Download presentation
Presentation is loading. Please wait.
Published byAndrew Jefferson Modified over 9 years ago
1
LDK R Logics for Data and Knowledge Representation Propositional Logic Originally by Alessandro Agostini and Fausto Giunchiglia Modified by Fausto Giunchiglia, Rui Zhang and Vincenzo Maltese
2
2 Outline Introduction Syntax Semantics Truth valuation Satisfiability Validity Entailment Logical implication Reasoning Services Normal Forms 2
3
Introduction: propositions All knowledge representation languages deal with sentences Sentences denote propositions (by definition), namely they express something true or false (the mental image of what you mean when you write the sentence) Logic languages deal with propositions Propositional logic is the simplest logic that does this (no individuals, no quantifiers) 3 “All men are mortals”“Obama is the president of the USA” ¬ Mortal ∨ ManPresident INTRODUCTION :: SYNTAX :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING SERVICES :: NORMAL FORMS
4
Introduction: example 4 World SEMANTIC GAP Monkey Mental Model Language L PROPOSITION SENTENCE INTRODUCTION :: SYNTAX :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING SERVICES :: NORMAL FORMS
5
Introduction: the famous triangle 5 CONCEPT (what we have in mind) SYMBOL (what we write) REFERENT (the real object) Monkey stands for refers to symbolizes INTRODUCTION :: SYNTAX :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING SERVICES :: NORMAL FORMS
6
Language (Syntax) Alphabet of symbols: The first step in setting up a formal language is to list the symbols of the alphabet Propositional Logic (PL) is a symbolic language Σ 0 : the alphabet of a PL language 6 Σ0Σ0 Descriptive Logical , , , … Constants one proposition only A, B, C … Variables they can be substituted by any proposition or formula P, Q, ψ … NOTE: not only characters but also words (composed by several characters) like “monkey” are descriptive symbols INTRODUCTION :: SYNTAX :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING SERVICES :: NORMAL FORMS
7
Additional Symbols Auxiliary symbols Parentheses: ( ) Defined symbols Logical defined constants are, for all propositions P: ⊥ (falsehood symbol, false, bottom) ⊥ = df P ∧ ¬P T (truth symbol, true, top)T = df ¬ ⊥ Defined symbols are not strictly necessary However, they increase the usability by reducing the syntactic complexity of propositions 7 INTRODUCTION :: SYNTAX :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING SERVICES :: NORMAL FORMS
8
Formation Rules (FR): well formed formulas Well formed formulas (wff) in PL can be described by the following BNF (*) grammar (codifying the rules): ::= A | B |... | P | Q |... | ⊥ | ⊤ ::= | ¬ | ∧ | ∨ Atomic formulas are also called atomic propositions Wff are propositional formulas (or just propositions) A formula is correct if and only if it is a wff Σ 0 + FR define a propositional language (*) BNF = Backus–Naur form (formal grammar)Backus–Naur form 8 PARSER ψ, PL Yes, ψ is correct! No INTRODUCTION :: SYNTAX :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING SERVICES :: NORMAL FORMS
9
Example: the Monkey-Banana problem Significant data: monkey, bananas, box Significant knowledge: Low, High, Climb, GetBanana All other data and knowledge are irrelevant! Both data and knowledge are codified as (atomic or more complex) formulas in the language Language (any language you want to define): MonkeyLow, BananaHigh, MonkeyClimbBox, MonkeyGetBanana “There is a monkey in a laboratory with some bananas hanging out of reach from the ceiling. A box is available that will enable the monkey to reach the bananas if he climbs on it. The monkey and box have height Low, but if the monkey climbs onto the box he will have height High, the same as the bananas. At this point the monkey can get a banana [...]” 9 INTRODUCTION :: SYNTAX :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING SERVICES :: NORMAL FORMS
