Presentation is loading. Please wait.

Presentation is loading. Please wait.

Anselm’s “1st” ontological argument Something than which nothing greater can be thought of cannot exist only as an idea in the mind because, in addition.

Similar presentations


Presentation on theme: "Anselm’s “1st” ontological argument Something than which nothing greater can be thought of cannot exist only as an idea in the mind because, in addition."— Presentation transcript:

1 Anselm’s “1st” ontological argument Something than which nothing greater can be thought of cannot exist only as an idea in the mind because, in addition to existing as an idea in the mind, it can also be thought of as existing in reality, that is, objectively, which is greater than existing only as an idea in the mind. If something than which nothing greater can be thought of exists only as an idea in the mind, then “that than which something greater cannot be thought of” is “that than which something greater can be thought of,” which is impossible because it is self-contradictory. Something than which nothing greater can be thought of must exist, not only as an idea in the mind, but in reality. 1. 2. 3.

2 In other words, A God that actually exists is greater than a “God” that exists only as an idea in the mind. If “God” exists only as an idea in the mind, then “God” is “not- God” (because something that exists only as an idea in the mind is not “something than which nothing greater can be thought of”). Thus, the claim that God does not actually exist implies a contradiction and is therefore necessarily false. If the claim that God does not actually exist is necessarily false, then the claim that God actually exists is necessarily true (because the negation of a contradiction is a tautology). 1 2 3 4

3 Anselm’s “2nd” Ontological Argument It is possible to think of something that cannot be thought not to exist [that is, a necessary being]. A necessary being [something that cannot be thought not to exist] would be greater than something that can be thought not to exist [that is, a contingent being]. If something than which nothing greater can be thought of could be thought of as not existing, then something than which nothing greater can be thought of would not be something than which nothing greater can be thought of, which is an outright contradiction and thus absurd. Something than which nothing greater can be thought of has such a high degree of existence, that is, necessary existence, that it cannot be thought of as not existing, that is, its nonexistence is impossible. 1. 2. 3. 4.

4 In other words, n It is possible to think of a necessary being, i.e., a being whose nonexistence is impossible. n Necessary existence is greater than contingent existence, and a necessary being is greater than a contingent being. n If the nonexistence of God is possible, then God must be a contingent being. But then “God” would be “not-God” because a contingent being cannot be “something than which nothing greater can be thought of.” n Thus, the claim that God’s nonexistence is possible implies a contradiction and is therefore necessarily false. n If the claim that God’s nonexistence is possible is necessarily false, then the claim that God’s nonexistence is impossible is necessarily true (because the negation of a contradiction is a tautology).

5 MORE THAN 150 YEARS LATER…

6 Aquinas’ Proofs The five ways

7 Thomas Aquinas (1225-1274) Joined Dominican order against the wishes of his family; led peripatetic existence thereafter. Considered the most learned man of his day; much in demand as teacher and lecturer. Summa Theologica never finished, following ‘ecstasy’ in Dec. 1273 Doctor of the Church

8 Aquinas on God’s existence Believed, as against several interesting objections, that God’s existence can (and needs to be) ‘demonstrated’ (‘proved’, in the modern sense). Believed, as against several interesting objections, that God’s existence can (and needs to be) ‘demonstrated’ (‘proved’, in the modern sense). By this he meant 2 things: By this he meant 2 things: 1. That God exists is not ‘self-evident’ or axiomatic or a matter of definition 2. That God exists is something which we can be completely sure of, as a matter of reason (and not simply of faith)

9 Is the existence of God self-evident? “self-evident” = that which requires no proof in order to be known. “self-evident” = that which requires no proof in order to be known. 3 objections: the existence of God is self- evident because: 3 objections: the existence of God is self- evident because: I. Knowledge of God is innate II. The concept includes existence III. God is truth, & no one can consistently deny the existence of truth.

10 Answers to the objections Objection 1: we know only in a vague way (“God is man’s beatitude”) that God exists, and this is quite different from knowing absolutely that He exists. Objection 1: we know only in a vague way (“God is man’s beatitude”) that God exists, and this is quite different from knowing absolutely that He exists. Obj.2: distinction between mental and real existence maintained even in the case of “that than which no greater can be thought” Obj.2: distinction between mental and real existence maintained even in the case of “that than which no greater can be thought” Obj.3: “The existence of truth in general is self-evident but the existence of a Primal Truth is not self-evident to us.” Obj.3: “The existence of truth in general is self-evident but the existence of a Primal Truth is not self-evident to us.” General rejoinder: what is self-evident cannot be denied, but “God is” can be denied. General rejoinder: what is self-evident cannot be denied, but “God is” can be denied. Therefore, “God is” is not self-evident (that is, his existence requires proof)

11 Objections to the idea that God’s existence can be proven Objection 1: God’s existence is a matter of faith, not demonstration (reason) Objection 1: God’s existence is a matter of faith, not demonstration (reason) Obj. 2: God, by definition, exceeds our understanding, therefore we can’t even know what it is we’re trying to prove the existence of (“the essence is the middle term of demonstration”) Obj. 2: God, by definition, exceeds our understanding, therefore we can’t even know what it is we’re trying to prove the existence of (“the essence is the middle term of demonstration”) Obj.3: We can’t know God directly, only by his effects; but His effects (as finite objects or events) can’t tell us anything about His nature (which is, by dfn., infinite). Therefore, we can’t prove anything about Him. Obj.3: We can’t know God directly, only by his effects; but His effects (as finite objects or events) can’t tell us anything about His nature (which is, by dfn., infinite). Therefore, we can’t prove anything about Him.

