouldn’t, be allowed  Selling enriched uranium to a terrorist  Similarly with contract law…  First day: to get efficient outcomes, enforce any contract both parties wanted enforced  But next, we’ll see exceptions – contracts which shouldn’t be enforced, due to externalities or market failures/transaction costs When should voluntary trade not be allowed?

6 5  Obvious: contract to buy a kilo of cocaine is unenforceable Example of an unenforceable contract: a contract which breaks the law

7 6  Obvious: contract to buy a kilo of cocaine is unenforceable  Less obvious: otherwise-legal contract whose real purpose is to circumvent a law  Legal doctrine: derogation of public policy  Derogate, verb. detract from; curtail application of (a law)  Applies to contracts which could only be performed by breaking law…  …but also to “innocent” contracts whose purpose is to get around a law or regulation Example of an unenforceable contract: a contract which breaks the law

8 7  Labor unions required by law to negotiate “in good faith”  Recent NBA labor troubles  Old CBA: 57% of “basketball-related income” went to player salaries  Owners were offering less than 50%, players demanding 53%...  Imagine the following contract:  “For the next 50 years, if the NBAPA accepts a CBA paying less than 55% of BRI in player salaries, then we also agree that all non-retired players will work for you as coal miners every offseason at federal minimum wage.”  Purpose is purely to “bind hands” in negotiations with ownership  Contract would not be enforced Derogation of public policy – example

9 8  In general: a contract is not enforceable if it cannot be performed without breaking the law  Exception: if promisor knew (and promisee didn’t)  I’m married, my girlfriend in California doesn’t know; I promise her I’ll marry her, she quits her job and moves to Madison  My company agrees to supply a product that we can’t produce without violating a safety or environmental regulation  Keeping either promise would require breaking the law…  …but I’d still be liable for damages for breach  Like in Ayres and Gertner: default rule penalizes better- informed party for withholding information Derogation of public policy

10 9  Talked earlier about default rules  Default rules apply if no other rule is specified…  …but can be contracted around  Rules like “derogation of public policy” cannot be contracted around  Parties to a contract can’t say, “even though this type of contract would normally not be valid, this one is”  Rules which always apply: immutable rules, or mandatory rules, or regulations  Fifth purpose of contract law is to minimize transaction costs of negotiating contracts by supplying efficient default rules and regulations. Default rules versus regulations

11 10 Ways to get out of a contract

12 11  Formation defense  Claim that a valid contract does not exist  (Example: no consideration)  Performance excuse  Yes, a valid contract was created  But circumstances have changed and I should be allowed to not perform without penalty  Most doctrines for invalidating a contract can be explained as either…  Individuals agreeing to the contract were not rational, or  Transaction cost or market failure Formation Defenses and Performance Excuses

13 12  Courts will not enforce contracts with people who can’t be presumed to be rational  Children  Legally insane  Incompetence  One party was “not competent to enter into the agreement”  No “meeting of the minds” One formation defense: incompetence

14 13  If courts won’t enforce a contract signed by someone who wasn’t competent…  What if you signed a contract while drunk?  You need to have been really, really, really drunk to get out of a contract  (“Intoxicated to the extent of being unable to comprehend the nature and consequences of the instrument he executed”)  Lucy v. Zehmer, Virginia Sup Ct 1954 So…

15 14  Zehmer and his wife owned a farm (“the Ferguson farm”), Lucy had been trying to buy it for some time  While out drinking, Lucy offers $50,000, Zehmer responds, “You don’t have $50,000”  “We hereby agree to sell to W.O. Lucy the Ferguson Farm complete for $50,000 00, title satisfactory to buyer.” Lucy v. Zehmer

16 15  Zehmer and his wife owned a farm (“the Ferguson farm”), Lucy had been trying to buy it for some time  While out drinking, Lucy offers $50,000, Zehmer responds, “You don’t have $50,000”  “We hereby agree to sell to W.O. Lucy the Ferguson Farm complete for $50,000 00, title satisfactory to buyer.” Lucy v. Zehmer

17 16  So, you can be pretty drunk and still be bound by the contract you signed  Might think “meeting of the minds” would be impossible  But imagine what would happen if the rule went the other way Lucy v. Zehmer

18 17  So, you can be pretty drunk and still be bound by the contract you signed  Might think “meeting of the minds” would be impossible  But imagine what would happen if the rule went the other way  Borat lawsuits  Julie Hilden, “Borat Sequel: Legal Proceedings Against Not Kazahk Journalist for Make Benefit Guileless Americans In Film”  Moral of the story: don’t get drunk with people who might ask you to sign a contract Lucy v. Zehmer

19 18 Another formation defense: dire constraints

20 19  Necessity  I’m about to starve, someone offers me a sandwich for $10,000  My boat’s about to sink, someone offers me a ride to shore for $1,000,000  Contract would not be upheld: I signed it out of necessity  Duress  Other party is responsible for situation I’m in  “I made him an offer he couldn’t refuse”  Contract signed at gunpoint would not be legally enforceable Dire constraints

21 20 source: http://news.yahoo.com/man-sues-former-hostages-says- broke-promise-190902970.html Duress