10
Examples of formulas 10 FormulaCorrect inLab-Monkey inlab-monkey in-lab-monkey inLab(Monkey) (Monkey ∧ GetBanana) ∨ ¬ High Yes (wff) inLab(Monkey) ∧ P ¬ ∧ Q No NOTE: In PL we do not have individuals (it is not so expressive). Parentheses in inLab(Monkey) are not the auxiliary symbols like in e.g. (Monkey ∧ GetBanana) ∨ ¬ High (problem of ambiguity) INTRODUCTION :: SYNTAX :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING SERVICES :: NORMAL FORMS
11
Propositional Theory Propositional (or sentential) theory A set of propositions It is a (propositional) knowledge base (containing true facts) It corresponds to a TBox (terminology) only, where no meaning is specified yet: it is a syntactic notion Recall that: knowledge is a set of facts, i.e. statements we assumed statements are propositions 11 INTRODUCTION :: SYNTAX :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING SERVICES :: NORMAL FORMS
12
Propositional Theories and Databases A propositional theory is not a database! Propositions don’t show data explicitly (no individuals) In PL the form P(a) must be interpreted as P-a (so the use of form P(a) is ambiguous). Example: In the sentence ‘inLab(Monkey)’, the string ‘Monkey’ does not refer to an individual from some data domain 12 INTRODUCTION :: SYNTAX :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING SERVICES :: NORMAL FORMS
13
Example: the Monkey-Banana problem 13 L = {MonkeyLow, BananaHigh, MonkeyClimbBox, MonkeyGetBanana, , , } T = { (MonkeyLow BananaHigh MonkeyGetBanana) (MonkeyLow MonkeyClimbBox) ( MonkeyLow BananaHigh MonkeyGetBanana)} NOTE: We still need to assign semantics to the symbols in the language. “There is a monkey in a laboratory with some bananas hanging out of reach from the ceiling. A box is available that will enable the monkey to reach the bananas if he climbs on it. The monkey and box have height Low, but if the monkey climbs onto the box he will have height High, the same as the bananas. At this point the monkey can get a banana [...]” INTRODUCTION :: SYNTAX :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING SERVICES :: NORMAL FORMS
14
Semantics means providing an interpretation So far the elements of our propositional language are simply strings of symbols without formal meaning The meanings which are intended to be attached to the symbols and propositions form the intended interpretation ν (nu) of the language 14 INTRODUCTION :: SYNTAX :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING SERVICES :: NORMAL FORMS
15
Semantics: formal model Intensional interpretation We must make sure to assign the formal meanings out of our intended interpretation to the (symbols of the) language, so that formulas (propositions) really express what we intended. The mental model: What we have in mind? In our mind (mental model) we have a set of properties that we associate to propositions. We need to make explicit (as much as possible) what we mean. The formal model This is done by defining a formal model M. Technically: we have to define a pair (M, ⊨ ) for our propositional language Truth-values In PL a sentence A is true (false) iff A denotes a formal object which satisfies (does not satisfy) the properties of the object in the real world. 15 INTRODUCTION :: SYNTAX :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING SERVICES :: NORMAL FORMS