12 Replies to the objections Objection 1: Anything which can be known by “natural reason” is not an article of faith -- something is an article of faith only if it cannot be known by other means Objection 1: Anything which can be known by “natural reason” is not an article of faith -- something is an article of faith only if it cannot be known by other means Obj.2: We don’t need to know what it is that we’re proving the existence of (that is, it’s essence), only that it exists Obj.2: We don’t need to know what it is that we’re proving the existence of (that is, it’s essence), only that it exists Obj.3: As in 2, we’re only trying to prove that He exists and not anything about His nature. Every effect indicates, at the very least, the existence of its cause. Obj.3: As in 2, we’re only trying to prove that He exists and not anything about His nature. Every effect indicates, at the very least, the existence of its cause. General rejoinder: 2 ways of proving things: a priori and a posteriori; God’s existence can only be proven in the latter way

13 Character of Aquinas’ proofs Aquinas distinguishes a priori (from cause to effect; from the nature of something to its consequences) from a posteriori (from effect to cause; from observable consequences to the nature of what causes those) proofs -- the first are deductive proofs, what are the second kind? Are they proofs at all? (recall our previous discussion of “proof”?) Aquinas distinguishes a priori (from cause to effect; from the nature of something to its consequences) from a posteriori (from effect to cause; from observable consequences to the nature of what causes those) proofs -- the first are deductive proofs, what are the second kind? Are they proofs at all? (recall our previous discussion of “proof”?)

14 Proof 1: argument from motion “motion” Aquinas understands to be a paradigm case of change; the argument here is better thought of as the argument from change “motion” Aquinas understands to be a paradigm case of change; the argument here is better thought of as the argument from change Change = going from potential to actual Change = going from potential to actual Every such ‘move’ requires something which is itself actual to begin with Every such ‘move’ requires something which is itself actual to begin with A chain of such ‘moves’ cannot be infinitely long A chain of such ‘moves’ cannot be infinitely long Therefore, there must be a ‘first mover’ (a first initiator of change), which is not itself moved; this first mover is God. Therefore, there must be a ‘first mover’ (a first initiator of change), which is not itself moved; this first mover is God.

15 Proof 2: argument from efficient cause Aquinas, following Aristotle, recognizes four kinds of ‘causes’ (4 kinds of ‘why’): formal, material, final, and efficient causes Aquinas, following Aristotle, recognizes four kinds of ‘causes’ (4 kinds of ‘why’): formal, material, final, and efficient causes Nothing is the efficient cause of itself; therefore, for every effect there must exist some efficient cause distinct from the effect Nothing is the efficient cause of itself; therefore, for every effect there must exist some efficient cause distinct from the effect Such a chain of causes cannot go on to infinity; therefore there is a first cause (and that is God) Such a chain of causes cannot go on to infinity; therefore there is a first cause (and that is God)

16 Proof 3: argument from possibility Everything which exists, exists only contingently (that is, it is possible that it could not exist) Everything which exists, exists only contingently (that is, it is possible that it could not exist) Any contingent being must have, at some time, not existed (if it is possible that it not exist at this time, then necessarily it did not exist at some time) Any contingent being must have, at some time, not existed (if it is possible that it not exist at this time, then necessarily it did not exist at some time) The world, taken as a whole & as contingent, must have at some time therefore not existed The world, taken as a whole & as contingent, must have at some time therefore not existed But what once did not exist must come to exist in virtue of something which itself must exist. But what once did not exist must come to exist in virtue of something which itself must exist. That necessary being is God. That necessary being is God.

17 Proof 4: argument from gradation Every quality or attribute which can be thought of in terms of degree, is referenced to some standard (more or less good to some standard of goodness, more or less red to some standard of redness, etc.) Every quality or attribute which can be thought of in terms of degree, is referenced to some standard (more or less good to some standard of goodness, more or less red to some standard of redness, etc.) Since being admits of degrees (as does goodness & every other sort of perfection), there must be something which is the standard for that attribute (a formal cause of that attribute) Since being admits of degrees (as does goodness & every other sort of perfection), there must be something which is the standard for that attribute (a formal cause of that attribute) That standard is God That standard is God

18 Proof 5: argument from design Natural kinds and events are only understood properly as having an end state or aim Natural kinds and events are only understood properly as having an end state or aim Such non-intelligent things can act towards such ends only by being directed by something which is intelligent (something which could have motives or purposes) Such non-intelligent things can act towards such ends only by being directed by something which is intelligent (something which could have motives or purposes) Therefore there is an intelligent being which directs natural kinds and events; and that being is God. Therefore there is an intelligent being which directs natural kinds and events; and that being is God.

19 Character of Aquinas’ God What is the nature of the God which is revealed by “the five ways”? What is the nature of the God which is revealed by “the five ways”? the initiator of all motion (change) the ultimate cause of all things a necessary being the standard against which all things are measured a surpassingly complex intelligence


Download ppt "Anselm’s “1st” ontological argument Something than which nothing greater can be thought of cannot exist only as an idea in the mind because, in addition."

Similar presentations


Ads by Google