22 21  Example  Mugger threatens to kill you unless you give him $100  You write him a check  Do you have to honor the agreement?  “Efficiency requires enforcing a contract if both parties wanted it to be enforceable”  He did – he wants your $100  You did – you’d rather pay $100 than be killed  So why not enforce it?  Makes muggings more profitable  leads to more muggings  Tradeoff: refuse to enforce a Pareto-improving trade, in order to avoid incentive for bad behavior Friedman on duress

23 22  Example  Mugger threatens to kill you unless you give him $100  You write him a check  Do you have to honor the agreement?  “Efficiency requires enforcing a contract if both parties wanted it to be enforceable”  He did – he wants your $100  You did – you’d rather pay $100 than be killed  So why not enforce it?  Makes muggings more profitable  leads to more muggings  Tradeoff: refuse to enforce a Pareto-improving trade, in order to avoid incentive for bad behavior Friedman on duress

24 23  Same logic doesn’t work for necessity  You get caught in a storm on your $1,000,000 sailboat  Tugboat offers to tow you to shore for $900,000  (Otherwise he’ll save your life but let your boat sink)  Duress: if we enforce contract, incentive for more crimes  Necessity: if we enforce contract, incentive for more tugboats to be available to rescue sailboats  Why is that bad? What about necessity?

25 24 What about necessity? “Should I motor around looking for sailboats to save?”  Social cost = private cost = value of my time  Social benefit = probability x (value of boat – cost of tow)  Private benefit = probability x (price I can charge – cost of tow)  If tugboat captain can charge the whole value of the boat, he spends efficient amount of time saving sailboats!  So maybe we should enforce this contract…

26 25 What about necessity? “Should I sail today?”  Suppose tugboat is there to rescue me if there’s a storm  Social benefit = private benefit = how much I enjoy sailing  Social cost = probability x cost of tow  Private cost = probability x price he can charge  If tugboat captain can only charge cost of tow, I sail efficient amount  If he can charge the whole value of the boat, I undersail!

27 26  Same transaction sets incentives on both parties  Price that would be efficient for one decision, is inefficient for other  “Put the incentive where it would do the most good”  Least inefficient price is somewhere in the middle  And probably not the price that would be negotiated in the middle of a storm! Friedman’s point

28 27  Same transaction sets incentives on both parties  Price that would be efficient for one decision, is inefficient for other  “Put the incentive where it would do the most good”  Least inefficient price is somewhere in the middle  And probably not the price that would be negotiated in the middle of a storm!  So makes sense for courts to overturn contracts signed under necessity, replace them with ex-ante optimal terms  More general point  Single price creates multiple incentives  May be impossible to get efficient behavior in all dimensions Friedman’s point

29 28  Court won’t enforce contracts signed under threat of harm  “Give me $100 or I’ll shoot you”  But many negotiations contain threats  “Give me a raise, or I’ll quit”  “$3,000 is my final offer for the car, take it or I walk”  The difference?  Threat of destruction of value versus failure to create value  A promise is enforceable if extracted as price of cooperating in creating value; not if it was extracted by threat to destroy value Real duress versus fake duress

30 29  Captain hires crew in Seattle for fishing expedition to Alaska  In Alaska, crew demands higher wages or they’ll quit, captain agrees  Back in Seattle, captain refuses to pay the higher wages, claiming he agreed to them under duress  Court ruled for captain  Since crew had already agreed to do the work, no new consideration was given for promise of higher wage Example: Alaska Packers’ Association v Domenico (US Ct App 1902)

31 30 A performance excuse: impossibility

32 31  When performance becomes impossible, should promisor owe damages, or be excused from performing?  A perfect contract would explicitly state who bears each risk  Contract may give clues as to how gaps should be filled  Industry custom might be clear  But in some cases, court must fill gap Next doctrine for voiding a contract: impossibility

33 32  In most situations, when neither contract nor industry norm offers guidance, promisor is held liable for breach  But there are exceptions  Change “destroyed a basic assumption on which the contract was made” Next doctrine for voiding a contract: impossibility

34 33  In most situations, when neither contract nor industry norm offers guidance, promisor is held liable for breach  But there are exceptions  Change “destroyed a basic assumption on which the contract was made”  Efficiency requires assigning liability to the party that can bear the risk at least cost  How to determine who that is? Next doctrine for voiding a contract: impossibility

35 34  Friedman offers several bases for making this determination  Spreading losses across many transactions  Moral hazard: who is in better position to influence outcome? Who is the efficient bearer of a particular risk?

36 35  Friedman offers several bases for making this determination  Spreading losses across many transactions  Moral hazard: who is in better position to influence outcome?  Adverse selection: who is more aware of risk, even if he can’t do anything about it?  “…The party with control over some part of the production process is in a better position both to prevent losses and to predict them. It follows that an efficient contract will usually assign the loss associated with something going wrong to the party with control over that particular something.” Who is the efficient bearer of a particular risk?