16
Example: Banana (I) Bananas may differ in many ways, but when using the proposition Banana we have in mind some specific properties: e.g. a given shape, a given color... These specific properties determine the intension of the proposition Banana The intentional interpretation of the proposition Banana determines its truth-value (true or false). 16 INTRODUCTION :: SYNTAX :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING SERVICES :: NORMAL FORMS
17
Example: Banana (II) 17 World SEMANTIC GAP Banana Mental Model Language L PROPOSITION What we have in mind? 1) There is at least a banana 2) The banana is yellow 3) The banana has curve shape 4) No matter if opened SENTENCE Banana (Yellow Curve) Language L’ SENTENCE OUR MENTAL MODEL MATCHES WITH THE REAL WORLD, SO THE SENTENCES ARE TRUE INTRODUCTION :: SYNTAX :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING SERVICES :: NORMAL FORMS
18
Example: Banana (III) 18 World SEMANTIC GAP Banana Mental Model Language L PROPOSITION What we have in mind? 1) There is at least a banana 2) The banana is yellow 3) The banana has curve shape 4) No matter if opened SENTENCE Banana (Yellow Curve) Language L’ SENTENCE OUR MENTAL MODEL DOES NOT MATCH WITH THE REAL WORLD, SO THE SENTENCES ARE FALSE INTRODUCTION :: SYNTAX :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING SERVICES :: NORMAL FORMS
19
Example: Banana (IV) 19 I mean banana as something yellow and curve, no matter if partially opened I mean banana as something yellow or red, which can be one or many together, no matter how big they are, and whether they are opened or not FORMAL MODEL M1 FORMAL MODEL M2 TFTF MENTAL MODEL THE WORLD INTRODUCTION :: SYNTAX :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING SERVICES :: NORMAL FORMS
20
Truth-values Definition: a truth valuation on a propositional language L is a mapping ν assigning to each formula A of L a truth value ν (A), namely in the domain D = {T, F} ν (A) = T or F according to the modeler, with A atomic ν (¬A) = T iff ν (A) = F ν (A ∧ B) = T iff ν (A) = T and ν (B) = T ν (A ∨ B) = T iff ν (A) = T or ν (B) = T ν ( ⊥ ) = F (since ⊥ = df P ∧ ¬P) ν ( ⊤ ) = T (since ⊤ = df ¬ ⊥ ) 20 INTRODUCTION :: SYNTAX :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING SERVICES :: NORMAL FORMS
21
Example of truth valuation ν 21 L = {MonkeyLow, BananaHigh, MonkeyClimbBox, MonkeyGetBanana, , , } T = { (MonkeyLow BananaHigh MonkeyGetBanana) (MonkeyLow MonkeyClimbBox) ( MonkeyLow BananaHigh MonkeyGetBanana)} Informal Semantics: “If the monkey is low and the banana is high in position, then the monkey cannot get the banana. “ Formal Semantics: ν (MonkeyLow) = T ν (BananaHigh) = T ν (MonkeyClimbBox) = F ν (MonkeyGetBanana) = F MODEL INTRODUCTION :: SYNTAX :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING SERVICES :: NORMAL FORMS
22
Truth Tables To compute (in polynomial time) truth valuations, the method of truth tables was introduced (Wittgenstein, 1921). Truth tables are well-known: Truth-table (TT) for the logical constants ¬, ∧, ∨ 22 INTRODUCTION :: SYNTAX :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING SERVICES :: NORMAL FORMS
23
Truth Relation (Satisfaction Relation) Let ν be a truth valuation on language L, we define the truth- relation (or satisfaction-relation) ⊨ and write ν ⊨ A (read: ν satisfies A) iff ν (A) = True Given a set of propositions Γ, we define ν ⊨ Γν ⊨ Γ iff if ν ⊨ θ for all formulas θ ∈ Γ 23 INTRODUCTION :: SYNTAX :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING SERVICES :: NORMAL FORMS
24
Model and Satisfiability Let ν be a truth valuation on language L. ν is a model of a proposition P (set of propositions Γ ) iff ν satisfies P ( Γ ). P ( Γ ) is satisfiable if there is some (at least one) truth valuation ν such that ν ⊨ P ( ν ⊨ Γ ). 24 INTRODUCTION :: SYNTAX :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING SERVICES :: NORMAL FORMS
25
Truth and Validity Let ν be a truth valuation on language L. P is true under ν if ν ⊨ P P is valid if ν ⊨ P for all ν (notation: ⊨ P) P is called a tautology 25 INTRODUCTION :: SYNTAX :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING SERVICES :: NORMAL FORMS
26
Example 26 L = {MonkeyLow, BananaHigh, MonkeyClimbBox, MonkeyGetBanana, , , } Informal Semantics: “If the monkey is low and the banana is high in position, then the monkey cannot get the banana. “ Formal Semantics: ν (MonkeyLow) = T ν (BananaHigh) = T ν (MonkeyClimbBox) = F ν (MonkeyGetBanana) = F MODEL ν ⊨ MonkeyLow and ν ⊨ BananaHigh [SATISFIABLE] ν ⊨ MonkeyClimbBox and ν ⊨ MonkeyGetBanana [SATISFIABLE] MonkeyLow MonkeyLow is a tautology [VALID] INTRODUCTION :: SYNTAX :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING SERVICES :: NORMAL FORMS
27
Entailment Propositional entailment ⊨ ψ where = { θ 1,..., θ n } is a finite set of propositions ν ⊨ θ i for all θ i in implies ν ⊨ ψ 27 INTRODUCTION :: SYNTAX :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING SERVICES :: NORMAL FORMS
28
Example 28 L = {MonkeyLow, BananaHigh, MonkeyClimbBox, MonkeyGetBanana, , , } Informal Semantics: “If the monkey is low and the banana is high in position, then the monkey cannot get the banana. “ Formal Semantics: ν (MonkeyLow) = T ν (BananaHigh) = T ν (MonkeyClimbBox) = F ν (MonkeyGetBanana) = F MODEL = {MonkeyLow, BananaHigh} ν ⊨ MonkeyLow and ν ⊨ BananaHigh implies ν ⊨ MonkeyGetBanana therefore ⊨ MonkeyGetBanana [ENTAILMENT] INTRODUCTION :: SYNTAX :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING SERVICES :: NORMAL FORMS
29
Entailment Difference in notation ⊨ ψ iff ⊨ ψ Left side means we have already filtered out all the models that do not satisfy Right side means that we start from all models. In any case the final result is the same. 29 INTRODUCTION :: SYNTAX :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING SERVICES :: NORMAL FORMS
30
Implication: Premise (I) Propositional entailment in the finite, i.e. ⊨ ψ where = { θ 1,..., θ n } is a finite set of propositions How to embed such a notion directly in the language? As we will see, this would allow us to use truth tables and directly reformulate entailment in terms of the other reasoning services 30 INTRODUCTION :: SYNTAX :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING SERVICES :: NORMAL FORMS
31
Implication: Premise (II) Entailment can be viewed as the logical implication ( θ 1 ∧ θ 2 ∧... ∧ θ n ) → ψ to be read θ 1 ∧ θ 2 ∧... ∧ θ n logically implies ψ → is a new symbol that we add to the language 31 INTRODUCTION :: SYNTAX :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING SERVICES :: NORMAL FORMS
32
We extend our alphabet of symbols with the following defined logical constants: → (implication) ↔ (double implication or equivalence) ::= A | B |... | P | Q |... | ⊥ | ⊤ ::= | ¬ | ∧ | ∨ | → | ↔ (new rules) The operator precedence is (from higher to lower): ¬, ∧, ∨, →, ↔ Let propositions ψ, θ, and finite set { θ 1,..., θ n } of propositions be given. We define: ⊨ θ → ψ iff θ ⊨ ψ ⊨ ( θ 1 ∧... ∧ θ n ) → ψ iff { θ 1,..., θ n } ⊨ ψ ⊨ θ ↔ ψ iff θ → ψ and ψ → θ Implication and equivalence 32 INTRODUCTION :: SYNTAX :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING SERVICES :: NORMAL FORMS