37 36  Baxendale (shipper) could influence speed of delivery, Hadley could not  So Baxendale was efficient bearer of the risk of delay  Court ruled he didn’t owe damages for lost profits, forcing Hadley to bear much of this risk  Only makes sense as a “penalty default”  Rule creates incentive for Hadley to reveal urgency of this shipment That’s why Hadley v Baxendale was “surprising”

38 37 Contracts based on bad information (may not get to this)

39 38  Four doctrines for invalidating a contract  Fraud  Failure to disclose  Frustration of purpose  Mutual mistake Contracts based on faulty information

40 39  Fraud: one party was deliberately tricked Fraud source: http://www.wyff4.com/r/29030818/detail.htmlhttp://www.wyff4.com/r/29030818/detail.html

41 40  Under the civil law, there is a duty to disclose  If you fail to supply information you should have, contract will be voided – failure to disclose  Less so under the common law  Seller has to share information about hidden dangers…  …but generally not information that makes a product less valuable without making it dangerous  Exception: new products come with “implied warranty of fitness”  Another exception: Obde v Schlemeyer What if you trick someone by withholding information?

42 41  Under common law, seller required to inform buyer about hidden safety risks, generally not other information  But…  Obde v Schlemeyer (1960, Sup Ct of WA)  Seller knew building was infested with termites, did not tell buyer  Termites should have been exterminated immediately to prevent further damage  Court in Obde imposed duty to disclose (awarded damages) Duty to disclose under common law

43 42  Under common law, seller required to inform buyer about hidden safety risks, generally not other information  But…  Obde v Schlemeyer (1960, Sup Ct of WA)  Seller knew building was infested with termites, did not tell buyer  Termites should have been exterminated immediately to prevent further damage  Court in Obde imposed duty to disclose (awarded damages)  Some states require used car dealers to reveal major repairs done, sellers of homes to reveal certain types of defects… Duty to disclose under common law

44 43 Failure to disclose? source: http://kdvr.com/2012/10/26/chinese-man-sues-wife-for-being-ugly-wins-120000/http://kdvr.com/2012/10/26/chinese-man-sues-wife-for-being-ugly-wins-120000/

45 44 Frustration of Purpose  Change in circumstance made the original promise pointless  Coronation Cases  “When a contingency makes performance pointless, assign liability to party who can bear risk at least cost” What if both parties were misinformed?

46 45 Frustration of Purpose  Change in circumstance made the original promise pointless  Coronation Cases  “When a contingency makes performance pointless, assign liability to party who can bear risk at least cost” What if both parties were misinformed? Mutual Mistake  Mutual mistake about facts  Circumstances had already changed, but we didn’t know  Logger buys land with timber on it, but forest fire had wiped out the timber the week before  Mutual mistake about identity  Disagreement over what was being sold

47 46  Hadley v Baxendale (miller and shipper)  Hadley knew shipment was time-critical  But Baxendale was deciding how to ship crankshaft (boat or train)  Party that had information was not the party making decisions  Efficiency generally requires uniting knowledge and control  Contracts that unite knowledge and control are generally efficient, should be upheld  Contracts that separate knowledge and control may be inefficient, should more often be set aside Another principle for allocating risks efficiently: uniting knowledge and control

48 47  Mutual mistake: neither party had correct information  Contract neither united nor separated knowledge and control  Unilateral mistake: one party has mistaken information  I know your car is a valuable antique, you think it’s worthless  You sell it to me at a low price  Contracts based on unilateral mistake are generally upheld Mutual vs. Unilateral Mistake

49 48  Mutual mistake: neither party had correct information  Contract neither united nor separated knowledge and control  Unilateral mistake: one party has mistaken information  I know your car is a valuable antique, you think it’s worthless  You sell it to me at a low price  Contracts based on unilateral mistake are generally upheld  Contracts based on unilateral mistake generally unite knowledge and control  And, enforcing them creates an incentive to gather information Mutual vs. Unilateral Mistake

50 49  War of 1812: British blockaded port of New Orleans  Price of tobacco fell, since it couldn’t be exported  Organ (tobacco buyer) learned the war was over  Immediately negotiated with Laidlaw firm to buy a bunch of tobacco at the depressed wartime price  Next day, news broke the war had ended, price of tobacco went up, Laidlaw sued  Supreme Court ruled that Organ was not required to communicate his information Unilateral mistake: Laidlaw v Organ (U.S. Supreme Court, 1815)

51 50  Laidlaw v. Organ established: contracts based on unilateral mistake are generally valid  Agrees with efficiency: these contracts typically unite knowledge and control  What about Obde v. Schlemeyer?  The termites case was based on unilateral mistake  Court still upheld contract, but punished seller for hiding information  In that case, contract separated knowledge from control Uniting knowledge and control

52 51  Productive information: information that can be used to produce more wealth  Redistributive information: information that can be used to redistribute wealth in favor of informed party  Cooter and Ulen  Contracts based on one party’s knowledge of productive information should be enforced…  …especially if that knowledge was the result of active investment  Contracts based on one party’s knowledge of purely redistributive information, or fortuitously acquired information, should not be enforced Unilateral mistake: productive versus redistributive information


Download ppt "Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 13."

Similar presentations


Ads by Google