33
Truth Table of → By defining the semantics of → in terms of ⊨ we have the following truth-table for the logical implication P → Q: REMEMBER: Given ν, P ⊨ Q iff ν ⊨ P then ν ⊨ Q. 33 INTRODUCTION :: SYNTAX :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING SERVICES :: NORMAL FORMS
34
Three Properties of Logical Implication Property 1: For all ψ and θ : ψ → θ iff ¬ ψ ∨ θ Property 2: For all ψ : ¬ ψ iff ψ → ⊥ Property 3: For all ψ : ⊥ ⊨ ψ (inconsistent theories imply any proposition) 34 INTRODUCTION :: SYNTAX :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING SERVICES :: NORMAL FORMS
35
Examples (tautologies) Laws for ∧, ¬ and → : (A ∧ ¬B) → ¬(A → B) ¬(A → B) → (A ∧ ¬B) Pierce’s law: ((A → B) → A) → A De Morgan’s laws: ¬(A ∨ B) → (¬A ∧ ¬B) (¬A ∧ ¬B) → ¬(A ∨ B) ¬(A ∧ B) → (¬A ∨ ¬B) (¬A ∨ ¬B) → ¬(A ∧ B) 35 INTRODUCTION :: SYNTAX :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING SERVICES :: NORMAL FORMS
36
Exercise (tautologies) Prove the following double implications (i.e., logical equivalences) by using truth tables. 36 (α ∧ β) ↔ (β ∧ α) Commutativity of ∧ (α ∨ β) ↔ (β ∨ α) Commutativity of ∨ ((α ∧ β) ∧ γ) ↔ (α ∧ (β ∧ γ)) Associativity of ∧ ((α ∨ β) ∨ γ) ↔ (α ∨ (β ∨ γ)): Associativity of ∨ ¬(¬α) ↔ α Double-negation elimination (α →β) ↔ (¬β →¬α) Contraposition INTRODUCTION :: SYNTAX :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING SERVICES :: NORMAL FORMS
37
Exercise (tautologies) Prove the following double implications (i.e., logical equivalences) by using truth tables. 37 (α → β) ↔ (¬α ∨ β) → -elimination (α ↔ β) ↔ ((α → β) ∧ (β → α)) ↔ -elimination ¬(α ∧ β) ↔ (¬α ∨ ¬β) DeMorgan Law for ∧ ¬(α ∨ β) ↔ (¬α ∧ ¬β) DeMorgan Law for ∨ (α ∧ (β ∨ γ)) ↔ ((α ∧ β) ∨ (α ∧ γ)) Distributivity of ∧ over ∨ (α ∨ (β ∧ γ)) ↔ ((α ∨ β) ∧ (α ∨ γ)) Distributivity of ∨ over ∧ INTRODUCTION :: SYNTAX :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING SERVICES :: NORMAL FORMS
38
Reasoning Services The basic reasoning tasks (or “services”) we can represent (and compute) using ⊨ are: Model Checking (EVAL) Satisfiability (SAT) Unsatisfiability (UnSAT) Validity (VAL) Entailment (ENT) 38 INTRODUCTION :: SYNTAX :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING SERVICES :: NORMAL FORMS
39
Reasoning Services: EVAL Model Checking (EVAL) Is a proposition P true under a truth-valuation ν ? Check ν ⊨ P EVAL P, ν Yes No Does ν ⊨ MonkeyLow MonkeyGetBanana ? INTRODUCTION :: SYNTAX :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING SERVICES :: NORMAL FORMS 39
40
Reasoning Services: SAT Satisfiability (SAT) Is there a truth-valuation ν where P is true? find ν such that ν ⊨ P SAT P ν No Find a ν that ν ⊨ MonkeyLow GetBanana For instance, the truth-valuation ν where both are true INTRODUCTION :: SYNTAX :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING SERVICES :: NORMAL FORMS 40
41
Reasoning Services (unSAT) Unsatisfiability is the impossibility to find a truth-valuation ν 41 Monkey is satisfiable. Monkey ∨ ¬ Monkey is satisfiable. Monkey ∧ ¬ Monkey is unsatisfiable (inconsistent). In fact, for every truth-valuation ν, either ν (A) = T, so ν (¬A) = F, hence ν (P) = F; or ν (A) = F, so ν (¬A) = T, hence ν (P) = T. INTRODUCTION :: SYNTAX :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING SERVICES :: NORMAL FORMS
42
Reasoning Services: VAL Validity (VAL) Is P true according to all possible truth-valuation ν ? Check whether for all ν, ν ⊨ P VAL P Yes No Is P = MonkeyLow ∨ MonkeyLow valid? Yes! INTRODUCTION :: SYNTAX :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING SERVICES :: NORMAL FORMS 42
43
Reasoning Services (Entailment) A set Γ (eventually empty) of propositions θ entails a proposition ψ, written: Γ ⊨ ψ if ν ⊨ θ for all θ ∈ Γ, then ν ⊨ ψ (for a given ν or for all ν) If Γ ⊨ ψ, then we say that ψ is a logical consequence of Γ, and that Γ logically implies ψ. NOTE: ⊨ P is the same as {} ⊨ P 43 INTRODUCTION :: SYNTAX :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING SERVICES :: NORMAL FORMS
44
Reasoning Services: ENT Entailment (ENT) All θ ∈ Γ true in ν (in all ν ) implies ψ true in ν (in all ν ) check Γ ⊨ ψ in ν (in all ν ) by checking that: given that ν ⊨ θ for all θ ∈ Γ implies ν ⊨ ψ ENT Γ, ψ, ν Yes No Does MonkeyLow ⊨ MonkeyGetBanana ? No! Does MonkeyLow BananaHigh ⊨ MonkeyGetBanana? Yes! INTRODUCTION :: SYNTAX :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING SERVICES :: NORMAL FORMS 44
45
Reasoning Services (Entailment) Exercises: Demonstrate that {today} ⊨ today ∨ tomorrow Demonstrate that {today} ⊭ tomorrow Suppose P = today ∨ tomorrow. Then: Define Γ such that Γ ⊨ P Define Γ such that Γ ⊭ P 45 INTRODUCTION :: SYNTAX :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING SERVICES :: NORMAL FORMS
46
Reasoning Services: properties (I) EVAL is the easiest task. We just test one assignment. SAT is NP complete. We need to test in the worst case all the assignments. We stop when we find one which is true. UnSAT is CO-NP. We need to test in the worst case all the assignments. We stop when we find one which is true. VAL is CO-NP. We need to test all the assignments and verify that they are all true. We stop when we find one which is false. ENT is CO-NP. It can be computed using VAL (see next slide) 46 INTRODUCTION :: SYNTAX :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING SERVICES :: NORMAL FORMS
47
Reasoning Services: properties (II) VAL( ψ ) iff UnSAT( ψ ) SAT( ψ ) VAL( ψ ) iff SAT( ψ ) VAL( ψ ) ⊨ ψ, where = { θ 1, …, θ n } iff VAL( θ 1 … θ n ψ ) 47 ψ = (A A) is valid, while ( A A) is unsatisfiable ψ = A is satisfiable in all models where ν(A) = T. Informally, the left side says that there is at least an assignment which makes A true and there is at least an assignment which makes A false; the right side says that there is at least an assignment which makes A true (in other words it makes A false) and there is at least an assignment which makes A false (in other words it makes A true). This means that not all assignments make A true (false). Take A ⊨ A B. the formula (A A B) is valid. INTRODUCTION :: SYNTAX :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING SERVICES :: NORMAL FORMS
48
Reasoning Services: properties (III) EVAL is easy. ENT can be computed using VAL VAL can be computed using UnSAT UnSAT is the opposite of SAT All reasoning tasks can be reduced to SAT!!! SAT is the most important reasoning service. 48 INTRODUCTION :: SYNTAX :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING SERVICES :: NORMAL FORMS
49
Normal Forms: Literals A literal is either an atomic proposition or the negation of an atomic proposition, i.e., for all propositional variables P P and ¬P are literals. P is a positive literal ¬P is a negative literal 49 Monkey HighBanana ¬GetBanana ¬ClimbBox INTRODUCTION :: SYNTAX :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING SERVICES :: NORMAL FORMS
50
Normal Forms: Clauses A (disjunctive) clause is a disjunction of literals α 1 … α n A unit clause is a clause that contains only a single literal An empty clause does not contain literals 50 B ∨ ¬C ∨ ¬DMonkey ∨ ¬Monkey B and ¬C are unit clausesB ∨ ¬C is not INTRODUCTION :: SYNTAX :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING SERVICES :: NORMAL FORMS
51
Conjunctive Normal Form (CNF) A proposition is in conjunctive normal form (CNF) if it is a (finite) conjunction of (disjunctive) clauses 51 Examples of formulas in CNF: ¬A ∧ B (A ∨ ¬B) ∧ (B ∨ ¬C ∨ ¬D) A ∧ (B ∨ C ∨ ¬D) A B (¬ A C) (B ¬ D E) Examples of formulas NOT in CNF: ¬(A ∧ B)¬ is the outmost operator A ∧ (B ∨ C ∧ ¬D) ∧ is nested within ∨ INTRODUCTION :: SYNTAX :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING SERVICES :: NORMAL FORMS
52
Conversion of a formula to CNF Theorem (e.g. Mendelson, 1987 [Prop. 1.4, Ex. 1.41(a)]) Every formula P has an equivalent CNF, namely P can be converted (in polynomial time) into a proposition Q such that: Q is in CNF P and Q are equivalent (i.e., have the same truth table) A conversion to a CNF that operates as in the theorem above is said to be complete The algorithm implementing the conversion to a CNF is based on the tautologies about logical equivalence (or double implication): Double-negation law (i.e. elimination of ¬¬) De Morgan’s laws Distributive laws Elimination of → and 52 INTRODUCTION :: SYNTAX :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING SERVICES :: NORMAL FORMS
53
Conversion to CNF: Basic Tautologies 53 ( α → β ) ↔ (¬ α ∨ β )c → -elimination ( α ↔ β ) ↔ (( α → β ) ∧ ( β → α )) ↔ -elimination ¬( α ∧ β ) ↔ (¬ α ∨ ¬ β ) DeMorgan Law for ∧ ¬( α ∨ β ) ↔ (¬ α ∧ ¬ β ) DeMorgan Law for ∨ ( α ∧ ( β ∨ γ )) ↔ (( α ∧ β ) ∨ ( α ∧ γ )) Distributivity of ∧ over ∨ ( α ∨ ( β ∧ γ )) ↔ (( α ∨ β ) ∧ ( α ∨ γ )) Distributivity of ∨ over ∧ ¬(¬ α ) ↔ α Double-negation elimination INTRODUCTION :: SYNTAX :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING SERVICES :: NORMAL FORMS
54
Example: Conversion to CNF of A ↔ (B ∨ C) 1. Eliminate ↔ : (A → (B ∨ C)) ∧ ((B ∨ C) → A) 2. Eliminate → : (¬A ∨ B ∨ C) ∧ (¬(B ∨ C) ∨ A) 3. Move ¬ inwards using de Morgan’s laws: (¬A ∨ B ∨ C) ∧ ((¬B ∧ ¬C) ∨ A) 4. Apply distributivity of ∨ over ∧ and flatten: (¬A ∨ B ∨ C) ∧ (¬B ∨ A) ∧ (¬C ∨ A) (*) (*) in CNF and equivalent to ‘A ↔ (B ∨ C)’. 54 INTRODUCTION :: SYNTAX :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING SERVICES :: NORMAL FORMS
55
Normal Forms: Conjunctive clauses A conjunctive clause is a conjunction of literals α 1 … α n NOTE: a conjunctive clause IS NOT a clause! 55 B ¬C ¬DMonkey ¬Monkey INTRODUCTION :: SYNTAX :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING SERVICES :: NORMAL FORMS
56
Disjunctive Normal Form (DNF) A proposition is in disjunctive normal form (DNF) if it is a (finite) disjunction of conjunctive clauses 56 Examples of formulas in DNF: ¬A ∨ B (A ∧ ¬B) ∨ (B ∧ ¬C ∧ ¬D) A ∨ (B ∧ C ∧ ¬D) A ∨ B ∨ (¬ A ∧ C) ∨ (B ∧ ¬ D ∧ E) Examples of formulas NOT in DNF: ¬(A ∨ B)¬ is the outmost operator A ∨ (B ∨ C ∧ ¬D) ∧ is nested within ∨ INTRODUCTION :: SYNTAX :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING SERVICES :: NORMAL FORMS
57
Horn clauses A Horn clause is a (disjunctive) clause with at most one positive literal. NOTE: ¬ A ¬ B D is equivalent to A B D 57 ¬ A A ¬ B ¬ D ¬ A B ¬ D INTRODUCTION :: SYNTAX :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING SERVICES :: NORMAL FORMS
Similar presentations
© 2025 SlidePlayer.com. Inc.
All rights reserved.